This debate took place
on Los Angeles radio station KKLA FM 99.5. I remember speaking with Bahnsen by phone sometime in 1991 about the debate, which had been
broadcast fairly recently, but I cannot be more specific about the date
(and would be grateful to anyone who would be good enough to provide
this information).
We have the following
transcription thanks to efforts of someone whose screen name is “Jonah”
and who posted it on January 7, 2011
here [link is dead]
“for whoever wants it.” I
hope “Jonah” doesn’t mind the use I’ve made of it. I made some stylistic changes, mostly in punctuation. To conserve
space, I have deleted the repeated introductions and other announcements
that radio host and debate moderator John Stewart made during the
program.
I did not check the
transcription against the audio, but as someone who has listened to it
several times over the past twenty years, I can vouch for its fidelity. No one has to take my word for it, however: the audio of the radio
broadcast is available on
YouTube. My internal critique of Smith’s worldview
is advertised in the left column. Its approach was inspired by what I had then understood of Bahnsen's
apologetic method.
Anthony Flood
January 13, 2013
Updated June 4, 2010
A Debate on the Existence of God
Greg Bahnsen vs. George Smith
Moderator:
God. Well, the Bible begins with—“In
the beginning God!” And the Bible says twice in the Psalms, “The fool
has said in his heart there is no God!”
But why are there so many agnostics and atheists if God’s existence is
so evident? There may be many explanations, but there are certain
arguments consistently raised by skeptics which call into question God’s
existence. Coming up we’ll discuss atheism and the case against God
with atheist George Smith and Christian apologist Greg Bahnsen. My
guest, George Smith, has written two books. One is entitled Atheism:
The Case Against God, the other: Atheism, Ayn Rand, and Other
Heresies, and George first published Atheism: The Case Against
God in 1974. The book is still in print published by . . .
Prometheus. And then for six years he was a general editor and
scriptwriter for the Audio Classics audio tapes by Knowledge Products,
currently senior research fellow for the Institute for Human Studies at
George Mason University, and again his latest book Atheism, Ayn Rand,
and Other Heresies. George Smith, we welcome you to the program.
Smith:
Thank you.
Moderator:
Let me get you to get a little
closer to the mic there, George.
Moderator:
Also, we have Dr. Greg Bahnsen, presently scholar in resident at the
Southern California Center for Christian Studies, an author of five
books and nearly a hundred journal or periodical articles in Christian
apologetics, ethics, and theology. His doctorate is in philosophy, the
area of knowledge or epistemology from the University of Southern
California, and he has degrees from Westminster Theological Seminary;
and Dr. Greg Bahnsen, we welcome you as well.
Bahnsen:
Thanks, John, good to be here.
Moderator:
Well, let’s start with George
Smith—the status quo is [the] existence of God. Most people would
believe in that so since you are sort of opting to challenge the status
quo, let’s start with your background, George, in the case against God,
give us your background. Why don’t you believe there is a God?
Smith:
Well, first of all, let’s be clear
about what the definition of atheism is as used by most atheists.
Atheism is definitely the absence or lack of belief in a god, so after
the question: Do you believe in a god? To answer “No” is to make you an
atheist. I don’t believe in God primarily because I don’t see any good
reason why I should. In other words, the burden of proof in my mind
clearly falls on the theist or the God-believer first to define what
he’s talking about when he’s using the term “God,” and secondly, then,
to provide arguments or proof of some kind that such a being exists.
Moderator:
And what type of proof are we
talking about, apodictic certainty? Are you talking about the
preponderance of evidence? What would you accept as sufficient proof to
have you change your point of view?
Smith:
Well, it depends on the kind of
being that is defined, I mean, it seems to me we require stronger
evidence of proof of certain things than we do others, especially when
something is so out of our context of ordinary experience. For example,
it seems to me that if someone claims to have seen a man rise from the
dead, we’re going to require a fairly strong degree of proof to accept
that assertion. I think the problem though, with theists as I have
encountered them, is not in the area of proof, it’s that they stumble at
the first requirement which is providing some kind of coherent
description if not a definition of what kind of being they have in mind
when they describe God, a description that’s not utterly unintelligible
or at least that’s not contradictory. And that’s the problem I have and
in many cases when I ask what do you mean by God? I don’t get any
answer that makes much sense to me. They might as well say, “I believe
in a blark!” It’s a nonsense word in that sense in my mind.
Moderator:
George, when we talk about your
working definition that you don’t see any evidence for God or sufficient
evidence for God—I mean, there are shades of definitions here of
agnostic and atheist, so you see loosely the term “atheist” to describe
those that have never seen enough evidence for God.
Smith:
We simply do not believe in a god,
and I admittedly, since I’m using the term “god” I should provide at
least a rough estimate of what I mean when I use the term. A god for
me, generally speaking, has to be some kind of supernatural, or if you
like, transcendent being. In my mind, I reject any naturalistic concept
of God. In other words, if somebody says to me, “I believe that nature
is God,” I say, “Fine, but why call it God why not just call it nature?”
So at least the minimum requirement has to be that it’s some kind of
being that transcends or falls outside the natural context of nature,
falls outside natural law [unintelligible] that can perform miracles, do
things that natural creatures cannot.
Moderator:
But apparently by your presence here
you’re open to discuss it and if enough evidence were induced, you would
be willing to modify your perspective.
Smith:
Yeah, and I’ve been asked before the
question what it would take to convince me. Well, not to be too
flippant about it, but I suppose if in a Monty Python-like manner the
clouds were to open and a giant hand were to come down from the clouds
and grab me by the scruff of the neck and shake me and say, “I’m here,
I’m here!”
Moderator:
That would do it for most people.
Smith:
Yeah, that would get me thinking.
Moderator:
And the reason I ask these is to try
for my own understanding [to] determine whether you would fall into the
category of what I would call a soft-boiled or a hard-boiled agnostic or
somebody that is at least open to discuss it or if you’ve totally ruled
out any possibility of God’s existence.
Smith:
Well, again until someone tells me
what they mean by God, I can’t answer that question. Do I rule out the
possibility of life on other planets? I don’t know. It depends on the
arguments. So in essence, I guess I’m open in principle. It’s just
that I’ve heard—I’ve been an atheist for many years now and involved
myself in a lot of debates—and I think I’ve heard most of the arguments
I’m going to hear, so somebody is going to have to come up with
something new to convince me.
