From The
Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society 20:4
(December, 1977), as reprinted in Evangelicals and Inerrancy, ed.
Ronald Youngblood (Nashville: Thomas Nelson, 1984), 199-216. Main text
taken from
Covenant Media Foundation,
but corrected against the anthologized text. By “corrected,” I mean not
only that words set in ALL CAPITALS in that online version have been
restored to italics, but also that many other errors of spelling,
punctuation, incompleteness of reference, misplaced text, missing words,
and other infelicities have been corrected. For greater ease of reading,
I have taken the liberty of breaking up certain paragraphs into smaller
units.
Anthony Flood
November 17, 2011
Inductivism, Inerrancy, and Presuppositionalism
Greg Bahnsen
At the heart of contemporary evangelical bibliology and apologetics is
the question of Scriptural inerrancy—in particular, the most appropriate
and effective method of its exposition and defense. The three elements
mentioned in the title of this paper have been derived from a short but
potentially significant interchange between Daniel Fuller and Clark
Pinnock in the Christian Scholar’s Review.1
Their brief discussion of Biblical
authority is a noteworthy skirmish—one that puts a particular
epistemological and apologetical outlook to a critical test. An
analysis of the Fuller-Pinnock encounter may very well offer
evangelicals unexpected but sound guidance through the thicket of
present-day theological and apologetical questions impinging on
inerrancy. To begin this recommended analysis we can rehearse how
Fuller and Pinnock relate the three topics of inductivism, inerrancy and
presuppositionalsim to each other. Three major theses emerge from a
reading of the two published letters exchanged between these two
writers, and each can be substantiated by quotation from the relevant
literature. Thesis I may be stated as follows: Presuppositionalism is
opposed to empirical procedures and inductive investigation.
Fuller says to Pinnock: “If faith really has to begin the
approach to Scripture, then I don’t think you can talk very meaningfully
about induction. I would argue that really, after all, you are on Van
Til’s side, not on Warfield’s” (p. 331). “I am trying to do as Warfield
and let induction control from beginning to end. You say on page 185 [of
Pinnock’s Biblical Revelation] that following Christ’s view of
Scripture ‘will always prove safe’. . . . This is the language of an
unassailable starting point—the language of deductive thinking—of Van
Til” (p. 332).
Pinnock replies to Fuller: “It is more common to be criticized by our
fideistic evangelical colleagues for being too concerned about questions
of factual verification. Dr. Fuller recognizes that I wish to follow
the epistemology of the Princeton apologetic as it was developed by B.
B. Warfield, but he believes that I am inconsistent in this and tend to
lapse into presuppositional modes of expression, if not thought. He
would even place me on Van Til’s side, mirabile dictu” (p. 333).
Pinnock wants us to understand that “Dr. Fuller and I share a view of
the constructive relation between faith and history” (p. 333).
Thus it is that both Pinnock and Fuller set an inductive, empirical
approach (like that of Warfield and the Princeton school) over against
the approach of presuppositionalism (as found in an apologist like Van
Til). On the one side you have a constructive relation between history
and faith where induction controls from beginning to end the questions
of factual verification, whereas on the other side you have mere
deductivism and fideism. Presuppositionalism and inductivism are
accor-dingly portrayed as polar opposites, as conflicting
epistemologies. To this antagonism Fuller and Pinnock both give assent.
Here now is Thesis II: Inductivism and empirical apologetics are
independent of presuppositional commitments, letting neutral reason and
critical thinking control the knowing process from beginning to end.
On this point Fuller and Pinnock are again agreed. In their discussion
with each other, both men make much of the alleged “inductive” nature of
their epistemologies and their approach to Biblical authority (and hence
apologetics). It is indispensable at this point to rehearse what they
mean by their commitment to “inductive” procedures. Let us once more
have them speak for themselves to this question.
“Induction, as I understand it, means letting criticism control all
aspects of the knowing process from beginning to end” (Fuller, p. 330).
“All knowing, including the knowledge which faith claims to have, comes
by but one way” (Fuller, p. 332). This one way is the empirical
approach, which is committed to factual verification (Pinnock, p. 333).
With inductivism faith does not begin the approach to Scripture, nor
does it start the knowing process at all (Fuller, pp. 331, 332). On the
other hand, true empiricism does not let negative criticism and
naturalistic presuppositions control thought (Pinnock, p. 333).
Therefore Fuller and Pinnock are saying that one begins with neither a
commitment to Scripture nor a commitment against Scripture. Apparently,
then, one is to be completely “open-minded” or neutral from the outset.
Indeed, this is precisely what they both claim. For inductivism
maintains that no mere claim to authority is self-establishing (Fuller,
p. 330), and it refuses to claim “an unassailable starting point”
(Fuller, p. 332). Moreover, it will not permit circular reasoning and
argumentation (Fuller, p. 330). Hence inductivism on this account does
not resort to self-attesting starting points, nor does its chain of
explanations and evidences ever bend around and ultimately book into
itself, forming a wide argumentative circle. Clearly, then, this
outlook holds to “the right of reason and criticism to be sovereign”
(Fuller, p. 330). It will “let critical thinking prevail” (Fuller, p.
332)—“to go all the way” (p. 333), because “you can’t just have it ‘in
part’” (Fuller, p. 332). According to Fuller and Pinnock, if one is
“consistently inductive” (p. 332) his every commitment will be based
totally on empirical evidences and critical thinking. In particular,
belief in inspiration and the security of Biblical authority will rest,
we are told, totally on inductive evidence (Fuller, p. 332) and
well-authenticated credentials (Pinnock, p. 333). This, then, is the
non-presuppositional inductive (or empirical) approach that Fuller and
Pinnock claim to be utilizing. It makes a radical, all-encompassing
demand on us epistemologically—“you either have it or you don’t”
(Fuller, p. 332).
