From
Westminster Theological Journal
LVII (1995) 1-31. I have formatted text taken from
Covenant Media Foundation’s
website.
Dr. Bahnsen's 1978 Ph.D. dissertation (written at the
University of Southern California), of which this paper is a “synopsis”
(see note 54), was entitled, “A Conditional Resolution of the Apparent
Paradox of Self-Deception” (available
in several formats since March 3, 2011).
“. . . the non-Christian is self-deceived about God—that the one who
does not believe in God actually does believe in God. The cogency of
presuppositionalism is tied up with the intelligibility of this notion
of self-deception. . . .
“While the self-deceiver is aware of the truth of p or sees it as
evidenced . . . and while his belief that p is indicated by his behavior
. . . he will not give assent to p but induces in himself—by controlling
attention to the relevant evidence—an incompatible (and false) belief
that S does not believe p. Accordingly, the self-deceiver is not aware
that he holds incompatible beliefs; after all, he does not believe that
he believes that p, but believes of himself that he does not believe p,
thus avowing mistakenly and only that he does not believe p. . .
. Thus the self-deceiver is not personally aware that his professed and
cherished belief about himself (that he does not believe that p) is
false. He is not simply a liar. . . .
“The analysis of self-deception offered here not only is adequate to
account for mundane and well-known cases of self-deception, but more
importantly, it is adequate to explain Paul’s description in Romans 1 of
men who know (believe) that God exists and yet suppress that belief
unrighteously.”
Anthony Flood
September 1, 2009
The Crucial Concept of Self-Deception in Presuppositional Apologetics
Greg Bahnsen
That self-deception which is practiced by all unregenerate men according
to the Apostle Paul’s incisive description in Romans 1:18ff is at once
reli-giously momentous and yet philosophically enig-matic. It is also
one of the focal points in con-tinuing criticism of Cornelius Van Til’s
apologetic1 and, as such, invites analysis with a view to
supplementing and strengthening the saintly professor’s remarkable
contribution to the history of apologetics.2
Paul asserts that all men know God so inescapably and clearly from
natural revelation that they are left with no defense for their
unfaithful response to the truth about Him. In verses 19-20, Paul says
“what can be known about God is plain within them because God made it
plain to them. . . being clearly perceived from the created world, being
intellectually apprehended from the things that have been made. . . so
that they are without excuse.” Nevertheless, even as they are
categorically depicted as “knowing God” (v. 21), all men are portrayed
in their unright-eousness as “holding down the truth” (v. 18). They are
suppressing what God has already successfully shown them about Himself.
As a result of hiding the truth from themselves, unbelievers neither
glorify nor thank God, but instead become futile in their reasoning,
undiscerning in their darkened hearts, and foolish in the midst of their
professions of wisdom (vv. 21-22). According to God’s word through
Paul, then, unbelievers suppress what they very well know, confirming
what Jeremiah the prophet so aptly declared, “The heart is deceitful
above all things” (17:9).
The apologetical importance of such self-deception should be quite
evident. Throughout the history of apologetics we find that Romans 1
has been of guiding interest to Biblically oriented apologists, and
indeed the self-deceptive charac-ter of man as presented there has
itself been stressed periodically by scholars of Reformed persuasion.
However, no apologist has drawn more consistent attention to this
characteristic of the natural man or made it more pivotal for his system
of defending the Christian faith than has Dr. Van Til. It is an
indispensable concept in his epistemology, as one will see in
systematically studying Van Til’s writings or analyzing his
apolo-getical perspective. The point is not simply that references to
the unbeliever’s self-deception, as taught in Romans 1, are conspicuous
and common in Van Til’s books, but that this notion functions in such a
crucial manner in his argumentation that without it presuppositional
apologetics could be neither intellectually cogent nor personally
appropriate as a method of defending the faith. A short rehearsal of a
few basic points in Van Til’s apologetic shows why this is so.
In A Survey of Christian Epistemology Van Til claims that “there
can be no more fundamental question in epistemology than the question
whether or not facts can be known without reference to God . . . and so
whether or not God exists.”3 That is, a metaphysical issue
is the most fundamental question in epistemology. Van Til’s
apologetical argument for the metaphysical conclusion that God exists,
however, is in turn epistemological in character. The Christian defends
the faith “by claiming . . . he can explain . . . the amenability of
fact to logic and the necessity and usefulness of rationality itself in
terms of Scripture.”4 He could thus write: “it appears how
intimately one’s theory of being and one’s theory of method are
interrelated.”5 This mutual dependence of metaphysics and
epistemology has always been characteristic of Van Til’s apologetical
position.6
So then, far from being a species of “fideism,” as it is so often
misconstrued by writers like Mont-gomery, Geisler or Sproul,7
Van Til’s approach to the question of God’s existence offers, I believe,
the strongest form of proof and rational demon-stration—namely, a
“transcendental” form of argument. He writes, “Now the only argument
for an absolute God that holds water is a tran-scendental argument . . .
which seeks to discover what sort of foundations the house of human
knowledge must have, in order to be what it is.”8 To put it
briefly, using Van Til’s words, “we reason from the impossibility of the
contrary.”9
In The Defense of the Faith, Van Til explains that this is an
indirect method of proof, whereby the believer and the unbeliever
together think through the implications of each other’s most basic
assumptions so that the Christian may show the non-Christian how the
intelligibility of his experi-ence, the meaningfulness of logic, and the
possi-bility of science, proof or interpretation can be maintained only
on the basis of the Christian worldview (i.e., on the basis of Christian
theism taken as a unit, rather than piecemeal).
The method of reasoning by presup-position may be said to be indirect
rather than direct. The issue between believers and non-believers in
Chris-tian theism cannot be settled by a direct appeal to “facts” or
“laws” whose nature and significance is already agreed upon by both
parties to the debate. The question is rather as to what is the final
reference-point required to make the “facts” and “laws” intelligible . .