Moderator:
And just one more point before I
bring Greg Bahnsen into this, but in terms of background and I don’t
mean to get ad hominem, but did you have any type of religious
training or academic training?
Smith:
I was—would consider myself a
fundamentalist Christian until about sophomore in high school. I was
devoutly religious. I had many what I call religious experiences. My
family was not especially religious, but I was. I prayed, I worked in
church services; I got my [unintelligible] badge in Boy Scouts. I was a
model Christian child, I [unintelligible]. And, things happen. I
discussed that in my latest book. There’s an essay called “My Path to
Atheism” where I go through the de-conversion process, as I call it.
Moderator:
And when you say you were religious
did you consider a personal relationship with Jesus Christ part of what
you had?
Smith:
Yes, yes I think so.
Moderator: Because some people would make a
differentiation between a religion and a relation-ship.
Smith:
Well, I was raised on Air Forces
bases. The churches were technically non-denominational, but my
experience was—I can’t say it was Baptist or any other particular
theology—but I considered myself a Fundamentalist. I accepted what I
considered to be a literal belief in the Bible, etc.
Moderator:
Dr. Greg Bahnsen, in your doctorate
from USC in epistemology and as a Christian theologian, of course, you
have done many debates and written in the area of God’s existence. Where
does one begin in presenting evidence for God? How would you approach
George Smith for example?
Bahnsen:
Well, [what] I appreciate about
George—I really met him this afternoon—I appreciate about his writings
that he understands how important epistemology is to the whole
discussion. If we’re going to talk about the existence of God, we’re
not going to want to reduce it to the question of emotion or just
volitional commitment of some sort without man’s intellect being
engaged, and I think he’s right about that. As Christians, we do not
give up our intellect when we believe in God or follow the Scriptures,
and so since the issue is epistemology, this may not be what your
hearers would like to get into perhaps, but we need to talk about what
amounts to proof and what amounts to knowledge and how these things are
possible. And I would say that we have to be extremely critical. I
know that Christians often have the reputation for not being critically
minded, and I think that’s probably a failing on our part when we’re
like that.
But if we’re going to be critically
minded, we need to examine the presuppositions of our thinking and we
have to look at the worldview that we’re espousing when we argue in a
particular way or not. And so, if I were talking with George over
coffee, I think I would probably talk to him first of all about what
outlook he has on the world. What does he conceive reality to be? How
does he know what he knows? How should he live his life? And I would
compare that to the Christian worldview, what we understand to be
reality and how we know what we know and how we should live our lives,
and then of course, we’re going to have to eventually get to the point
of understanding how does one choose one worldview over another. At
some point, maybe after two or three cups of coffee, I would eventually
challenge George that on an atheist worldview, the presuppositions of
atheism do not provide a foundation for proving anything whatsoever.
And therefore, in one sense, the strongest evidence and argument for
the existence of God is that without a belief in God you can’t prove
anything. And so I would make that the foundation for reason.
Often, and I think you’ll see this
if you read George’s book, you have people who present something of a
Thomistic approach to faith and reason where faith fills in the gaps
where reason lets us down or is inadequate. My own theological
perspective is more Augustinian rather than Thomistic, and I would argue
instead that every-thing we do engages the reason as a tool of man’s
intellect, but that the cogent use of reason is impossible apart from a
foundation of faith. And you see, I would preach that to my Christian
brothers and sisters. They need to read the Scriptures and use their
minds and not simply have an emotional Christianity. But that would
also be the premise that I would approach an atheist or unbeliever with.
I’d say that the best use of reason, in fact the only use of reason
comes about when Christian faith is the foundation for it, or the
worldview in terms of which you use your reason.
Moderator:
But Greg, you wouldn’t defer to
faith as being some mystical faculty or credulity. You’re talking about
a belief based upon evidence, then.
Bahnsen:
Yes, there have been plenty of
Christians throughout history that have taken that mystical approach to
faith. They’ve defined it as a second approach to knowledge apart from
man’s reason and so forth, but I think those are misguided. I would say
that faith is essentially belief, and the reason we talk about faith and
reason is because when we have faith it means we are trusting somebody
else’s expertise in some area. In that sense, the student at the
university who first hears lectures about U.S. history or about logic,
or what have you, begins to learn about these fields because he or she
has faith in the instructors that they’re giving them the straight
scoop, and that sort of thing. Christians have faith in another
person—I mean, not apart from that, but in addition—we have faith in the
person of God himself revealed in the Scriptures. But I wouldn’t say
that that faith is apart from reason, I would say that engages the
faculty of reason and it is in fact the foundation for the use of
reason.
Moderator:
So would proper reasoning lead you
to believe in the existence of God?
Bahnsen:
I would argue that there isn’t any
proper reasoning apart from the foundation of belief in God. It’s not
so much that it leads to belief in God, as belief in God is the
necessary pre-condition for using man’s reason at all.
Moderator:
Okay, George Smith, it sounds like
there needs to be sort of a priori understanding here to arrive
at the proper conclusions. How does that fit into your thinking?
Smith:
Well, there were several issues that
were raised. I don’t really understand exactly what Greg means when he
talks about belief in God as a pre-condition for reason. He might mean
that to prove the validity of reason, but he just said in order to even
reason, you can’t even do that without a belief in God. I don’t believe
in a God, and yet I presumably reason; maybe not to everyone’s
satisfaction, but I nonetheless do reason. As far as this idea of faith
and trust in another, you know, there’s nothing wrong with that use of
faith. It’s been used that way for centuries, but if I take the word of
someone else that I have not personally witnessed, I’m having faith in
it. But that kind of faith presupposes that you think the authority
can’t himself prove what he believes in. In other words, I may have
“faith” in a physicist about some scientific experiment he’s done. But
that assumes that I believe the physicist himself is not acting from
faith but himself can prove what he says. So in that sense, I would say
faith itself is dependent on the assumption that somebody, somewhere can
prove what they’re talking about.
And I really don’t understand this
idea that reason itself, or to prove the validity of reason we must have
faith. It seems to me we’re talking about two entirely different
things. And it seems to me that reason stands quite well on its own. I
can talk about A is A, that is a self-evident truth. Where’s the faith?
I can talk about the table being in front of me, now if you want to say
I have faith that the table is there, without getting into that sort of
argument, I think that’s absurd. I have direct physical contact with
the table; it’s quite obvious it’s there. We have truths of
mathematics. Where’s the faith there? And you can extend that out and
out. And reason I think—and there are degrees of proof and so forth—but
it seems to me reason’s quite capable of indicating itself.