We would formulate Thesis III as follows: The question of biblical
inerrancy can be settled only inductively. It should be rather
obvious that this thesis is demanded by the previous two.
Presuppositionalism has been shunned, and the radical demand to let
inductive empiricism answer every question in the knowing process has
been affirmed. Thus the question of the Bible’s errant or inerrant
nature must be answered, if at all, in an inductive manner. Fuller and
Pinnock would both say as much.
However, these two committed empiricists and anti-presuppositionalists
do not come to the same conclusion about the inerrant nature of
Scripture—that is, in the application of their common inductive approach
they have reached contrary positions. Fuller maintains the full
inerrancy of “any Scriptural statement or necessary implication
therefrom which involves what makes a man wise to salvation” (p. 331):
“if it errs where historical control is possible in matters germane to
‘the whole counsel of God’ which ‘makes men wise unto salvation,’ then
all the Bible becomes questionable” (p. 332). Pinnock calls this
unacceptable: “Though convenient for sidestepping certain biblical
difficulties, this dichotomy is unworkable and unscriptural” (p. 334).
We must, instead, take the view of the Biblical authors: “The attitude
of Jesus and the Apostles toward Scripture was one of total
trust. . . . What Scripture said, with a priori qualification,
God said, was their view. The whole graphē is God-breathed and
fully trustworthy” (p. 334). Consequently, “the theolo-gical truth is
discredited to the extent that the factual material is erroneous” (p.
335). So we observe that Fuller and Pinnock have agreed on all three of
the aforementioned these, but they have not ended up in the same place.
These two empirical apologists do not see eye-to-eye with respect to
Scriptural inerrancy and authority.
What makes this divergence of conclusion so interesting to us today is
the additional fact that, in their differing conclusions about
scriptural inerrancy. Fuller and Pinnock make decided
counter-accusations that the other writer is really less than true to
the radical demand of inductivism. Each man considers himself to be the
genuine champion of inductive empiricism in the attempt to relate faith
to history. Says Fuller, “I would argue that really, after all, you are
on Van Til’s side, not on Warfield’s” (p. 331): “there is a part of you
that wants to be inductive, to let critical thinking prevail. But you
can’t go all the way” (p. 332). Fuller challenges Pinnock with these
words: “Are you willing to be as consistently inductive as he [Warfield]
was?” (p. 332), and after mentioning resistance to the thunderous veto
against induction in Pinnock’s book on Biblical Revelation,
Fuller asks, “Are you willing to go all the way in resisting this veto?”
(p. 333). Thus Fuller thinks that Pinnock has arrived at his viewpoint
on scriptural inerrancy by a manner inconsistent with inductivism.
Nevertheless, and on the other hand, Pinnock feels that it is, rather,
Fuller who has not been faithful to the inductive epistemology we have
just outlined. He declares: “Fuller is less empirical at this point than
Warfield and I, because if he were more careful in his induction, he
would see at once that the dichotomy he has proposed [between revelation
and non-revelational statements in Scripture] is untenable in the light
of what he calls ‘the doctrinal verses’” (p. 334). Indeed, Pinnock says
that Fuller’s view of inerrancy would “make it relative to some dubious
a priori standard, inaccurately derived from the doctrinal
verses” (p. 334). Pinnock concludes that Fuller “is less than fully
consistent in the way he relates faith and history . . . . Most of the
material which in his view would belong to the ‘revelational’ category
lies outside the reach of science and history, safe from their critical
control” (p. 334)—even though in reality the theological and factual
material “are so inextricably united in the text” (p. 335). And so
there we have the counter-allegations. Pinnock feels that Fuller is not
consistently inductive; Fuller says the converse is true.
Let us now explore and respond to the three Fuller-Pinnock theses
seriatim, aiming to draw out of this telling interchange principles
and insights that can give us basic guidance in such theological and
apologetical issues as center on the inerrancy of Scripture.
As to Thesis I, we must rather flatfootedly challenge its accuracy.
Both Fuller and Pinnock have counterfeited the presuppositional outlook
by aligning it with fideistic deductivism over against empirical and
inductive methods. A perusal of Van Til’s many publications is
sufficient to falsify this preconceived misrepresentation. For instance:
The greater the amount of detailed study and the more carefully such
study is undertaken, the more truly Christian will the method be. It is
important to bring out this point in order to help remove the common
misunderstanding that Christianity is opposed to factual
investigation.2
What shall be the attitude of the orthodox believer with respect to
this? Shall he be an obscurantist and hold to the doctrine of
authority of the Scripture though he knows it can empirically be shown
to be contrary to the facts of Scripture themselves? It goes without
saying that such should not be his attitude.3
The Christian position is certainly not opposed to experimentation
and observation . . . . It is quite commonly held that we cannot
accept anything that is not the result of a sound scientific
methodology. With this we can as Christians heartily agree.4
Surely the Christian, who believes in the doctrine of creation, cannot
share the Greek depreciation of the things of the sense world.
Depreciation of that sense world inevitably leads to a depreciation of
many of the important facts of historic Christianity which took place in
the sense world. The Bible does not rule out every form of empiricism
any more than it rules out every form of a priori reasoning.5
Now this approach from the bottom to the top, from the particular to the
general, is the inductive aspect of the method of implication. .
. . All agree that the immediate starting point must be that of our
everyday experience and the “facts” that are most close at hand.