. . The Christian apologist must place himself upon the position of his
opponent, assuming the correctness of his method merely for argument’s
sake, in order to show him that on such a position the “facts” are not
facts and the “laws” are not laws. He must also ask the non-Christian
to place himself upon the Christian position for argument’s sake in
order that he may be shown that only upon such a basis do “facts” and
“laws” appear intelligible . . . . The method of presupposition
re-quires the presentation of Christian theism as a unit.10
Taking Christian theism “as the presupposition which alone makes the
acquisition of knowledge in any field intelligible,” the apologist must
conduct a critical analysis of the unbeliever’s epistemological method
“with the purpose of showing that its most consistent application not
merely leads away from Christian theism, but in leading away from
Christian theism, leads to the destruction of reason and science as
well.”11 This point, which Van Til drives home persistently
throughout his large corpus of publications, is expressed with these
words in A Christian Theory of Knowledge: “Christianity can be
shown to be, not ‘just as good as’ or even ‘better than’ the
non-Christian position, but the only position that does not make
nonsense of human experience.”12 Because the unbeliever’s
commitment to random eventuation in history (i.e., a metaphysic of
“chance”) renders proof impossible, predication unintelligible, and a
rational/irrational dialectic unavoidable, Van Til claims repeatedly in
his writings that the truth of Christianity is epistemologically
indispensable.13
It is in this sense, then, that the pre-suppositional argument for the
existence of God and the truth of the Bible is “from the impossibility
of the contrary.”
The argument for the existence of God and for the truth of Christianity
is objectively valid . . . . The argument is absolutely sound.
Christianity is the only reasonable position to hold. It is not merely
as reasonable as other positions, or a bit more reasonable than other
positions; it alone is the natural and reasonable position for man to
take.14
“Christianity is proved as being the very foundation of the idea of
proof itself.”15 Admittedly those are rather strong claims,
and as I see it, they constitute the most rigorous apologetical program
of intellectual defense being advanced in our time. It is, moreover,
just in the all-or-nothing epistemo-logical boldness of
presuppositionalism that Van Til finds the distinctiveness of Reformed
apologetics—what he calls “the basic difference” between it and other
types of defense.
The Romanist-evangelical type of apologetics assumes that man can first
know much about himself in the universe and afterward ask whether God
exists and Christianity is true. The Reformed apologist assumes that
nothing can be known by man about himself or the universe unless God
exists and Christianity is true.16
Ironically, those who are uneasy with the pre-suppositional approach to
apologetics include not only those who think that it, being fideistic,
does not prove enough, but also those who (reading the claims that we
have just cited) say that it proves far too much! The charge is made,
you see, that presuppositionalism implies that unbelievers can know
nothing at all and can make no contribution to science and scholarship
since belief in God is epistemologically indispensable according to the
presuppositionalist. And it is right here, right at this crucial point
in the analysis, that the notion of self-deception by the unbeliever
enters the picture.
Van Til always taught that “the absolute con-trast between the Christian
and the non-Christian in the field of knowledge is said to be that of
principle.” He draws “the distinction . . . between the regenerated
consciousness which in principle sees the truth and the unregenerate
consciousness which by its principle cannot see the truth.”17
If unbelievers were totally true to their espoused assumptions, then
knowledge would indeed be impossible for them since they deny God.
However the Christian can challenge the non-Christian approach to
interpreting human experience “only if he shows the non-Christian that
even in his virtual negation of God, he is still really presupposing
God.”18 He puts the point succinctly in saying: “Anti-theism
presupposes theism.”19 The intel-lectual achievements of the
unbeliever, as ex-plained in The Defense of the Faith, are
possible only because he is “borrowing, without recognizing it, the
Christian ideas of creation and provi-dence.”20 The
non-Christian thus “makes positive contributions to science in spite of
his princi-ples”21—because he is inconsistent. Van Til
replies directly to the charge that we are now considering with these
words:
The first objection that suggests itself may be expressed in the
rhetorical question “Do you mean to assert that non-Christians do not
discover truth by the methods they employ?” The reply is that we mean
nothing so absurd as that. The implication of the method here advocated
is simply that non-Christians are never able and therefore never do
employ their own method consistently . . . . The best and only possible
proof for the existence of such a God is that his existence is required
for the uniformity of nature and for the coherence of all things in the
world . . . . Thus there is absolutely certain proof for the existence
of God and the truth of Christian theism. Even non-Christians
presuppose its truth while they verbally reject it. They need to
presuppose the truth of Christian theism in order to account for their
own accomplishments.22
The sense of deity discussed by Calvin on the basis of Paul’s doctrine
in Romans 1 provides Van Til not only with an apologetical point of
contact, but also with an account of how those who disclaim any belief
in God can know much about most subjects.23
The knowledge of God which every man has as the image of God and as
surrounded by God’s clear revelation assures us, then, that all men are
in contact with the truth.24 Not even sin in its most
devastating expressions can remove this know-ledge, for Van Til says
“sin would not be sin except for this ineradicable knowledge of God.”25
It is this knowledge of God, of which Paul speaks in Romans 1, that Van
Til identifies as the knowledge which all men have in common, contending
that such common knowledge is the guarantee that every man can
contribute to the progress of science, and that some measure of unity in
that task can exist between believers and unbelievers.26
Because he is convinced that self-conscious-ness presupposes
God-consciousness,27 the pre-suppositionalist can assert
then, in the most im-portant sense, “There are no atheists.”28
Van Til clearly relies very heavily on Paul in making such a surprising
claim.
The apostle Paul speaks of the natural man as actually possessing the
knowledge of God (Rom. 1:19-21). The greatness of his sin lies precisely
in the fact that “when they knew God, they glorified him not as God.”
No man can escape knowing God. It is indelibly involved in his
awareness of anything whatsoever . . . . We have at once to add Paul’s
further instruction to the effect that all men, due to the sin within
them, always and in all relationships seek to “suppress” this knowledge
of God (Rom. 1:18) . . . . Deep down in his mind every man knows that he
is the creature of God and responsible to God. Every man, at bottom,
knows that he is a covenant breaker. But every man acts and talks as
though this were not so. It is the one point that cannot bear
mentioning in his presence.29
Van Til speaks of the unbeliever sinning against his “better
knowledge”—that “it is of the greatest possible importance” to
acknowledge that man knows God in some “original sense.”30
Now then, just because knowledge is a category of belief (viz.,
justified true belief), and because it can reduce unnecessary
philosophical complica-tions throughout this discussion, we could just
as well speak of the unbeliever’s suppressed belief about God as we
could speak of his suppressed knowledge of God. In fact, Van Til makes
his point in just that way also in his writings.