Moderator:
Well, let’s do this—let’s take a
break. We’ll come back and let Greg Bahnsen respond because I want to
talk about this area of evidence and where does faith fit in and where
does evidence fit in, and what kind of evidence should we look for to
come to the conclusion there is a God or that it’s reasonable to believe
in a supreme being. . . . Greg, let me go back to you and perhaps to
respond to George’s wondering: Does he lack reason because he doesn’t
begin with the premise of accepting God’s existence . . . [?]
Bahnsen:
Yeah, I’m glad that George replied
the way that he did because it allows for a clarification that I think
we often overlook. We take it for granted if we’ve studied philosophy,
but often people don’t see that there’s a difference between talking
about how you account for something and then what you’re able to do,
whether you can account for it or not. I can have tuberculosis and not
be able to give you any idea of the medical facts and dynamics of
tuberculosis, so there’s a difference between doing something and being
able to account for that, or for having something true about you and you
not being able to account for it.
And I wouldn’t suggest for a moment
that George Smith, for instance, doesn’t reason. He does reason. He
attempts to do that, and he attempts to do it consistently and so forth.
But when he says to your audience, “I reason, but I don’t have faith in
God!” My response is, “No, you do have faith in God!” And one
of the problems is—and this is why God would be unhappy with your life,
George—is because you don’t give Him the credit that He deserves, you
don’t glorify Him, because your very ability to reason depends upon your
knowledge of Him and submission to Him.
Now, of course, George doesn’t
outwardly worship God; he doesn’t go to a Christian church; he doesn’t
profess faith in Christ; he doesn’t believe the Bible and all sorts of
things; and I take him very seriously about that. But my challenge to
him as a philosopher and as a fellow human being would be that at a
deeper level, he does know this God that I’m talking about. The
Apostle Paul in Romans 1 describes this as suppressing the truth by
means of unrighteousness, that people can know God and yet they don’t
outwardly profess it, and because they do know God they are able to do
things. They can balance their checkbooks, they can drive a car, they
can make sense out of human relationships and love, and they can reason.
They are able to do that. But now are they able to give an account of
that?
And that’s where we get back to the
whole question of the atheist worldview and the Christian worldview. In
terms of the atheist worldview, I would challenge George that he cannot
give an account of the reasoning that he’s doing. An example that a
seminary professor once used that stuck with me for many years, Dr. Van
Til once said [Bahnsen paraphrases here.—A.F.], “There’s no
question that atheists count. Sometimes they count better than
Christians. They can do their math very well. They do count, but they
cannot account for their counting!” That is, in terms of their outlook
on the world, what they profess to be true about knowledge and about
reality—you know, the universals and absolutes of mathematics—would not
make any sense whatsoever. And so, I do agree that George does reason,
but I would suggest that he cannot, in terms of his worldview, make
sense of the reasoning that he engages in.
Moderator:
Greg, just one clarification on
that. Would that mean that all atheists are somehow unconscious theists?
Bahnsen:
Yes, I may want a more sophisticated
way of describing that than “unconscious,” but that is generally what
I’m suggesting here. It is that in their heart of hearts they do know
God, and they are rebelling against that knowledge by their outward
profession and the way in which they attempt even to put together a
rational worldview or appeal to reason as George very well does. But
you see, on his worldview there is no reason to appeal to.
I was thinking, if you don’t mind
George, my quoting from your book for a moment. I just took one
sentence that I thought would be a good point of departure for a
conversation with you. In the introduction to your Atheism: The Case
against God, you say, “To advocate irrationality is to advocate that
which is destructive to human life.” And you see, I read that sentence
and I say, I agree with that! I think to advocate irrationality is a
bad thing to do, that’s not the way to go. I don’t want Christians to
understand faith in that way, and I agree with you that irrationality is
destructive of human life.
Now here’s the interesting counter
to that: Why in an atheist worldview shouldn’t a person be irrational?
You might say, well, because it’s destructive of human life! But the
next question is, Well, why shouldn’t I be destructive of human life if
I were an atheist? Now, you know why I don’t believe in being
destructive of human life, the question is: why did you put that
in your book? Why does it bother you to be destructive of human life?
Smith:
Well, before I get into that, I’d
like to address a couple other things you said. First of all, there’s a
little bit of conversion by definition going on here. This idea that
atheists are really somehow unconscious crypto-theists has been around a
long time. Walter Kaufmann in a very good book called The Faith of a
Heretic talked about this problem, and pointed out that he was less
than thrilled by the prospect that no matter how much you profess not to
believe something, people say, “Well you know, you really do believe it!
I might just as well say, “I’m sure I could arrive at a theory to
justify it that all Christians are really just atheists underneath and
just don’t realize it, and once they put away their childish things they
will realize they’re atheists,” and so forth. I don’t think that gets
us anywhere. I’m not a crypto-theist, and this business about
justifying reasoning through faith in God strikes me as bizarre, because
as an atheist once said, to explain the unknown by the known is a
logical procedure; to explain the known by the unknown is a form of
theological lunacy.
I’m very familiar with the precepts
of reasoning and rules of logic, etc. We don’t need to derive faith in
to explain these or how we’re able to do them. That’s, by the way, how
we’re able to do it. That’s more of a biological issue, an issue of
evolution—the nature of consciousness and so forth. But to be more
specific, it seems to me even if there is a problem there, to say God is
responsible, well we’re dealing with this mysterious, vague notion of a
God and we’re going to have faith in this thing and how did God bring
all this about. In other words, it seems to me that we’re dealing with
something relatively simple and straightforward and can be dealt with
through reason and philosophy. And the theologian comes along and says,
“I’m going to explain everything, and I’m going to explain it by
positing an unknowable being who does things using some unknowable means
and, there!, that clears up the problem!” That for me simply compounds
the problem. On top of the philosophical problems we already have,
we’re adding this whole theological scene now which also has to be
explained. So, I simply disagree. Now, do you want me to address your
. . .
Moderator:
The destruction of human life. I’m
interested in that as well. Why should it matter? If people are
irrational and that leads to the destruction of human life—I mean, from
an atheistic perspective, so what?