. . . But the favorite charge against us is that we are . . . employing
the deductive method. Our opponents are thoughtlessly identifying our
method with the Greek method of deduction . . . . We need only to
observe that a priori reasoning, and a posteriori
reasoning, are equally anti-Christian, if these terms are understood in
their historical sense . . . . On the other hand, if God is recognized
as the only and the final explanation of any and every fact, neither the
inductive nor the deductive method can any longer be used to the
exclusion of the other.6
Every bit of historical investigation, whether it be in the directly
biblical field, archaeology, or in general history is bound to confirm
the truth of the claims of the Christian position. . . . A really
fruitful historical apologetic argues that every fact is and
must be such as proves the truth of the Christian theistic position.7
Far from being indifferent or antagonistic to inductive and empirical
science, Van Til has devoted much of his scholarly labors to the
constructive analysis of the philosophy of science. He has always
insisted that Christians relate their faith positively to science and
history, finding unequivocal evidence, indeed a definite demand, for
distinctively Christian conclusions in all inductive study of the facts
themselves.8
On the other hand he has persistently
and apologetically attacked unbelieving philosophies on the telling
ground that they render inductive science impossible.9
Consequently it is not at all surprising that Van Til has been unfailing
in his opposition to fideism, apologetic mysticism, and the notion that
belief cannot argue with unbelief. He is highly critical of those who
saw
no way of harmonizing the facts of the Christian religion with the
“constitution and course of nature. They gave up the idea of a
philosophical apologetics entirely, This fideistic attitude comes
to expression frequently in the statement of the experiential proof of
the truth of Christianity. People will say that they know that they are
saved and that Christianity is true no matter what the philosophical or
scientific evidence for or against it may be. . . . But in thus seeking
to withdraw from all intellectual argument, such fideists have virtually
admitted the validity of the argument against Christianity. They will
have to believe in their hearts what they have virtually allowed to be
intellectually indefensible.10
It might seem that there can be no argument between them. It
might seem that the orthodox view of authority is to be spread only by
testimony and by prayer, not by argument. But this would militate
directly against the very foundation of all Christian revelation,
namely, to the effect that all things in the universe are nothing if not
revelational of God. Christianity must claim that it alone is rational.
. . . An evangelical, that is a virtually Arminian theology, makes
concessions to the principle that controls a “theology of experience”
. . . and to the precise extent that evangelicalism makes these
concessions in its theology, does it weaken its own defense of the
infallible Bible.11
These pro-inductive or pro-empirical attitudes of Van Til are
conspicuous: To miss them one would need to approach his writings, if at
all, with far-reaching and vision-distorting preconceived notions. We
cannot but conclude that the Fuller-Pinnock Thesis I is simply mistaken.
Presuppositionalism is not opposed to empirical procedures or inductive
investigation, nor does it discourage them.
What Van Til and the presuppositionalists do say—and this point
will be crucial to the understanding subsequent parts of this paper—is
that not only must one utilize inductive empiricism but he must press
beyond this and examine the foundations of science and inductive method.
That is, we must not stop short in our philosophical analysis but
rather inquire into the presuppositions necessary for an intelligent and
justified use of empiricism. As Van Til puts it: “I would not talk
endlessly about facts and more facts without ever challenging the
non-believer’s philosophy of fact.”12
Van Til makes it clear that presuppositionalism does not “disparage the
usefulness of arguments for the corroboration of the Scripture that came
from archaeology. It is only to say that such corroboration is not of
independent power.”13
The apologist “must challenge the
legitimacy of the scientific method as based upon an assumed metaphysic
of chance.”14
So hopeless and senseless a picture must be drawn of the natural man’s
methodology, based as it is upon the assumption that time or chance is
ultimate. On his assumption his own rationality is a product of chance.
. . . Our argument as over against his would be that the existence of
the God of Christian theism and the conception of his counsel as
controlling all things in the universe is the only presupposition which
can account for the uniformity of nature which the scientist needs.15
Christianity does not thus need to take shelter under the roof of “known
facts.” It rather offers itself as a roof to facts if they would be
known. Christianity does not need to take shelter under the roof of a
scientific method independent of itself. It rather offers itself as a
roof to methods that would be scientific.16
The point is that the “facts of experience” must actually be interpreted
in terms of Scripture if they are to be intelligible at all.17
With this background we can better understand the general thrust of
presuppositional method in apologetics:
To argue by presupposition is to indicate what are the epistemological
and metaphysical principles that underlie and control one’s method.18
The Reformed method of argument is first constructive. It presents the
biblical view positively by showing that all factual and logical
discussions by men take place by virtue of the world’s being what God in
Christ says it is. It then proceeds negatively to show that unless all
facts and all logical relations be seen in the light of the Christian
framework, all human interpretation fails instantly. . . . What we shall
have to do then is to try to reduce our opponent’s position to an
absurdity. Nothing less will do. . . . We must point out to them that
univocal reasoning itself leads to self-contradiction, not only from a
theistic point of view, but from a non-theistic point of view as well.
It is this that we ought to mean when we say that we must meet our
enemy on their own ground. It is this that we ought to mean when we say
that we reason from the impossibility of the contrary.19
Having challenged Thesis I and having briefly explained the nature of
presuppositional reasoning with respect to inductivism, we can now
proceed to correct the dubious allegation of Thesis II that inductive
empiricism is independent of presuppositions, allowing neutral and
critical thinking (which assents to nothing except upon evidential
strength) to control the knowing process completely from beginning to
end. We already have had occasion above to note that inductive
empiricism is intelligible and justified within the context of certain
metaphysical and epistemological precommitments or basic assumptions.
Thus we have already challenged the alleged neutrality of the
inductivist. As hard as Fuller and Pinnock may try to hide it from
themselves, the stubborn fact remains that, for them both, critical and
neutral reasoning does not prevail and reign supreme throughout their
knowing processes. They have their covert presuppositions. I would
like to illustrate this observation by means of a series of
considerations that can be conveniently summarized under three headings.
I.
Unargued Philosophical Baggage
In discussing issues under this rubric, my aim is to point out that
inductive empiricism is not a philosophically neutral or unproblematic
tool by which evangelical apologetics may proceed.