To be sure, all men have faith. Unbelievers have faith as well as
believers. But that is due to the fact that they too are creatures of
God. Faith therefore always has content. It is against the content of
faith as belief in God that man has become an unbeliever. As such he
tries to suppress the content of his original faith . . . . And thus
there is no foundation for man’s knowledge of himself or of the world at
all . . . . When this faith turns into unbelief this unbelief cannot
succeed in suppres-sing fully the original faith in God. Man as man is
inherently and inescapably a believer in God. Thus he can contribute to
true knowledge in the universe.31
Our brief rehearsal of presuppositional apolo-getics has brought us step
by step to the realization that a crucial component in Van Til’s
perspective, one that is necessarily contained in any credible account
of its functioning, is the conviction that the non-Christian is
self-deceived about God—that the one who does not believe in God
actually does believe in God. The cogency of presuppositionalism is
tied up with the intelligibility of this notion of self-deception. If
we do not find our point of contact with the unbeliever in his
suppressed knowledge of God and reason with him in such a way as to
“distinguish carefully between the natural man’s own conception of
himself and the Biblical conception of him”—that is, if we do not
proceed on the firm premise that the unbeliever is engaged in
self-deception of the most significant religious kind—then, according to
Van Til, we “cannot challenge his most basic epistemological assumption”
that his reasoning can indeed be autonomous. And immediately Van Til
adds, “on this everything hinges.”32
The concept of self-deception is critical to Van Til’s
presuppositionalism. Everything hangs on it, according to him. If
there should be something suspect or muddled about the notion of self-decep-tion
here, then the entire presuppositional system of thought is suspect and
unacceptable as well. Its key argumentative thrust relies completely on
the truth of the claim that unbelievers are suppressing what they
believe about God the Creator. That is why I stated at the beginning
that the self-deception as depicted in Romans 1 is religiously momentous
and also why the unbeliever’s self-deception is a pivotal notion—a
sine qua non truth—for the presuppositional method of de-fending the
faith.
However, as I also wrote at the outset of this essay in reference to
Romans 1, the notion of self-deception is philosophically enigmatic. It
is more than just a bit odd, is it not, to say that someone believes
what he does not believe! Indeed, it sounds downright
self-contradictory. At just the crucial point where the
presuppositionalist must make reference to clear and compelling
considerations in order to give a justifying and credible account of the
very heart of this apologetical method, he seems to take an unsure step
into philosophical perplexity. It hardly seems to the critics of
presuppositionalism that its account of itself explains the unclear in
terms of the clear. It appears rather to move from the unclear to the
even more unclear. For now the obvious question, if not challenge, will
arise: what could it mean for an unbeliever to simultaneously be
a believer? Is the notion of self-deception at all coherent?
The quite enigmatic character of his conception of the unbeliever as
self-deceived is confessed very plainly in Van Til’s writings, where he
admits that the problem of the unbeliever’s knowledge “has always been a
difficult point . . ., often the one great source of confusion on the
question of faith and its relation to reason.”33 Van Til
insists that we must do justice to the twin facts that every unbeliever
knows God, and yet, that the natural man does not know God. If we do
not stress these two points, following Romanist and Arminian apologists,
then we will necessarily allow for a compromising apologetic.34
Van Til was aware of the counter charge that was likely to be made.
It is ambiguous or meaningless, says the Arminian, to talk about the
natural man as knowing God and yet not truly knowing God. Knowing is
knowing. A man either knows or he does not know. He may know less or
more, but if he does not “truly” know, he knows not at all . . . . In
reply to this the Calvinist insists that . . . the natural man does not
know God. But to be thus without knowledge, without living, loving,
true knowledge of God, he must be one who knows God in the sense of
having the sense of deity (Romans 1).35
As we can see, Van Til was appropriately sensitive to the charge of
self-contradiction. Accordingly he wanted to draw some kind of
distinction which would indicate that he, with Paul, was not taking away
with one assertion what he gives in another. Thus he qualified his
statements. “Non-Christians know after a fashion, as Paul tells us in
Romans.”36 Elsewhere he writes that “there is a sense in
which all men have faith and all men know God. All contribute to
science.”37 Therefore he taught “there are two senses to the
word ‘knowledge’ used in Scripture.”38
A common way in which Van Til denominates those two senses, and the
difference between them, is by saying that unbelievers know God but “not
according to the truth,” or they do not “truly” know him, or they do not
have “true knowledge.”39 How is this to be construed?
Unbelievers presuppose (and hence believe) the truth of God and of
Christianity “while they verbally reject it.” The non-Christian “acts
and talks as though this were not so,” for he cannot bear the mentioning
of his knowledge of God.40 Why not? Van Til says all
sinners “have an ax to grind and do not want to keep God in remembrance.
They keep under the knowledge of God that is within them. That is they
try as best they can to keep under this knowledge for fear they should
look into the face of their judge.”41 Being troubled in
conscience, the unbeliever must make an effort “to hide the facts from
himself,” somewhat like a cancer victim who, in distress, keeps the
awareness of the truth at a distance from himself.42 Some
students of presup-positionalism have made, I think, the hasty error of
conceiving of this situation as a simple matter of lying. The
unbeliever, it is thought, knows God, but simply says that he does not
know God. However, Van Til did not take this artificial and simplistic
route. He recognized that the unbeliever’s situation is
epistemologically strange and hard to describe accurately (unlike the
lying scenario). On the one hand, Van Til portrayed the unbeliever as
holding this knowledge of God “subconsciously.” The non-Christian is
said to borrow Christian ideas “without recognizing it.”43
“He knows deep down in his heart” or “deep down in his mind,”44
so that the natural man’s knowledge of God is taken as “beneath the
threshold of his working conscious-ness.”45 And yet on the
other hand Van Til wanted to contend unequivocally for the sinful guilt
of men who suppress the knowledge of God. Thus they are also portrayed
by him as somehow conscious of what they are doing. Knowing that it
cannot successfully be done, says Van Til, the unbeliever pursues the
impossible dream of moral and epistemological autonomy, seeking to
suppress what he knows about God.46 Van Til writes, “He
knows he is a ‘liar’ all the time,”47 and accordingly his
denying of the truth is a self-conscious act. And yet in saying this,
Van Til immediately felt the need to place a qualification on his claim.