Smith:
You’re getting into the issue of
ethics, and [in] that very same book I have a quarter that deals with a
question of that. Now let me first say one thing. I’m not alone on
this. Now, I know that Greg says he’s more from an Augustinian
tradition rather than a Thomistic tradition, but philosophers in the
Thomistic tradition—and not just Catholics, those from that general
background—they themselves admit that reason can discover certain
precepts of natural law unaided by revelation, that God created the
universe in a certain way, and this is called natural revelation. The
deistic movement of the 18th and late 17th century talked about this. As
Greg well knows, there are different traditions here. Unlike Augustine,
Aquinas held that although he believed in original sin, he did not hold
his argument that original sin had corrupted man’s reasoning ability to
the extent that Augustine had. So he argued that even with original sin
it was still possible for human beings through the use of reason to
discern certain natural laws. Now certainly he thought they had to be
aided and supplemented by revelation, but he held that reason was
efficacious in that respect.
So the atheist is not alone in
holding that the precepts of morality, and if you understand what I mean
by natural law ethics that’s traditionally what it’s been called. The
use of reason, investigating the nature of human beings, the nature of
the environment in which we find ourselves, the nature of decision
making, you can arrive at general principles on how to live a good life.
Now, as to the question: why should we care? Well, that’s a legitimate
question. I care because for me happiness is a goal in itself. A good
life is a goal in itself. I could put the same question to the
Christian. Suppose God does exist, why should we care? Because he
tells us to care? Why kind of basis is this for ethics? I mean, it
puzzles me.
It seems that a philosopher has to
be concerned with rational arguments for an ethical system. Along comes
the Christian and says, “I have a basis for ethics. God will punish you
if you do this, and he’ll reward you if you do that!” That sounds to me
like a system of commandments. Either you do this or you don’t.
Where’s the reason there? Is it right only because God wills it, or
does God will it because it’s right? That’s a classic question. Is
murder wrong only because God says it’s wrong? If God tomorrow changed
his mind and said, “Thou shalt go out and murder,” would that make
murder right? Or does God forbid murder because murder is intrinsically
wrong? It seems to me the Christian is caught on the horns of a
dilemma. Either he has to take a hard line—it’s wrong because God wills
it to be wrong, in which case morality is reduced to a set of arbitrary
decrees with no reason behind them—or he has to say that God himself
forbids certain things because they are simply wrong. In which case
there’s a standard of morality apart from the will of God.
Moderator:
Okay, let’s hold it there, a lot on
the table. We’ll take a break and let Greg Bahnsen respond. . . . Greg,
to address what George has just raised, why don’t you respond to him
perhaps and people just tuning in, they can figure out what’s going on
here.
Bahnsen:
Yeah, let me kind of catch the
audience up here. I have suggested that Christians do not renounce the
use of reason, but I actually argue that reason cannot be intelligently
utilized apart from a Christian worldview and that, therefore, when we
find atheists like George Smith trying to be reasonable using criteria
for intelligibility and so forth, they are in fact acting like
crypto-Christians. That is, they’re working in terms of a Christian
worldview all the while denying what they know about God in their heart
of hearts.
And now George has responded to that
and I can understand why he would. Well, that may be just kind of a
version of name-calling. It’s like you say you’re an atheist, but I say
you’re really not. And I can respond by when you say you’re a
Christian, I say you’re an atheist. But you see, that is not the nature
of the claim here. If George believes that this is a reversible claim,
then, of course, we need to engage in some rational combat here and talk
about that. I would argue that the reason I say that he really does
know God in his heart of hearts is because he gives evidence of
depending upon the Christian worldview even when he reasons against the
Christian worldview.
And I’m not going to do that right
this minute, but just so you have some idea of what I’m talking about:
if George appeals to moral absolutes, I’m going to say, “Well, that’s
the sort of thing that Christians do that makes sense if there’s a God.
But the moral absolutes you appeal to in order to renounce belief in
God—it doesn’t make any sense in your worldview.” And I think [that’s
also the case] when you appeal to the use of scientific method and you
assume the uniformity of nature; but, of course, on an atheist worldview
you can’t make sense out of the uniformity of nature. Those are the
sorts of things that we would end up talking about if I was going to
show that, as a matter of fact, even his use of reason and moral
argumentation presupposes what he’s arguing against.
Now let’s bring this back to our
conversation. He has suggested, “Oh, well I could argue just the
opposite with you, that as a matter of fact what you’re doing
presupposes atheism.” And to that I would simply say, “George, name
that tune. Go ahead, if you think that you can show that I’m
presupposing atheism. I’d like to see the argument for that!” Because
I wasn’t just making an empty authority claim when I said you’re
presupposing the Christian worldview. I’m going to give you evidence
that you’re presupposing, and I’m going to show that you can’t make
sense of your reasoning and morality apart from it. And what you need
to do now is to show that I can’t make sense of my Christian morality
apart from the non-existence of God. That doesn’t strike me as a very
likely prospect for a philosopher to get to that conclusion, but I’d be
open to that. It’s not just a matter of name-calling and reversing
authority claims here when we talk about the pre-conditions of
intelligibility.
Now, when it comes to morality, I
need to move on quickly here. George has commented that even certain
Christian theologians have said that natural law is a basis for a
natural knowledge of at least some moral precepts, maybe not all that we
need, but some fundamental ones. And to him I would simply say I would
argue against those Christian theologians just as much as I would argue
against him that natural law is not in fact a source for moral
absolutes, that one cannot argue that from what is the case even the
natural regularities that we see about us to what ought to be the case.
You can’t move from a description of the world that we live in and our
experience to the way things ought to be. So he is right that some
Christian traditions would be closer to him, but my severe challenge to
the atheist would remain and I’d say I’d put the theologians who argue
from natural law right over there too and I’d say, “Let’s see if you can
justify ethics based on that any better than George can!” And I don’t
think they can.
Now is punishment the basis for
Christian ethics? Suggestion was made that we believe that, say, murder
is wrong because God has said so and he’ll punish us if we don’t agree.
But that of course is not the Christian position at all. Did God
forbid murder arbitrarily? This is the issue of voluntarism in
theology. And the old conundrum from the days of Plato has supposedly
been, well if God does this simply on the basis of his sheer volition,
he just wills murder to be wrong, then of course tomorrow he could will
murder to be right. On the other hand, if God has some reason for
willing murder to be wrong, then, of course, you don’t need God in order
to believe that murder is wrong, because the reason God has would be the
basis. But what that overlooks completely from a Christian standpoint
is God forbids murder because it’s contrary to his own unchanging
character. And God’s volition, that is to say his expressed will,
saying “Thou shalt not murder” is based upon who he is—the kind of God
he is and that is unchanging. So the character of God is the basis of
Christian morality, not simply the revelation of God or threats of
eternal punishment if we should be murderers and so forth.