(1) Inductivists are not as thoroughly inductive as they think, for the
reflexive theoretical statements of the inductivists about their
procedure and practice, its merits and criteria are not inductive or
empirical in nature. Hence extra-inductive commitments are immediately
discernible.
(2) Should the Christian inductivist assume universal uniformity or
regularity in nature and history so as to provide the metaphysical
precondition of his inductivism—but thereby exclude miracles? Or should
he begin by allowing miracles (which, by the way, is a supra-empirical
commitment to the range of the possible)—but thereby dismiss the
reliability and uniformity needed for inductive knowledge?
(3) What sort of rational basis or evidence does the inductivist have
for his implied belief in natural uniformity (e.g., against Hume’s
skeptical attack on induction)? Such issues as the nature of induction,
its preconditions, and the basis for a commitment to the uniformity of
nature are rarely discussed by evangelicals. But this is at the heart
of inductive epistemology, and it is still central in philosophical
disputes today.
(4) Of course, the nature of evidence that should be given for the
theory of induction will be determined by the nature of that theory’s
objects and methods. So we can ask, “What kind of entity is spoken of
in the inductivist’s self-referential theoretical statements?” Once
this is answered, if ever, we must go on and ask, “What is a
proposition, an idea, a belief, a standard of evidence, a directive, a
rule, etc?” For instance, are they properties, relations, substances,
individuals, dispositions, functions, modes of cognition, or what?
These are all categorically different things in metaphysics, and
therefore without dealing with the demands of such questions are
incomplete, inadequate, inconsistent and self-delusory apologetic may
inevitably be the outcome.
(5) The foregoing questions, along with the upcoming one, all indicate
that one’s metaphysic must be formulated correctly at the outset if
epistemological headaches are to be avoided later. For instance,
cognizance is a familiar kind of fact to epistemologists (e.g., “I see
x,” “I know p,” being conscious of, believing,
remembering, etc.), and cognizance is just as much a reality as what
scientists study directly. Thus we ask how cognizance is to be
categorized, so as to avoid category mistakes about it. The common
tendency is to hold that cognizance is a relation between a subject and
an object. But this leads to the obvious epistemological problem of
seeking an object of cognition. As a relation, cognizance would require
something that cognizance is about, for relations require the existence
of their terms. But, then, to what is a belief related in cases of past
belief? What is its object? More generally, what is the nature of the
objects of cognition, especially in cases of error and illusion?
(6) So to be intelligible and reasonable an inductive epistemology
cannot be understood, accepted, and followed with an ontology. With
reference to empiricism and metaphysics, it should be noted that no
valid argument has ever been given for the statement, “Only perceivable
individuals exist.” And indeed such a proposition is highly suspect in
light of the importance of abstract entities. Without abstract entities
(a) there would be no sense in talking about validity and invalidity in
argument; (b) there could be no induction, for nothing would be
repeatable (i.e., the future would have to be different from the past);
and (c) there would be no objective knowledge, since we could not
transcend the individuality of experience and gain a community of
knowledge (i.e., we could not experience the same thing). So, then,
abstract entities seem necessary for inductive epistemology, but of
course abstract entities are precisely the kind of things we cannot and
do not experience empirically and inductively.
(7) Given Fuller’s and Pinnock’s notion of inductive empiricism where
neutral, critical thinking controls the knowing process from beginning
to end, their alleged epistemology commits them to the view that all
synthetic and meaningful ideas derive from experience, that all
non-demonstrative (inductive) reasoning is empirical generalization from
observations, and that empirical knowledge is founded upon a set of
independently intelligible and separately credited observation claims.
The credibility of this outlook is subject to serious challenge:
(a) If held consistently from beginning to end, it would preclude the
use of certain ideas necessary to inductive science (e.g., normal
observer, location, etc.) that cannot be empirically specified in the
above way; and
(b) it would involve saying that what one directly experiences are his
own sensations and thoughts, and, therefore, since words derive their
meaning from observation and stipulation, some theory of private
language must be affirmed. Against this, however, such a theory is not
intelligible; language calls for a consistent application of words, but
to speak of a privately consistent application is meaningless since
there is no possible way to tell independently (i.e., objectively or
publicly) that a word is in fact being used consistently (i.e., given
the same private sense now that it was given in the past). Fuller and
Pinnock must either show that they are not committed to the views
that lead to the above two problems and yet are consistently following
inductive empiricism from beginning to end, or they must present
refutations to these problems in a way that consistently follows
inductive empiricism from beginning to end. Whatever response they
choose, it will soon be clear that their inductive method is committed
to a great deal of philosophical fare that was not “critically” or
“neutrally” established. Moreover, the view that there are
independently intelligible and separately credited observation claims
should also be cross-examined and rejected in light of the following
considerations:
(c) observation claims derive their credibility from background
assumptions (e.g., what counts as a “fact,” and how facts are discerned,
is determined within a broader theoretical framework; every
observational claim takes one beyond his present direct
experience—instance, assuming normalcy of perception in the particular
instance, uniformity of category scheme, constancy of observational
subject, commonality of language, etc.);
(d) observation claims indeed derive their meaning within the network of
background assumptions (e.g., there are no purely ostensive words since
an observational term—“red”—will not retain a constant meaning through a
change of theory—e.g., from Aristotelian to quantum physics); and
(e) observations themselves are theory-infected, that is, are
interpretations of stimuli in light of assumptions, beliefs, categories,
and anticipations (e.g., the work of Gestalt psychology,
indicating the ambiguity of objects of perception, etc.). Again we have
compelling reason to doubt that inductive empiricists actually do or can
let critical and neutral thinking control the knowing process from
beginning to end; the very appeal to observation is governed by
presuppositions that transcend the particular observation itself. To
acquiesce to these considerations, Fuller and Pinnock would have to
retract or radically qualify their thorough inductivism. But on the
other hand if they wished to dispute these considerations, could they do
so on purely empirical and inductive grounds without engaging in
philosophical assumptions and reasoning?