Notice that the word ‘liar’ in the preceding quotation is placed
conspicuously in quotes. Van Til wants to say it with some measure of
reservation. Elsewhere he explained that the unbeliever’s hostility is
not “wholly self-conscious.”48 To his qualitative
distinc-tion (knowledge/true knowledge), and to his spatial distinction
(knowing/knowing deep down), he now adds a quantitative distinction
(wholly self-conscious/partially self-conscious).
Again it must be borne in mind that when we say that fallen man knows
God and suppresses that knowledge so that he, as it were, sins self-con-sciously,
this too needs qualification. Taken as a generality and in view of the
fact that all men were repre-sented in Adam at the beginning of history,
we must say that men sin against better knowledge and also
self-consciously. But this is not to deny that when men are said to be
without God in the world they are ignorant . . . . There is therefore a
gradation of those who sin more and those who sin less,
self-conscious-ly.49
One way or another, however, Van Til teaches that the natural man is
“ethically responsible” for his suppressing of the truth.50
He states that “the Scriptures continue to hold man responsible for his
blindness,”51 and he calls the result of the unbe-liever’s
self-deceptive effort “culpable ignor-ance.”52 The reason
for his failure to recognize God as he should “lies exclusively in
himself,” says Van Til; it is nothing less than “willful transgres-sion”
which accounts for his refusal.53 So again, Van Til has
indicated how awkward it is to speak of the unbeliever as self-deceived.
On the one hand, the unregenerate’s knowledge is considered
sub-conscious, and he does not recognize his utilizing of it. And yet
on the other hand, the unregenerate is portrayed as actively seeking to
suppress it, and in some measure he consciously and willfully works to
hide it from himself. Van Til runs his reader from pole to pole. On
the one hand he does not want to say that the unbeliever is a bare liar,
and yet on the other hand he does want to say that the unbeliever is
fully culpable, just like any liar would be.
Given this short review of Van Til’s discussion of the apologetical
situation, we have learned (1) that a recognition of the unbeliever’s
self-decep-tion is indispensable to presuppositional apolo-getics, and
yet (2) that its recognition is fraught with obscurity. As long as the
notion of self-deception appears uncertain, awkward, or unclear, the
cogency of the presuppositional method will remain in the balance. We
must say in conformity to Romans 1 that in some sense the non-Christian
knows and does not know God. In some sense, he believes, but
disbelieves in God. In some sense, he is unconscious of suppressing the
truth and still responsibly conscious of doing so. So then, what might
prove especially beneficial would be for us to give some sense to these
apparent paradoxes. If we can do so, the philosophy of presuppositional-ism
will be noticeably advanced and more readily presentable to struggling
defenders of the faith who need it so desperately.
An Enigmatic Yet Familiar Notion
In working toward a solution to the problem of self-deception, we
should pause at the outset to observe that while Paul’s (and Van Til’s)
use of that concept may be perplexing, the concept itself has certainly
not been unfamiliar. Portraying men as self-deceived has been a virtual
commonplace in Western literature, and thus the apparently paradoxical
nature of the concept cannot be thought to be a uniquely religious
matter.
Popular, cynical platitudes about man’s procli-vity to self-deception
have been published contin-ually by men from Demosthenes to Benjamin
Fran-klin, who once quipped, “who has deceived thee so often as
thyself?” The Puritan preacher, Daniel Dyke, wrote a four-hundred page
treatise pub-lished in 1617, entitled The Mystery of Selfe-De-ceiving.
A century later, the Anglican apologist, Bishop Butler, included his
famous sermon “Upon Self-Deceit” in a published collection of his
sermons. In it he correctly recognized, “A man may be entirely
possessed of this unfairness of mind, without having the least
speculative notion what the thing is.”55 It has been common
to make mention of self-deception, even though it may be uncommonly
difficult to explain philosophically just what it is.
Yet even among philosophers the notion has been common stock. From what
was said about it by Plato, Rousseau, Goethe, Schopenhauer, and
Nietzsche, one would learn how dubious a view it is that men really want
the truth when the truth happens to be uncomfortable for them. Special
attention is given to the concept of self-deception in Hegel’s theory of
“unhappy consciousness,” in Kierkegaard’s discussion of “purity of
heart,” and Sartre’s view of “bad faith.” According to Sartre, men
evade responsibility for their existential freedom through intentional
ignorance of the human reality.
Apart from the obscure works of the philoso-phers, however,
self-deception is also one of those human realities on which great works
of Western literature have been richly sustained over many years. One
thinks of the classic portrayal of it in Sophocles’ Oedipus Rex
or Shakespeare’s The Tragedy of King Lear. We remember the
soliloquy on self-swindling in Dickens’ Great Expectations,
Emma’s intrigues with lovers in Flaubert’s Madame Bovary, or
Strether’s efforts to remain oblivious to unwanted evidence in Henry
James’ The Ambas-sadors. The tragic condition of self-deception
is discussed and depicted in great Russian literature of the past—such
as Dostoevsky’s Notes from Underground, Tolstoy’s Anna
Karenina, Father Sergius, and The Death of Ivan Ilych.
Indeed, one of the most graphically accurate depictions of
self-deception is found in Tolstoy’s War and Peace, when Count
Rostov returns home from a business trip to discover that something has
happened to his daughter. We read:
The Count saw clearly that something had gone wrong during his absence;
but it was so terrible for him to imagine anything discredible
occur-ring in connection with his beloved daughter, and he so prized his
own cheerful tranquility, that he avoided asking questions and did his
best to persuade himself that there was nothing very much wrong or out
of the way . . . . 56
The illustrations from literature could be multi-plied many times over.
We could mention O’Neill’s The Iceman Cometh, or Andre Gide’s
Pastoral Sym-phony, or Camus’ The Fall, or any number of
other entertaining, perplexing accounts.
We still would not be fully aware of how com-mon the notion of
self-deception has been in human thought until we supplemented the
survey with those sociological and psychological ap-proaches to man
which have so profoundly affected Western culture in the last century.