When George says that happiness is a
goal in itself, see I would throw the voluntarist problem back on him at
that point and say, “Well, George, even assuming—and I don’t think this
is correct, but just for argument’s sake—that on the basis of happiness
as your telos or goal for living that you could make sense of why
you don’t murder or why you try to be reasonable. I would still
challenge you: why can’t another individual freely say, “Well, I don’t
want to live for happiness, and I don’t want to live for life-affirming
values, and so forth? That is, in an atheist universe there would be no
absolutes at all. It would be everyone for themselves or, as
Shakespeare put it: “Sound and fury signifying nothing.”
Moderator:
George?
Smith:
Okay, a lot of stuff here; I’ll try
to be brief. First of all, there’s confusion here, and this goes back to
Greg’s original point. There is no “atheistic worldview,” let’s get
straight about that. Atheism is simply the absence of belief in God.
It does not by itself suggest or dictate any positive philosophy.
There are a lot of atheists with a lot of different worldviews.
Suppose, for example, that I don’t
believe in magic elves, which I don’t, and let’s call my disbelief
elfism. It’s as if Greg would say, “Well, elfism as a worldview doesn’t
explain anything.” And I agree, it doesn’t, it wasn’t meant to explain
anything. It’s the absence of a belief. And I’m the first to admit that
lacking a belief doesn’t explain anything. It’s the role of philosophy
after you’re an atheist to construct a positive philosophy which may
have no intrinsic relationship to your atheism, per se. There are
atheist existentialists, atheist Marxists, atheist advocates of Ayn
Rand’s objectivism. Atheism is again not a worldview, and that’s the
basic confusion here.
In that sense, I suppose the
Christian worldview does explain more than the atheistic
worldview—simply because even if the Christian worldview explains one
thing it’s got it over atheism, because atheism isn’t a worldview and it
wasn’t meant to explain anything. So in that sense, I agree.
As for this stuff about God’s
unchanging character, let me just address the ethics thing. The problem
with this is that it would take a lot of airtime and a lot of discussion
to sit here and discuss the rational foundations of ethics, but I’d
rather address one of the points first. This idea that somehow
implicitly I show evidence of having a belief in God.
Did Christianity invent these
things? Was Aristotle somehow a Christian at heart even centuries
before the time of Jesus? My view is Aristotelian, if it’s anything,
and unless we’re going to argue that these pagan philosophers—by the
way, that was an interesting question addressed by the early Greek
apologists: to what extent the pagan or the Greek philosophers could’ve
had true knowledge without knowledge of Christ. And they argued, kind
of, that some of the Greek philosophers had gotten their wisdom from
Moses, and they went around in circles trying to justify how anyone who
obviously were not Christians—because it was before the time of
Christianity—could’ve received true knowledge. So I don’t really know
how to respond to that exactly. It seems to me that it’s just playing
word games essentially.
There’s nothing implicitly theistic
about me saying A is A. And to take a very simple example, why does
that evidence lead to belief in God? “A is A” is a self-evident truth,
the existence of God certainly isn’t. It seems to me that “A is A” is
much more evident than the existence of God is. Again, I don’t see any
reason there to suppose that we need to believe in God.
Bahnsen:
Well, let me suggest first of all
that you’re right that there is no one atheist worldview in the sense
that all atheists agree with each other about epistemology, and ethics,
and metaphysics. I was being general when [I] talked about the atheist
worldview. But to state it more precisely, all we’re saying is [that]
no particular atheist worldview can make sense out of reason, ethics,
the sorts of things that are necessary for human life, to make sense out
of life. And so if you want to talk about existentialism, then we’ll
take time to talk to do that, if you want to talk about Aristotle, we’ll
take time to do that.
What I’m saying is in each and every
single case, those who reject the worldview that I’m describing as
Biblical Christianity are not able to make sense out of proof and
science and ethics and so forth. Atheism is not a generic name for a
positive worldview, but there is no positive atheistic worldview where
reason is even a necessity much less something that can be made sense
out of.
Now, when George ends his last
answer by saying, “‘A is A’ is self evident,” what I would say is: go
back and study logic. I mean, the law of identity has been rejected by
some people. There are some worldviews, atheistic non-Christian
worldviews that don’t agree—but now, look, I do agree with the
law of identity, I believe in logic and so forth—but, you see, I believe
that I can make sense out of that because I am a Christian. But in a
non-Christian worldview, there really isn’t a reason why we couldn’t
deny the law of identity or come up with other kinds of what we might (I
think you and I would agree) would be contradictory approaches to logic,
but nevertheless are called logic in some worldviews.
Moderator:
[Unintelligible] to jump in we’ll
take a break and come right back. . . . Before we go to the phones, Greg
Bahnsen you were sort of on a roll there, and I think I cut you off
prematurely. What were you about to say?
Bahnsen:
Well, I wanted to respond real
quickly to George’s good question: Was Aristotle a Christian at heart?
And I’m going to bite the bullet and say, yes he was. I don’t mean by
that, of course, anything like what the early Christians struggled with,
whether Aristotle or Plato had learned about Moses and through Moses and
so forth. We as Christians believe God has revealed himself in the
natural order and through the conscience of man. We believe that all men
know this God even if they haven’t had a Biblical revelation of him, so
in that sense, Aristotle had a Christian worldview in his heart of
hearts even if he didn’t know about Moses or Christ for that matter. In
the same way that an Old Testament Jew would’ve been able to make sense
out of reason and ethics and science because of the worldview provided
to him by God in revelation.
In George’s book, I noticed
something again that I appreciated very much when he said that it’s the
responsibility of the philosopher to identify the underlying assumptions
of commonly held beliefs. And I think on that note, he and I could have
a very fruitful discussion trying to identify the underlying
assumptions, say, of the scientific method, and if I can just throw that
one out—I’d like to know how George would deal with this. We know that
those who engage in the scientific method are able to extrapolate
knowledge from the past into the future by assuming what’s called
induction. That is, that future cases will be like past cases or in
popular [unintelligible] the uniformity of nature.
Now, I know George believes in the
procedures of science; I do too, as a Christian. And the reason why I
would rely upon the principle of induction is because I believe in a
sovereign God who controls the universe. But it would be interesting to
know what underlying assumption George has when he engages in the same
scientific procedure as me. Is he using induction as a principle and,
if so, why? Is that arbitrary?
Moderator:
George?