(8) Given the inductivist’s commitment to empirical procedures, we can
press even harder philosophically and ask whether sense perception is
reliable, in light of
(a) the problem of illusion (since the non-veridical nature of an
illusion is not recognized while the illusion is experienced, how can
veridical perception ever be distinguished reliably from illusions?),
and
(b) the problem of perspectival variation (since various visual images I
receive from different perspectives on an object cannot reasonably be
attributed to the changing qualities of that object itself, perception
seems not to be telling me the truth about those objects).
(9) Space will not permit us to speak further about such problems as
(a) the traditional way of distinguishing inductive and deductive
arguments and how it undermines the use of probability,
(b) how to rate probability and explicate its nature in inductive study
(especially in cases of the testimony of historical writers), or
(c) how to explain the analytic/synthetic distinction that inductivism
assumes, and especially how to explain the distinction in a way that
does not commit us to such awkward and extra-empirical metaphysical
furniture as necessity or essences.
Suffice it to say that each of these issues presents a solid challenge
to the credibility of Fuller’s and Pinnock’s espousal of exhaustive
inductivism. How are they to delineate and delimit sharply their
“inductive” method or the “synthetic” area to which it is applied with
the calculus of “probability”?
(10) In the very nature of their historical discipline, Fuller and
Pinnock are not the presuppositionless inductivists that they
make themselves out to be. The historian studies not the direct
phenomena but the sources that report the past. The historian must
interpret his sources, attempting to reconstruct the past. He does not
simply accept the facts as a passive observer. He is faced with the
chore of cross-examining his sources (which cannot but be silent in
response), knowing what questions are appropriately addressed to the
various types of sources, knowing when he is pushing the sources too far
for desired information, etc. Moreover, the historian’s inquiry must be
directed toward a specific goal from its inception; he does not simply
string together anything and everything he learns about a certain period
or event, but rather is seeking particular kinds of answers to
particular questions, certain lines of evidence for various sorts of
hypotheses, different conceptions of relevance, etc.
History as a science is also inherently value-impregnated. The ordinary
language that historians use is quite a bit more than merely
descriptive. And this is only to be expected, since they cannot
properly reduce human history to the history of natural objects—to do so
would be to screen out that which is peculiar to humans: intentions,
desires, motives, morals, etc. In approaching the evidence the
historian is also forced to use a criterion of selectivity, and this
itself involves personal value judgments. Such selectivity enters right
into the historian’s attempt to find solutions, and not simply into his
choice of problems to study. In this selectivity the historian either
utilizes a notion of historical causation or a standard of historical
importance. In the former case his causal explanations are not
value-neutral, for he has to judge that certain conditions were relevant
as causes and some were not.
Furthermore, a causal analysis of human action and social history is
itself a matter of assigning responsibility (thus involving moral
judgment). If the historian follows out the idea of historical
causation in his selectivity, then he is faced with the selection
between competing models of “explanation” (i.e., shall he seek to render
covering laws as suggested by Hempel, non-deducible generalizations
[Gardner], joint-sufficiency conditions [Goudge], or necessary
conditions [Dray; Danto]?). On the other hand, if the historian’s
selectivity is guided by a standard of historical importance (e.g., what
is memorable, intrinsically valuable, etc.), then he is ipso facto
doing more than simple description of the past. Thus in all these
ways we see how strong the case is against the common conception of
objective, neutral historiography.
After a sober consideration of the ten issues we have briefly surveyed,
it ought to be quite clear that neutral and presuppositionless reasoning
does not and cannot have full control in Fuller’s or Pinnock’s
inductivism. The very use of that epistemology commits one to a great
deal of unargued philosophical baggage. By its use one wittingly or
unwittingly endorses certain crucial assumptions. And in connection
with a commitment to inductivism, one inescapably must face difficult
philosophical questions pertaining to epistemology and ontology,
questions that can be left unanswered only at the price of theoretical
arbitrariness and disrespect for the very justifying considerations that
inductivism demands for our every commitment—from beginning to end.
II.
Evident Precommitments
When we read the letters Fuller and Pinnock have exchanged, we see quite
obviously that each man is committed in advance to so conducting his
empirical studies that the teachings of Scripture will be vindicated.
Says Fuller, “I sincerely hope that as I continue my
historical-grammatical exegesis of Scripture, I shall find no error in
its teaching” (p. 332), for “if there is one error anywhere in what
Scripture intends to teach, then everything it intends to say is suspect
and we have not even one sure word from God” (p. 331). Likewise Pinnock
declares that he will not permit naturalistic presuppositions to control
his thought, lest he no longer speak as a Biblical supernaturalist (p.
333). Evan apart from having verified every particular statement of the
Scriptures, Pinnock generally indicates in advance that “the whole
graphē is God-breathed and fully trustworthy” (p. 334). Indeed he
does not want to dichotomize the Bible into factual and revelational
truths, lest the revelational material shrink “before the advance of the
latest critical charge” (p. 335).
Therefore it is manifest on the very surface of their letters that
Fuller and Pinnock are not after all neutral and without their
scholarly precommit-ments. The kind of thing we have just witnessed
them saying would, in a hostile atmosphere, be sufficient to indict and
convict them for failing to be impartial and requisitely objective (or
“open-minded”) in their approach to the Bible’s veracity. These two
writers simply need to be honest with themselves and recognize that,
because they are saved by God’s redeeming grace and have submitted in
faith and love to Jesus Christ, they are dedicated in advance to
protecting their Savior’s word from discredit. That, however, is not
presuppositionless, neutral inductivism.