One thinks here, of course, of the discussion by Marx of “false
consciousness” and collective illusion, caus-ing an entire social class
to obscure the motives of its thought from itself. We recall the
sociology of knowledge presented by Karl Mannheim, who pointed to the
tenacity of commitment to theore-tical formulations which, although
impractical, have been acquired in the cooperative process of group
life. Finally, we cannot overlook Freud’s psychoanalytic study of
subconscious maneuvers and defense mechanisms by which men cling to
their cherished illusions.
So whether we turn to works in religion, philoso-phy, literature,
sociology or psychology, we cannot come to the conclusion that the
notion of self-deception is somehow an unfamiliar one. We have ample
evidence that men identify something in their experience as
self-deception. The notion is readily utilized in everyday
conversation, not simply in published works of scholars. The vocabulary
of self-deception is recognizable (even by children), mastered by
people, and taught to others. And so, when the son of Mrs. Jones has
been caught red-handed stealing lunch money out of students’ desks at
school, and Mrs. Jones continues to protest her son’s innocence—despite
this being the third time such an incident has taken place, despite her
discomfort and red face when the subject of dishonesty comes up in
casual conversations, despite the fact that she does not trust her son
around her purse any longer—and she continues to explain his innocence
with strange explanations (like the school officials have a vendetta
against little Johnny, they were framing him, etc.) nobody finds it
awkward to say the poor lady “is deceiving herself.” You see, self-decep-tion
is part of our common experience, and famili-arity with it breeds
acceptance of it as a genuine reality of life.
The Apparent Paradox and
Search for a Solution
Our ready acceptance of the phenomenon of self-deception, however, has
been challenged over the last thirty-five years; philosophical attention
has been given to conceptual questions about self-deception which arise
in both the theory of knowledge and the philosophy of mind.
The analytical-epistemological approach to the subject was somewhat
anticipated in Bertrand Russell’s critique of Freud in The Analysis
of Mind (1921) and in Gilbert Ryle’s criticism of mind-body dualism
in The Concept of Mind (1949). Russell spoke of desire-motivated
beliefs (or wishful thinking), and Ryle pointed out that the practice of
self-deception challenges the common dualist assumption that man has
some direct introspec-tive knowledge of the workings of his own mind, a
knowledge free from illusion and doubt. However critical, intense and
thorough philosophical scru-tiny of the notion of self-deception was
inaugu-rated in 1960 by Raphael Demos in his pioneering article entitled
“Lying to Oneself.”57 A long series of reactions and
counter-proposals has developed in the philosophical journals since that
time. Now inquiry was made into just what self-deception must involve
to qualify as such, and into whether it is a feat which can literally be
accomplished. Analyses of the notion always seemed headed for some form
of paradox.
You see, the natural thing to do is to model self-deception on the
well-known activity of other-deception. Deceiving oneself is thought of
as a version of deceiving someone else. A problem here, of course, is
that in other-deception the roles of deceiver and deceived are
incompatible; yet in self-deception a person is thought to play both of
these incompatible roles himself! Sartre put the matter plainly in his
book Being and Nothingness.
It follows first that the one to whom the lie is told and the one who
lies are one in the same person, which means that I must know in my
capacity as deceiver the truth which is hidden from me in my capacity as
the one deceived. Better yet I must know the truth exactly in order to
conceal it more carefully—and this not at two different moments, which
at a pinch would allow us to re-establish the semblance of duality—but
in the unitary structure of a single project. How then can the lie
subsist if the duality which conditions it is sup-pressed?58
Let us stop and analyze the situation. In a case of other-deception,
Jones is aware that some proposition is false, but Jones intends to make
Smith believe that it is true—and he succeeds. If we take Smith out of
the picture and substitute in Jones, so as to gain “self-deception,”
we end up saying “Jones, aware that p is false, intends to make himself
believe that p is true, and succeeds in making himself believe that p is
true.”59 Such a statement is surely puzzling, for it
suggests, “that somebody could try to make, and succeed in making,
himself believe something which he, ex hypothesi, at the same
time believes not to be true.”60 It would be easy to
conclude, then, that self-deception is an incoherent project that cannot
be fulfilled.
So we are forced to ask whether there actually is such a thing as
perpetrating a deception on oneself. How could it occur in practice?
How could it be described without contradiction? How can someone,
after all, as deceived, believe p, yet as deceiver disbelieve
p? It now appears that self-deception, despite the familiarity of the
notion, is about as difficult to do as presiding over one’s own funeral.
When we introduce the element of mendacity (dishonesty, lying) into the
picture, the problem is even further complicated. Here we move from
epistemic notions about belief into the philosophy of mind with
questions about con-sciousness, purpose, and intention. There have been
“weak models” of self-deception proposed by some philosophers, intending
to take the sting out of the paradox by maintaining that an agent does
not know what he is up to in self-deception.61 In “strong”
self-deception the enterprise is purpose-ful and not so innocent. And
it is this strong version of self-deception which is usually
thought necessary for moral culpability in self-deception. This
approach, however, only intensifies the philosophical perplexity
involved in the notion, for the kind of thought that goes into planning
and executing what you are doing in purposefully deceiving someone else,
makes doing it to yourself seem impossible. “Self-deception is not a
matter of mere stupidity or carelessness in thinking. It is a craftily
engineered project, and this is why it seems pointless and
self-contradictory.”62
So then, the analytical-epistemological ap-proach to the literature on
self-deception in recent years makes us hesitant to speak of it
confidently and clearly. And the maze of philosophical treatments given
to the paradoxical notion only intensifies our confusion. Herbert
Fingarette, in the first full book published on the subject, summarizes
the problem nicely:
Were a portrait of man to be drawn, one in which there would be
high-lighted whatever it is most human, be it noble or ignoble, we
should surely place well in the foreground man’s enormous capacity for
self-deception. The task of representing this most intimate, secret
gesture would not be much easier were we to turn to what the
philosophers have said. Philoso-phical attempts to elucidate the con-cept
of self-deception have ended in paradox—or in loss from sight of the
elusive phenomenon itself. . . . We are beset by confusion when once we
grant that the person himself is in self-deception. For as deceiver one
is insincere, guilty; whereas as genuine-ly deceived one is an innocent
victim. What, then, should we make of the self-deceiver, the one who is
both the doer and the sufferer? Our funda-mental categories are placed
squarely at odds with another. . . . ‘The one who lies with sincerity,’
who convinces himself of what he even knows is not so, who lies to
himself and to others and believes his own lie though in his heart he
knows that it is a lie—the phenomenon is so familiar, the task so easy,
that we nod our heads and say, ‘of course.’ Yet when we examine what we
have said with respect to our inner coherency, we are tempted to dismiss
such a de-scription as nonsense.63
At this juncture we can take the route of denying the reality of
self-deception or the route of resolving the apparent contradiction
involved in the notion. My procedure will be to take self-deception as
a datum, and thus I am committed to saying that at best it is
only apparently self-contradictory. While it is not inconceivable that
those many people who have made use of the notion of self-deception over
the centuries have been unwittingly contradicting themselves, it is
still not very likely. We resist the conclusion that self-deception is
actually impossible because we know that people do not merely play at
self-deception. They engage in it in tragic ways, and very often they
later come to realize the fact (for instance, think here of that
devastating book by Albert Speers, Inside the Third Reich).