Smith:
Well the underlying assumption is
that a thing is what it is. An existing thing has specific
characteristics, and it’s restricted to the range of behavior or action
as defined by those characteristics. A cat will not give birth to baby
elephants.
Bahnsen:
Why not?
Smith:
Because that’s the nature of the
cat.
Bahnsen:
Well, that’s begging the question,
to say it’s the nature of the cat.
Smith:
But you say that it’s the nature of
God all the time. I can say it’s the nature of the cat.
Bahnsen:
No, actually I’m not just saying
it’s the nature of God. I’m saying God reveals himself to people . . .
Smith:
I’m saying my view of causation is
that causation is essentially the law of identity applied to action.
Things act as they do because they have specific, determinate
characteristics and the [unintelligible] the physical or whatever nature
of an existing thing determines the nature of the actions that that
thing can take. So when one billiard ball strikes another billiard
ball, the nature of the billiard ball is the nature of the motion,
determines what the causal result will be. That’s why we get down to
the law of identity. There’s regularity in nature because things are
existing, determinate things with specific characteristics.
Bahnsen:
Well, it’s a tremendous
philosophical mistake to assimilate the law of causality to the laws of
logic, but if you study the history of philosophy, you’d know that this
idea that things have a determinate nature and that’s why they behave
the way they do is associated with the conclusion that there can be no
change, that is, it’s impossible for things to change, well, because the
law of identity prevents things from changing. So now I would continue
the discussion. Let’s look at our underlying assumptions. How is it
possible to extrapolate into the future, if you use the law of
identity—there’s no change to look for in the future.
Smith:
Well, let’s assume that I’m wrong.
I could refer you to books: H. W. B Joseph’s book on logic. Maybe you’d
consider it outdated. Brand Blanshard held a very similar view. It’s
been held by—Richard Taylor holds a similar view. Okay, but let’s
assume that they’re all wrong and it’s a minority view on the nature of
causation. Granted. But at least I’m trying to reach an explanation
within the sphere of reason. In other words, it seems to me that my
explanation, even if you don’t accept it, makes a lot more sense than
saying God does it. I mean, to me that explains nothing. If you’d like
to quote another line from my book, quote the line where I said: the
concept of God explains nothing. When you’ve been talking to me about
how can we explain this, how can we make sense of this. Okay, I’m
attempting to give an explanation and maybe an incorrect one, but it is
within the realm of human understanding. I would challenge you to tell
me how God explains anything. Let’s assume there is a problem, if my
explanation—let’s make sense out of it: “A Blark did it.” That’s all I
say. And I would say to you Greg, “You know, Greg, you really couldn’t
reason if it weren’t for the existence of a Blark! You’d be a little
bit puzzled and you’d understand the problem here and to me if we’re
going to talk about explanation, right or wrong it has to be in the real
of human understanding and human reason. If you simply plug in the word
“Blark” or in your case the word “God,” whenever you encounter a
problem, it doesn’t solve the problem. That is my fundamental point.
Bahnsen:
I understand. The fallacy here is
the false analogy that when a person appeals to God he’s appealing to an
undefined word like “Blark.”
Smith:
But you haven’t defined it.
Bahnsen:
Well, I’d be glad to do, though. We
can open up the Bible; we can look to the Westminster Confession of
Faith for a definition of God. I don’t think you have any doubt that
Christians have a definition of God.
Smith:
They have many definitions of God.
Bahnsen:
They do, and we’re going to deal
with the one that I hold to because I’m the one arguing today.
Smith:
Good point.
Bahnsen:
Does appealing to God explain
anything? Well, of course when you ask philosophically: what is an
explanation? The answer is, of course, it does. It may strike you as
being as easy as a Sunday school child’s understanding, but if I’ve got
a Heavenly Father who created the entire universe and controls every
detail, even to the hairs on my head, and I say of this creative
personality who has this sovereign might and plan that he sees to it
that gravity holds on planet Earth day by day by day—that does in fact
explain it, but it may not be the explanation that you want. I’m just
talking about now what counts as an explanation. An explanation is
something which enables you to predict the future and to account for why
you predict it that way.
Moderator:
. . .
Taking your phone calls let’s go to
Benny a first time caller from Hawaiian Gardens. Benny you’re on KKLA.
Benny:
Hi John. My question is for Mr.
Smith, and what I’d like to ask him is, where does he believe life
started or came from?
Smith:
Okay, that question can be taken one
of two ways, as a philosophical question or as a scientific question.
I’m not a scientist, so my scientific answer, I don’t know. By the
way, if I can mention a book called The Blind Watchmaker by
Richard Dawkins, which I think is one of the best books I’ve seen,
directly addressing his creationist argument, and I think it’s a very
plausible book for people who might be skeptical about evolution. But
it seems to me what the caller might be getting at is the philosophical
problem of the origin of life. Without going into all the problems
there and by the way Dawkins does address them, let me say that
philosophically, life is just one natural aspect of the universe that
seems to have evolved and seems to be rather unusual as far as we know
among planets, but I don’t think there’s any philosophical problem
involved.
Moderator:
Is there any concern about first
cause that you need to get into from your perspective, George?
Smith:
Well, no, I mean, again it depends
when you’re asking me philosophically or scientifically.
Philosophically, I don’t think the first cause argument holds up. The
so-called argument from life doesn’t hold up as a philosophical point.
There are other objections to these arguments, but it seems to me one
of the prime objections, one of the most commonly raised, is that the
argument always has to go back one step further. If everything must
have a cause and we wish the conclusion that therefore God doesn’t have
a cause, or that seems to be part of the argument, well, if everything
has to have a cause, then God has to have a cause.
Moderator:
Unless there’s an infinite regress.
Greg Bahnsen, how would you address what Benny has asked here about
life?
Bahnsen:
Well, I think Benny’s question’s a
very good one. See, I would follow it up George, by asking: Is it your
belief that life came from non-life, or is it your belief that life is,
I think you were saying, part of the characteristics of reality or the
universe in which case there always has been life—it never did have to
come into being, it’s always been in being.
And secondly—and I’ll be quiet at
that point—I think the question of first cause arguments has not been
adequately dealt with if you only talk about the overly general approach
to the cosmological argument that says everything has to have a cause,
and then the question naturally is: Does God have to have a cause? A
more profound question is: What do we presuppose when we use the concept
of causality? This is going to be a repeat of what George has heard
earlier. I would argue that when people use the causal notion or the
inductive principle that they are presupposing a Christian view of the
universe and that’s what makes science possible. So I wouldn’t argue
that you go from cause back to cause back to cause and finally get to
God. That’s a very, I think, primitive understanding of the argument,
but I think the very notion of causality presupposes the Christian God,
as well. But back to life. Does life come from non-life?