III.
Scriptural Declarations
Finally, we know that presuppositionless impartiality and neutral
reasoning are impossible and undesirable because God’s word teaches that
(1) all men know God, even if suppressing the truth (Rom. 1);
(2) there are two basic philosophic and presuppositional outlooks—one
after worldly tradition, the other after Christ (Col. 2);
(3) thus there is a knowledge falsely so-called that errs according to
the faith (I Tim. 6) and a genuine knowledge based on repentant faith (2
Tim. 2); consequently,
(4) some men (unbelievers) are “enemies in their minds” (Rom. 8) while
others (believers) are “renewed in Knowledge” (Col. 3), and
characteristic of these two mindsets is the fact that the former cannot
be subject to God’s Word (Rom. 8) but sees it as utter foolishness (1
Cor. 1), while the latter seeks to bring every thought captive in the
obedience of Christ (2 Cor. 10) in whom is found all the treasures of
wisdom and knowledge (Colossians 2)) because the fear of the Lord is the
beginning of knowledge (Proverbs 1). This mindset submits to Christ’s
word, just as the wise man builds his house upon a rock (Matt. 7); and
it views the alleged foolishness of preaching as indeed the wisdom and
power of God (1 Cor. 1). Presuppositionless neutrality is both
impossible (epistemologically) and disobedient (morally); Christ says
that a man is either with him or against him (Matt.
12:30), for “no man can serve two masters” (6:24). Our every
thought (even apologetical reasoning about inerrancy) must be made
captive to Christ’s all-encompassing Lordship (2 Cor. 10:5; 1 Pet. 3:15;
Matt. 22:37).
Therefore in response to the Fuller-Pinnock Thesis II we must say: As a
matter of fact, no man is without presuppositional commitments. As a
matter of philosophical necessity, no man can be without
presuppositional commitments. And as a matter of Scriptural teaching,
no man ought to be without presuppositional commitments.
We come, then, finally to Thesis III—that the question of Biblical
inerrancy must be settled inductively, not presuppositionally.
Is this doctrine about Scripture to be formulated on the basis of
what Scripture says about itself (and thus presuppositionally), or
rather do we take the phenomenological approach of handling the various
Biblical phenomena and claims (among which are the problem passages)
inductively with a view to settling the question of Scripture’s
inerrancy only in light of the discovered facts of empirical and
historical study?
Another way of laying out the different approaches here is to point out
that the Bible makes a large set of indicative claims (e.g., that David
was once king of Israel, that Jesus was born at Bethlehem, that Jesus
was divine, that salvation is only through his shed blood, etc.).
Needless to say, this set is very large indeed. Now among this set of
Scriptural assertions is to be found certain self-referential statements
about the set as a whole (e.g., “Thy word is truth,” “The Scripture
cannot be broken,” “All Scripture is inspired by God,” etc.). The
question then arises: Does one decide the question of Scriptural
inerrancy by an inductive examination of the discursive and individual
assertions of Scripture one by one, or by settling on the truth of these
special self-referential assertions and then letting them control our
approach to all the rest?
It is clear to anyone who will reflect seriously on this question that
the statements of Scripture abut Scripture are primary and must
determine our attitude toward all the rest. Why is this so?
(1) An exhaustive inductive examination cannot be carried out in
practice. The doctrinal profession of the Bible’s absolute truthfulness
such that alleged errors or discrepancies are only apparent could take
inductive scholarship as its sole or central foundation only if each and
every assertion had been examined and publicly vindicated (the
requirements of which stagger the imagination), but even then all of the
external inductive evidence cannot be presumed to be in (future
discoveries and refinements of evidence might pervasively change the
complexion of the pool of relevant data)—in which case the theologian
could legitimately (i.e., by cautious, circumspect, presuppositionless,
inductive war-rant) profess only a provisional and qualified inerrancy,
even if he had successfully completed the enormous task of inductively
confirming all of the Bible’s numerous assertions.
(2) By their very character, many Scriptural assertions cannot be tested
inductively but must be accepted, if at all, on Scripture’s own
attestation (e.g., Christ’s interpretation of his person and work as
being divine and redemptive.20
We must not forget that the necessity of special revelation does not
arise as a shortcut for the intellectually ungifted who do not pursue
their inductive homework thoroughly and accurately, but rather stems
from the fact that there are divine truths that all men, especially as
fallen, could never discover on their own but that must be unveiled by
God to them (cf. Matt 16:17). Such revealed truths (e.g., that the
ascended Christ now makes continual intercession for us to the Father)
are not subject to our inductive examination and confirmation; they are
accepted on the authority of God speaking in the Scripture itself. And
yet they are just as much members of the set of Scriptural assertions
(and as such included in the range of the set-reference statements) as
are the apparently more mundane historical assertions (e.g., that Judas
of Galilee rose up after Theudas).
(3) As we have seen already, inductive study itself has crucial
presuppositions that cannot be accounted for except on a Biblical basis,
and therefore in a profound sense of inductive study is already
committed to the content of these self-referential statements of
Scripture.
We see, then, that the self-referential statements are and must be
primary in our approach to the nature of Scripture and the question of
its authority. The question of Biblical inerrancy must be resolved
presuppositionally. Central to evangelical Bibliology and apologetics is
the issue of inerrancy and inductivism, and yet we must see that the
latter is in no position to serve as the foundation for the former. If
intelligibility in our doctrinal affirmation of inerrancy depends on the
intelligibility of the presuppositionally pure inductive theory of
apologetics, then the doctrine has been scuttled for sure.
And so we can agree with Pinnock against Fuller. One cannot but let the
Bible speak for itself about its own nature and attributes, and
consequently one cannot choose to submit to Scriptural truths at some
points (e.g., Christ’s deity and redeeming work are beyond the
adjudication of empirical criticism) and reserve self-sufficient
critical authority elsewhere (e.g., historical data are accepted or
rejected on the strength of empirical examination). Fuller’s inductive
approach is epistemologically and theologically impossible. It is
double-minded.