Given Paul’s teaching in Romans 1—not to mention the actual use of the
phrase ‘to deceive oneself’ in James 1:26 and 1 John 1:8—the Christian
especially will want to resist dismissing self-deception as an
incoherent impossibility. Most people, then, will be more sure that
self-deception occurs than they would be of any explanation which
renders it only apparent. So whenever we confront an account of
self-deception which makes it appear self-contra-dictory, our assumption
should be that the confusion lies not in the notion of self-deception
but in the person’s philosophical account of it. Accordingly our work is
cut out for us: as elusive as it may be, we are committed to finding an
adequate and coherent analysis of self-deception.
What will be required of us if we are going to succeed? The basic
requirement for an acceptable analysis of self-deception is simply that
it must “save the phenomenon,” while at the same time respecting the law
of contradiction. Thus our account must be descriptively accurate—true
to paradigm examples of self-deception. It is useful here to recall
Wittgenstein’s warnings against a reductionistic “craving for
generality” which is “contemptuous of the particular case.” We must
admit at the outset that the many and varied uses for the term
‘self-deception’ bear a “family resemblance” to each other.64
Doubtless there will be borderline cases, where ambiguous evidence
makes it difficult to tell if all of the usual elements of
self-deception are present. There will be extreme cases where some
element of self-deception is accentuated out of proportion—even as the
colloquial exclamation “That’s insane!” is an exaggeration of the
literal and proper use of the concept of insanity. There will be
analogous cases, deficient cases, peculiar cases, and on and on.
Nevertheless, there are typical or paradigmatic cases from which we
learn to use the expression “self-deception” and apply it to further,
diverse cases. Our use of this vocabulary is not so ad hoc as to
preclude the possibility of our picking out genuine cases of
self-deception. So I will aim to give necessary and sufficient
conditions for the truth of the assertion, “S deceived himself into
believing that p,” as it is taken in the full-fledged and paradigmatic
sense.
In order to be descriptively correct, our analysis must not radically
depart from ordinary language. Nor must it confuse or merge
self-deception with related and similar phenomena in human experience
(e.g., ignorance, wishful thinking, change of belief). Beyond being
accurate and exact, our account must also be completely rid of any
incoherence, which requires using clearly defined notions in the
analysis so that self-contradiction (or its absence) is detectable. We
do not want to explain self-deception, moreover, by appealing to
concepts which are even less clear than the one we are attempting to
understand—for example, by an ambiguous and misconceived distinction
between “psychological knowing” and “epistemological knowing,” which is
easily faulted as obscure, if not simply wrong. Yet on the other hand,
we do not want to make the analysis so pat and easy that the perplexing
element in self-deception is dismissed altogether, causing us to wonder
why it should ever have appeared problematic to begin with (for
instance, by drawing a trivial distinction between what someone ought to
know and what he actually does know—a strategy which brings
self-deception down to the level of any mundane oversight in one’s
thinking, such as not knowing your father’s age).65
Within the guidelines we have rehearsed here, we need to formulate an
adequate analysis of self-deception. While existentialist treatments
(e.g., Sartre, Fingarette) affirm the contradiction found in
self-deception as an experienced reality, the analytic tradition has
offered various avenues for removing the apparent logical difficulties.
In the philosophical journals, you will notice three basic strategies
for resolving the paradox.
The first strategy is to deny that there is a parallel between
self-deception and other-deception. Some maintain that deception is
inherently other-regarding, and thus the skeptical conclusion is
advanced that there actually is no such thing as self-deception. What
is commonly called “self-deception” needs to be given a more accurate
description.66 Others say that words like “deceive,” “know,”
or “believe” are used in a non-standard fashion in accounts of
self-deception, not having the same intended sense as in descriptions of
other-deception.67 Finally, others who deny the
other-deception parallel recommend that we “look and see” what
conditions actually hold when self-deception locutions are utilized, in
which case we will notice that self-deception situations do not involve
two incompatible beliefs (as in other-deception), but rather only a
particular kind of single belief entertained under peculiar
circum-stances. Thus we speak of “self-deception” when we want to
reprimand irresponsible holding of an unwarranted belief,68
or self-deceived beliefs are taken as those held in belief-adverse
circum-stances,69 or where there is an irrational refusal to
look at evidence,70 or where one simply desires to hold the
belief,71 or where weak-willed dishonesty permits
desire-generated blindness,72 or some emotion has
irrationally obscured the contrary evidence.73
The second strategy is to accept the other-deception model (the reality
of perpetrating a deception upon oneself) and maintain that
self-deception is a conflict state of holding incompatible beliefs, but
then resolving the paradox of believing contrary things by introducing
various kinds of distinctions. Some distinguish between knowledge and
“as-it-were-knowledge,”74 or between full be-lief and
“half-belief,”75 contending that the differ-ent senses for
this epistemic vocabulary in analys-es of self-deception render the
paradox only apparent. Other philosophers treat self-deception as a
literal case of other-deception, positing some kind of duality (e.g.,
levels of consciousness, split personality) within the self-deceived
person himself.76 Another approach is to draw a temporal
distinction between S-the-deceiver and (later) S-the-deceived.77
Finally, many writers have at-tempted to give a coherent account of
self-deception as a conflict state of incompatible beliefs by drawing
some kind of distinction regarding consciousness—for instance,
distinguishing two levels of awareness,78 or between general
and explicit consciousness,79 or between general aw-areness
and detailed awareness,80 or between conscious purpose and
unreflective purpose,81 or between conscious and unconscious
knowledge,82 or between strong and weak consciousness.83
The third strategy proposes to utilize an altogether different model for
self-deception which avoids appeal to such epistemic terms as
“knowledge” or “belief,” using instead a volition-action model wherein
one fails to “spell-out” for himself his engagements in the world. In
this way it is thought we can preserve the purposiveness and culpability
essential to any adequate account of the phenomenon, yet avoiding the
paradoxes which have proved inherent in the epistemic accounts of
self-deception.84
My evaluation is that none of these three major strategies for resolving
the apparent paradox will pass the tests of adequacy prescribed above.