Smith:
That’s a scientific question and I
don’t know. My best guess would be that it would be the complex protein
molecules that go into the building blocks of life probably did come out
of synthesizing processes and so forth. Dawkins goes into that, but
again, that’s a scientific not a philosophical question.
Bahnsen:
But I do think it illustrates
something that’s very important for your hearers to know, John. And
that’s that atheists are just as much full of what we might call “faith
commitments” as Christians are. Clearly they are different commitments,
but you have George here saying that he’s willing to acknowledge the
possibility of life coming from non-life. The next question would be—
Smith:
I said I don’t know.
Bahnsen:
He doesn’t know, but I mean after
all we have to have some view of life when we talk about it. There’s an
empty faith commitment here about life, it seems to me, when you say you
don’t know. Maybe it did come from non-life—that irrational possibility
exists. Did intelligence come from non-intelligence? Did morality come
from non-morality? There are always these leaps and gaps in the
non-Christian worldview that obviously in two minutes we’re not going to
the get to the bottom of, but they’re worth exploring and so I’m glad
Benny asked that question.
Moderator:
Okay, Benny, I appreciate the call.
Let’s go to Jared a first-time caller from Costa Mesa. Jared, you’re on
KKLA.
Jared:
Hi John. My question is for George.
The name of his book is . . . what?
Moderator:
Atheism: The Case
Against God. That’s his first book, and his
second book is Atheism, Ayn Rand, and Other Heresies.
Jared:
Okay, speaking about what
everybody’s talking about today with evidence, the Bible being our
evidence with the appearance to Moses, the history of prophecy and how
they came true, the claims and miracles of Christ, and the eyewitness
resurrection of Christ. We have evidence, but yet I haven’t heard any
evidence from Mr. Smith of a claim of no evidence against God, the
belief in God, or the existence of God.
Smith:
As I said at the beginning of the
program, the atheist is not obliged to prove anything. Atheism is simply
the lack of belief. If you do not believe in the existence of magic
elves it is not incumbent on you to prove that they don’t exist or to
give reasons why you don’t believe. If I come forward to you and say,
“I just saw a magic elf running across the room and disappear in a puff
of smoke!” And challenge you to disprove it and [ask you] why don’t you
believe it. You simply say, “If you want me to believe it, prove it, or
give me some reason to think that it wasn’t just a figment of your
imagination.”
Bahnsen:
I think in the history of the vocabulary of atheism, agnosticism and so
forth, that it would be a fair remark although I have no jealousy for
the words—who cares about the words—but I do think that atheism has not
meant what George is portraying. I mean that’s closer to what we’ve
been calling agnosticism. But it is interesting to me—and I think your
caller is on to something that I wondered about too as I looked at
George’s book—it’s subtitled The Case Against God. He’s not
saying that there’s no case for God, which is the only thing he’s done
this afternoon is to say, “Well, you know the burden of proof is on
you!” But when you write a book, George, against God, I think you do
bear the burden of some proof to show why we should be against and not
just neutral on the question.
Smith:
Yes, and that’s what the 327 pages
are about.
Moderator:
Okay, we’ll leave it at that. I
appreciate the call, Jared. We’ll take a break and take more of your
phone calls. Stay with us.
Moderator:
. . .
Before we go back to the phones,
George, you wanted to give more or less your definition of atheism.
Smith:
Well, I’ve already given it, but
Greg raised a point, which is a very common misconception that somehow
defining atheism as the absence of belief as opposed to what’s called
the positive definition, the outright denial, etc., the idiosyncratic
definition. In fact, it’s not. In my recent book I have an entire
[unintelligible] called defining atheism and I present just as examples,
twelve to fifteen or more prominent atheists who for the last 200 years
have defined atheism in precisely that manner, along with a number of
prominent theologians: Richard Watson, around the mid 1800’s, Robert
Flint, in a very important book on agnosticism, who was a Christian, who
simply said atheism is the lack or the absence of belief in God. My
point is that we should look to what atheists have been arguing for many
years and what they themselves claimed to have been saying, not to
critics who tell us what they should have said.
Moderator:
Okay, let’s go back to the phones.
Max, a first time caller from Canoga Park who I think I’ve heard from
before. Max, you’re on KKLA.
Max:
Howdy-doo! George?
Smith:
Yes?
Max:
I’ve got your book and it’s
dog-eared and underlined and highlighted all over the place. I think
it’s the best book that has ever been written on atheism.
Smith:
Thank you.
Max:
But the title should really be
Atheism: The Case Against the Idea of God
Smith:
Yes.
Max:
And that’s what you meant?
Smith:
Yeah, there was a little dramatic
license taken that would have spoiled the symmetry of the title. So
it’s a philosophical case against God, obviously.
Max:
And as to this explaining things,
how does one explain existence? To me that is totally absurd.
Smith:
I agree. Existence is simply the
causal primary. In other words, if you ask for a causal explanation of
something, that presupposes something that exists and acts as a causal
agent.
Max:
Exactly, and all of the arguments
for the existence of God presuppose the existence of God. It’s question
begging.
Bahnsen:
There’s no problem with that.
Moderator:
Hold on Max. Let Greg Bahnsen
respond to that.
Bahnsen:
Yeah, I think that is one of the
most common and silly arguments against the Christian apologetic
imaginable. Of course arguments in favor of God presuppose the
existence of God, just like arguments in favor of atheistic reason
presuppose atheistic reason.
Max:
Wait a minute, wait a minute, Sir.
Wait a minute, just one minute. There is no reason to presuppose
reason. Reason exists naturally. Without reason we wouldn’t be able to
. . .
Bahnsen:
Oh, it does? Now wait a minute,
where did you find reason growing naturally? Show me where that is.
Someone place in the United States?
Max:
Reason? Reason is the human brain,
Sir.
Bahnsen:
Oh, it is? Then what you’re talking
about is electro-chemical processes in the brain.
Max:
Is that not natural?
Bahnsen:
Well, that certainly is natural, but
that’s not at all what you mean by reason, I assure you, when you talk
about the use of the laws of logic because your brain cells are not
being controlled by anything like the laws of logic.
Max:
What are my cells being controlled
by?