On the other hand, we can agree with Fuller against Pinnock when he says
Pinnock has not really been thoroughly inductive, for Pinnock allows
certain Scriptural statements a privileged and controlling position—one
that is not subject to the radical demand to let critical thinking
prevail.
Before we are tempted to reply to this charge that nonetheless Pinnock
does take an inductive and evidential apologetical approach to these
self-referential statements of Scripture, let us hesitate and observe
that such a reply is hardly tenable.
(1) If Pinnock really took a thoroughly inductive approach to such
statements, that could only mean that he verified the set-reference
statement itself by inductively confirming every particular assertion
covered by it—that is, every claim that is within its range. This then
would collapse into the phenomenological approach we have just rejected.
It would be subject to its crucial defects, and Pinnock would be prey
to Fuller’s taunt that a part of him wants to be inductive but that he
cannot go all the way.
(2) Moreover, it must be observed that the very empirical apologetic
pursued by Pinnock in defense of the Bible’s divine credentials is of
necessity grounded in metaphysical and epistemological presuppositions
for which only the Bible can account. That is, he is intellectually
dependent on the Bible’s veracity even while examining the Bible’s
claims.
(3) Nor should it be thought that Pinnock can credibly work toward an
empirical confirmation of some of Scripture’s historical details
and then inductively infer that the other statements of Scripture
can also be accepted, for
(a) the argument would be thoroughly fallacious (just as if someone
argued that because some (even many) statements in the Koran, or
in Churchill’s The Gathering Storm, etc., are empirically
confirmed, we can infer that all of the statements in these
writings must be accepted as without error);
(b) the historical details may very well be veracious without the
theological interpretation of them being inductively substantiated
(e.g., that Paul was correct in historically asserting that Christ was
“born of a woman” is hardly warrant for saying that Paul was also
correct in soteriologically asserting that Christ “condemned sin in the
flesh”); and
(c) this approach would be subject to the same criticism as we have made
of Fuller (albeit in a slightly different way)—that is, the inductive
approach to inerrancy by an empirical apologist like Pinnock submits to
Scripture’s self-testimony at some places (e.g., the interpretation of
Christ’s person and work is absolutely inerrant) but relies on
self-sufficient critical reasoning elsewhere (e.g., the historical data
are provisionally inerrant to the extent of empirical confirmation or
infirmity). Pinnock operates inconsistently on two different and
incompatible epistemologies:
on the one hand the Bible’s assertions are endorsed as true, although
admitted as possibly untrue, only on the basis of a neutral and critical
evaluation of external evidence and independent reasoning (strictly
gauged to inductive and empirical credentials), but
on the other hand the Bible’s assertions are accepted as true without
qualification on its own sufficient authority (and in spite of apparent
empirical difficulties).
He double-mindedly defends a conception of Biblical authority in a way
that compromises that very authority by its methodological assumptions.
The question is this: what exercises control over out speculation,
evaluation, and conclusions—God’s revealed word in Scripture, or some
authority external to God’s revelation? Do empirical difficulties
render the Bible’s inerrancy only apparent, or does the Bible’s
inerrancy render empirical difficulties only apparent? Does critical
thinking reign supreme only over part of the Bible? The errors
of Fuller and Pinnock are epistemological and theological twins.
Significance and Conclusion
The reason it is important for us to consider and analyze this important
exchange on inerrancy between Pinnock and Fuller is simply that it
brings to the surface certain latent issues and inconsistencies in the
popular evangelical witness today. There is a basic intramural dispute
that must be resolved in our approach to inerrancy, and this resolution
is a necessary first step toward our apologetic reply to those who are
antagonistic to an evangelical understanding of Scripture and its
authority. Fuller correctly observes, “But we evangelicals have a basic
question we must settle before we can talk very coherently with those
farther afield” (p. 330).
That basic question is epistemological in nature—viz., whether we should
take an inductive or presuppositional approach to the nature and
authority of the Bible. We must conclude from our previous discussion
that Christ’s Lordship—even in the area of thought—cannot be treated
like a light switch, to be turned on and off at our own pleasure and
discretion. Christ
makes a radical demand on our thinking that we submit to his Word as
self-attesting. To do otherwise leads away from a recognition of his
divine person and saving work, for it leads away from an affirmation of
Scripture’s inerrancy. Moreover, it simultaneously leads away from the
intelligibility of all experience and every epistemic method. One must
begin with the testimony of Scripture to itself, rather than with the
allegedly neutral methods of inductivism. And this means acknowledging
the veracity of Scripture even when empirical evidence might appear to
contradict it (following in the steps of the father of the faithful,
Abraham: Rom. 4:16-21; Heb. 11:17-19). The classic inter-school
encounter between Pinnock and Fuller points beyond itself to the basic
and inescapable need for a presuppositional apologetic, rather than the
allegedly pure inductivism espoused by Pinnock and Fuller. Speaking of
such a presuppositional approach to the issue of inerrancy, J.I. Packer
said:
It is only unmanageable for apologetics if one’s apologetic method is
rationalistic in type, requiring one to have all the answers to the
problems in a particular area before one dare make positive assertions
in that area, even when those positive assertions would simply be
echoing God’s own, set forth in Scripture. But it might be worth asking
whether it is not perhaps a blessing to be warned off apologetics of
that kind.21
Notes
1
“Daniel Fuller and Clark Pinnock: On Revelation and Biblical Authority.”
Christian Scholars Review 2 (1973) 330-335; reprinted in JETS
[Journal of the Evangelical Theological Society] 16 (1973)
67-72.