In some cases we find necessary, but not sufficient, conditions for
self-deception set forth (e.g., adverse evidence, the influence of
desire on human belief). In other cases necessary condi-tions are
dismissed altogether (e.g., belief, incom-patible beliefs). Some
proposals merely state all over again the need for a resolution to the
problem (e.g., those using new senses for the epistemic vocabulary), or
else they reintroduce the paradox at a different point (e.g., having a
policy of not spelling-out an engagement in the world). Some
suggestions end up reducing self-deception to something else (e.g.,
reducing it to a change of belief, ignorance, cognitive error, or
pretending) and thereby render the notion dispensable. Another group of
attempted solutions rely on notions which are even more obscure or
problematic than self-deception itself (e.g., diverse kinds of
consciousness), escaping the appearance of paradox at the price of
equivocating on just what the self-believer believes he is aware of.
Other analyses confuse or merge self-deception with one of many related
states or actions (e.g., with wishful thinking, delusion, simple trust,
vacillation of opinion, obstinacy, or motivated belief). Virtually all
of the authors who have written on the subject have contributed some
helpful insights into the difficult issue of self-deception, and I will
draw from many of them in my own proposed resolution to the apparent
paradox. However, I am not convinced that these writers have been fully
true to the phenomenon or have escaped paradox.
Belief and Its Characteristics
There is something of a cognitive mess at the core of our lives. We are
inconsistent in our choices, incoherent in our convictions, persuaded
where we ought not to be, and deluded that we know ourselves
transparently. The concept of belief shows up in all of these kinds of
personal failures, and it should seem obvious that it does as well in
the kind of cognitive error we call “deception.” Deceived people have
been misled, deluded, beguiled or somehow mistaken in what they think
and expect to be the case; they engage in false believing. There are
few (if any) plausible grounds for disputing the claim that
self-deception involves holding one or more false beliefs. Ordinarily in
everyday thinking we construe self-deception in terms of belief (of some
variety, under some circumstance, etc.).
Fingarette, however, proposes as an alterna-tive analysis a volitional
account of self-deception which, stressing the element of intentional
ignor-ance, takes it to be a kind of action rather than a kind of
belief. Consciousness is an active and vocal power (rather than, as
traditionally thought, pas-sive and visual), and a person becomes
explicitly conscious of something through an intentional act of
“spelling out his engagements in the world.” Sometimes, though, there
are overriding reasons for a person to avoid spelling out these engage-ments,
as when doing so would be destructive of his self-conception or the
personal identity he has achieved. Lest the effort to avoid spelling
out the engagement itself reveal the engagement, one must avoid spelling
out that effort as well. Self-deception thus involves adopting an
avoidance policy whereby one purposefully chooses to stay ignorant of
some engagement in the world.
This is an inadequate alternative to belief-analyses of self-deception,
in the first place, because the troublesome concept of self-deception is
explained at the price of even greater obscurity (the unfamiliar
metaphor of “spelling out an en-gagement in the world”). Secondly, the
volition-action family of terms (which Fingarette prefers for explaining
self-deception) is itself heavily laden with notions involving cognitive
or epistemic terms like “belief,” “knowledge,” “perception,” etc. A
further difficulty is that Fingarette’s analysis overlooks completely
those cases of self-deception which involve an artificial and misleading
overdo-ing of spelling out one’s engagements in the world with an
inappropriate emotional detach-ment—the very opposite of Fingarette’s
avoidance policy. Finally, Fingarette’s alternative account does not rid
the notion of self-deception of paradox, but simply restates the paradox
in new terms. The effort to avoid spelling out one’s (preceding) effort
to avoid spelling out a distressful engagement in the world makes one
conscious of making oneself unconscious.
Others use the word “deceive” in a way which does not seem to make
believing false propositions essential to the act. Freudian
psychologists speak of the self-deceived person as being in the grip of
unconscious motivations (without mention of cognitive processes).
Kierkegaard spoke of a person’s failure to be true to himself and
ethically consistent as self-deception. However, Freudian and
existentialist uses of “deception” are either figurative language or
implicitly employ the cogni-tive sense of believing. If we are unable
to cash in talk of unconscious motives and true selves into descriptions
of ourselves which can be believed, it makes little sense to say we are
“being false” to ourselves or “living a lie.” Even when we say the
husband who is unfaithful to a knowing wife (they do not speak to each
other of his indiscretions) has “deceived” her, we mean he has violated
her expectations, in which case the cognitive sense of “deceive” is
again waiting in the wings.
There is simply no good reason to omit refer-ence to belief in a proper
analysis of self-decep-tion. More particularly, what is essential in
self-de- ception is that people hold a false belief—not simply an
unwarranted belief (e.g., the patient who chooses to disbelieve his
doctor’s report of cancer, only to turn out right in his wishful
thinking), and not simply the absence of expected belief (e.g., the
cuckold who literally thinks nothing about his wife’s infidelity,
although the neighborhood is loud with rumors and she has too many shady
late-night excuses). Even where people deceive them-selves about their
attitudes, hopes, emotions, etc. (e.g., false security, false pride),
the objects of self-deception themselves have a cognitive core. The
parent who is inappropriately proud of his child’s report card
experiences a certain emotion only by believing something about the
marks on the card. About the colleague who shows false sorrow over a
fellow worker’s firing we say, “He may think that he is sorry, but he
knows quite well he is delighted over this turn of events.”