Bahnsen:
Well, I would argue they’re being
controlled by God, but that’s not the answer you want. The question
that I have for you is: If you assume the laws of physics and biology
and so forth, I would think that you believe your brain cells are being
controlled by those laws and in which case you’re not really thinking
and making free decisions when you say the things you do, even arguing
against God. You’re simply the subject of bio-chemical responses. That
is not what we have meant historically by the use of reason.
Max:
Sir, as to controlling things by
natural laws, natural laws are nothing more than uniform occurrences
that do happen with unvarying uniformity.
Bahnsen:
Max, have you ever seen a natural
law? Have you ever tasted one, smelled one—
Max:
Of course not! The entire concept of
a law is totally abstract.
Bahnsen:
Exactly. Now can you explain to me
how in an atheist universe there are such things as abstract entities?
Max:
Come on! Every idea, every thought
is an abstraction.
Bahnsen:
That’s right; every one of them is
proof that you’re wrong as an atheist, then. How do you account for the
existence of abstract ideas in an atheist universe? They don’t grow on
trees, Max. You’ve already admitted that.
Max:
Oh boy, oh boy.
Bahnsen:
Well, now. Look, live by your own
presuppositions. That’s all I’m calling you to do.
Smith:
Is God an abstraction, Greg?
Bahnsen:
Uh, no.
Smith:
What is he?
Bahnsen:
God is a personal, non-physical
being.
Smith:
He’s non-physical. Give me more
specifics, I mean. Non-existence is non-physical as well, so how do we
distinguish God from non-existence?
Max:
I’m going to hang up, George, make
him explain God.
Smith:
I’m doing my best, Max.
Moderator:
Max, appreciate the call. Okay, go
ahead.
Bahnsen:
Well, obviously you distinguish God,
a non-physical being from, say, the concept of love or say, the concept
of number or the laws of physics or the laws of logic. You distinguish
them according to their characteristics. God is a person, makes choices
and does things. Numbers do not.
Smith:
He’s a non-physical person?
Bahnsen:
He’s a non-physical person, that’s
right. Well, you know that already, George, so make your point.
Smith:
Well, I don’t understand what the
concept of person—and it was as Max said, you’re getting on his case
about these abstractions and you’re claiming God somehow—
Bahnsen:
Oh, I don’t have any problem with
abstractions except in an atheist universe. In an atheist universe what
you have is a physical eyeball and a physical ear and some kind of stuff
in the head called a brain. What I want to know is where do you get
abstractions?
Smith:
Well, see, you’re going from the
unknown to the known.
Bahnsen:
No, I’m not. I’m going from the
known to the known.
Smith:
However, you think abstractions
originate or where they come from or how we explain them, I think we can
agree we do abstract and we do think conceptually. We know that.
Bahnsen:
The fact that we abstract is not the
issue here. It’s accounting for abstractions, which you can’t do.
Smith:
But we can agree at least to begin
with that even though I do not disagree. There are—abstractions do
exist.
Bahnsen:
In my universe it makes sense, in
yours it doesn’t.
Smith:
So at least we can agree, I know
what an abstraction is roughly, let’s say. Now, you claim that
abstractions need some sort of explanation and I say “Greg, what’s your
explanation for abstractions?” And you say, “It’s a personal,
non-physical person.”
Bahnsen:
No, I think you’ve mistaken me. You
asked what God was and I answered that. I think we both know what an
abstraction is. I didn’t ask for an explanation of an abstraction as
though you’ve go to give me some sort of causal story of where the
abstraction came from. I asked for how abstractions make sense, are
cogent, within a worldview where there is nothing but matter.
Moderator:
Okay, gentlemen, why don’t we hold that thought. . . . Let’s go to
Tina, first time caller from Covina. Tina, you’re on KKLA.
Tina:
Hi John, my question is to George: I
was wondering, has he studied the Bible?
Moderator:
That’s the question?
Tina:
Yes, well that’s part of the
question.
Moderator:
Well, what’s the whole question?
Tina:
My whole question, oh well, it’s a
tough one. . . . I was wondering what his conclusion is of what he has
studied.
Moderator:
What does he think about the Bible,
does it contain truth?
Smith:
Well, when I was in high school the
thing that really started getting me really very skeptical was when I
read the Bible from cover to cover for the first time because, like many
devout Christians, I never read the whole thing. I had read
pre-selected excerpts primarily from the New Testament from the Gospel
of John. And, I must say, the Old Testament centralizing on the
violence, the ceremonial laws—I wouldn’t say they swayed me from
Christianity, but it got me thinking. [I] went into my neighborhood
gospel supply, bought the Abingdon Bible Commentary, started buying the
Interpreter’s Bible commentaries, Bible dictionaries, concordances . . .
so in that sense—that was years ago—but yes, I studied the Bible, and I
don’t believe everything I read. That’s my reaction to it. It has some
very nice—I must say, literarily speaking, the book of Ecclesiastes is
beautifully written in the King James Version [and] Song of Solomon.
So, as literature some of it is quite nice.
Moderator:
But as far as being the source of
truth?
Smith:
Well, I mean there are some decent
things in the Bible, sure. There are some elegantly expressed moral
maxims, that sort of thing. It’s a collection of books not one book.
Some of it I like, some of it I don’t.
Moderator:
Greg Bahnsen, quick response to
Tina.
Bahnsen:
Well, I think her question was
really a personal and biographical one for George, and I understand his
answer. Maybe I’d say just in favor of the ceremonial laws of the Old
Testament, which are often a stumbling point for reading. But in a
sense, if you read them as foreshadows of the coming Savior, there’s
really a lot of beauty in most ceremonial laws: God displaying outwardly
to his people what the Messiah and his redemptive work would be like.
Smith:
Well, in the King James Version in
the Song of Solomon there are some of the more erotically expressed
passages and if you look at the running headings they say things like
“Christ Expresses His Love to the Church”—I had a hard time buying [that
that] what the Song of Solomon was really about.
Bahnsen:
I do, too, George.
Moderator:
Of course, a lot of those are
post hoc understandings of the Bible that not everyone accepts. I
appreciate my guests joining us. George Smith, your books Atheism:
The Case Against God, Atheism, Ayn Rand, and Other Heresies,
those are available in bookstores published by Prometheus. . . . Well,
Greg and George, I appreciate both of you joining us and I think it was
a very interesting, lively discussion. Thanks so much.
Bahnsen:
Thanks, John.
Greg L. Bahnsen page