2
C. Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, Vol. 2 of the
series “In Defense of Biblical Christianity” (den Dulk Christian
Foundation, 1932; reprinted 1969) 7. [The author added the emphasis, but
did not indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
3
C. Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge (New Jersey:
Presbyterian and Reformed, 1959) 35. [The author added the emphasis, but
did not indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
4
C. Van Til, Christian-Theistic Evidences (mimeographed syllabus,
Westminster Theological Seminary, 1961), 62, ii. [The author added the
emphasis, but did not indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
5
C. Van Til, An Introduction to Systematic Theology (mimeographed
syllabus, Westminster Theological Seminary, reprinted 1966) 45. [The
author added the emphasis, but did not indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
6
Survey, pp. 7, 120, 9, 10. [The author added the emphasis, but
did not indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
7
Theory, p. 293. [The author added the emphasis, but did not
indicate this alteration.—A.F.]
8
For example, Van Til has consistently criticized allegedly “Christian”
approaches to science which maintain either that the circle of
naturalistic interpretation vaguely points beyond itself to certain
religious truths (i.e., projection into theology or that the scientific
interpretation of the facts can also be supplemented with a religious
perspective (i.e., imposition of a theological dimension). E. g. see Van
Til’s articles “Bridgewater Treatises” and “Butler, Joseph,” The
Encyclopedia of Christianity (ed. G. G. Cohen: Marshallton, Delaware
National Foundation for Christian Education, 1968), 2, 178-179, 238-239,
and Van Til’s reviews of the Scientific Enterprise and Christian
Faith by M. A. Jeeves, WTJ 32 (May, 1970) 236-240; The
Philosophy of Physical Science by A. Eddington, WTJ 3
(November, 1940) 662; and The Logic of Belief by D. E. Trueblood,
WTJ 5 (November, 1942) 88-94.
9
E.g., see Van Til’s analysis of Dewey in his review of The Philosophy
of John Dewey, ed. P. A. Schilpp, WTJ 3 (November, 1940): “We
would humbly but firmly maintain that only Christianity makes sense and
philosophy as well as other forms of human experience intelligible” (p.
72). The same theme can be traced throughout Van Til’s many writings;
for instance, “I think that science is absolutely impossible on the
non-Christian principle” (The Defense of the Faith [Philadelphia:
Presbyterian and Reformed, 1995] 285) since it undermines the inductive
procedure (pp. 283-284). Speaking of the non-Christian’s method, Van Til
says: “Its most consistent application not merely leads away from
Christian theism but in leading away from Christian theism leads to the
destruction of reason and science as well” (p. 119).
10
Evidences, p. 37. [The author added the emphasis, but did not
indicate this alteration.—A.F.] Van Til’s clear opposition to fideism is
not sufficiently countenanced and credited by some fellow apologists
(e.g., N. Geisler, Christian Apologetics [Grand Rapids: Baker,
1976] 56 ff. In fact Van Til has made a very similar, but much earlier,
critique of fideism than Geisler [sic: that is, a critique very
similar to, but much earlier than, Geisler’s.—A. F.].
11
C. Van Til, “Introduction,” in B. B. Warfield, The Inspiration and
Authority of the Bible (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and Reformed,
1948) 36, 67.
12
The Defense of the Faith (1966) 258; also in Theory, p.
293.
13
“Introduction,” p. 37.
14
Evidences, p. 63.
15
Defense, pp. 119, 120.
16
Evidences, p. 56.
17
Theory, p. 26.
18
Defense, pp. 116, 117.
19
Survey, p. 225, 204, 205.
20
Lest it be thought that Christ’s interpretation, rather than being self-attestingly
established, is tested and vindicated by some informal logic such as “If
Jesus rose from the dead, then he is God and accordingly speaks the
truth at every point,” it should be commented that this very logic is
far from reflecting the unbiased, accepted and uniform conclusion or
thinking of the world of advanced scholarship!
That is, the logic of such an argument is itself derived from and
warranted by the Scriptures (if they are in fact properly interpreted as
teaching this line of reasoning), which means that Christ’s
interpretation is after all still based on Christ’s own word. That this
reasoning is subject to dispute is perhaps illustrated by considering
just three aspects of it:
(1) The inference “if resurrected, then divine” is hardly acceptable if
applied in a discriminating and special pleading fashion so as to avoid
concluding that Lazarus was also God;
(2) the committed secularist would almost certainly look upon such an
inference pattern as a manifestation of primitive, mythic,
God-of-the-gaps thinking and present an alternative inference pattern
congenial to naturalism (e.g., “If Jesus rose from the dead, then very
complex and sophisticated biological principles and factors surpassing
those presently recognized and utilized by scientists remain to be
discovered and rendered in natural formulas”); and
(3) one clearly begs many important questions, the unbelieving
philosopher will note, if he simply reasons that “if Jesus was God, he
always spoke the truth,” for this naively utilizes only one of many
competing conceptions of deity—e.g., the Greek gods were not unfailing
truth-tellers!
The evangelical apologist must finally realize that what should count as
an acceptable test for recognizing and acknowledging something as a
divine revelation can only be set forth and warranted by God
himself—which could only be done by revelation. That is, the criteria
for identifying revelation would themselves have to be revealed if they
were to be objectively trustworthy and properly accepted over against
the competing and mistaken options of man’s imagination. Divine
revelation must be self-attesting, for God alone is adequate to witness
to himself; cf. J. Murray. “The Attestation of Scripture,” The
Infallible Word (3rd rev. ed.; ed. P. Woodley: Philadelphia:
Presbyterian and Reformed, 1967 [1946]) 6, 10, 46-47.
21
J.I. Packer, “Hermeneutics and Biblical Authority,” Themelios
1/1, p. 12.
Greg L. Bahnsen page