I would maintain, then, that self-deception, as a form of deception,
involves believing false proposi-tions. Further, the mistaken believing
which is involved is fully genuine believing. We do not here speak of
“belief” in some odd, defective, or “twi-light” sense. The
self-deceiver is not merely feigning ignorance or being an obvious
hypocrite. He is concerned with the truth and makes efforts, albeit
strained, to sustain his false belief as rational. He is aware of the
weight and relevance of the evidence contrary to his belief, so he
distorts the evidence through pseudo-rational treatment of it. He is
not simply pretending. Although his twisting of the evidence shows that
he is trying to convince himself of something unlikely, he still behaves
in ways which rely upon the truth of what he says about his (false)
belief. He must say that he really believes the false proposition, or
else he would not be “deceived” after all. This is not simply
half-belief or near-belief, for that proposal would reduce
self-deception to mere vacillation, lack of confidence, or insincerity.
There is no lack of evidence for the self-deceiver’s full-fledged
believing; it is just that we have too many beliefs of his for which
there is adequate evidence—beliefs which are incompatible. Moreover,
the self-decei-ver’s false belief is not simply performatory in
character (an avowal which initiates a commitment about which he will
not follow through), for that would reduce self-deception to personal
deter-mination, striving, hoping contrary to fact, or wishful thinking.
We must turn attention, then, to the concept of belief if we would hope
to analyze self-deception adequately. This is a safe and promising move
because the concept of belief is familiar to everyone (despite notorious
philosophical questions which can nettle one’s understanding of it). Of
course “belief” could be defined in such a way as to preclude the
possibility of self-deception, but philosophers who have done so have
paid the price of implausibility. In the history of epistemology belief
is sometimes artificially restricted to an ideal philosophical notion
where people never believe contradictory propositions—which might better
be termed “rational belief.”85 This will hardly do as an
account of belief itself, for human nature is capable of more things and
stranger than common-sense philosophers suppose or than rationalistic
philosophers impose on the world in Procrustean fashion. One has a far
smaller opportunity to rid the world of irrationality if he takes the
short-cut of defining unreasonable or incoherent thinking out of
existence. Accor-dingly, I would suggest that the adequacy of one’s
conception of belief and of one’s conception of self-deception will
probably need to be judged jointly. To give a satisfactory account of
one while being untrue to the other is to fail to do justice to the full
range of human reality.
The term ‘believe’ has received analysis as a “parenthetical verb,” a
performative utterance, an expression denoting an occurrent mental event
or denoting a personal disposition to act in certain ways under certain
conditions.86 Each analysis has its advantages and
drawbacks, and in the end we are probably unable to provide a genuine
“anal-ysis” of belief just because it appears to be a notion which is
primitive or fundamental in the explanation of the wide range of
concepts in epis-temology and philosophy of mind. Belief cannot be
traditionally defined in terms of anything more basic than itself.
Nevertheless, nothing prevents us from offering a general
characterization of the ordinary notion of belief (without claiming com-pleteness).
Belief is a positive, intellectual, propositional attitude which is
expressed in a large variety of symptoms (some of which are subject to
degrees of strength). To believe something is to have a favorable
attitude toward a proposition—an atti-tude of the intellectual (rather
than merely cona-tive or affectional) kind. It is to take the
proposi-tion as true in a virtually automatic response to the evidence
as it is perceived by the person. Thus to believe p is to see it as
evidenced, to regard p as reliable. In the sense that belief is
controlled by and informed by the way evidence is construed by the
believer, belief is often said to be “con-strained”—and some
propositions are popularly said to be “beyond belief.” Even seemingly
unrea-sonable beliefs (cf. “blind faith”) will turn out upon exploration
to rest on something which is regarded by the believer anyway as a
warrant, calling for the belief in question. Although belief is a
positive propositional attitude informed by the evidence, that evidence
can (and often is) misconstrued, misperceived, and approached with
myopia of mind and senses. On this characterization, belief by no means
precludes believing false proposi-tions.
We can attempt a more precise characteriza-tion of belief here, one
which with a modicum of judicious philosophical industry can survive
whatever problems may remain to be worked out elsewhere.87
The proposed way of speaking of belief shows initial plausibility, has
been defended by respected scholars, and is bolstered by our common
understanding of the concept of belief (even though it may not be a
completely system-atic account or analysis). A base belief is an
action-guiding state of mind; it is a map-like mental state that is a
potential cause of particular action (mental, verbal, or bodily).
Specifically, belief is a persisting, intentional, mental state (made
up of ideas which give a determinate character to the state
corresponding to the proposition believed) with a stimulus-independent
causal capacity to affect or guide one’s theoretical and practical
behavior, under suitable circum-stances, in a wide variety of
manifestations. In what follows, then, the expression “S believes that
p” will be understood as true if and only if S relies upon p (sometimes,
intermittently, or continu-ously) in his theoretical inferences and/or
practical actions and plans.88
The grounds for saying that someone is self-deceived will coincide with
or include the grounds for saying that he believes some proposition. If
S did not take p as evidenced—that is, if S did not have a positive
attitude or mental state such that p was relied upon in his theoretical
or practical inferences—then we could not distinguish self-deception
from mere ignorance of, or dislike for, p. It is just because S
unavoidably looks upon some evidence as supporting p—and is thereby in
the mental state of relying upon p in his inferences (practical and/or
theoretical)—that his desire to avoid or manipulate that evidence in
“self-deception” is meaningful. S does not wish to have his mind
“in-formed” by the evidence in this fashion; he does not want to believe
what he does believe. He would rather forget or hide the unpleasant
truth that has gripped him, that is, to make covert that he relies upon
p in his theoretical inferences and/or practical actions and plans. His
negative emotional response to p leads him to try and escape his
uncontrived way of seeing things.
There are certain further points regarding belief about which we should
make special mention. First, the bases for ascribing a belief to someone
(the marks by which we discern a belief) are provided by both occurrent
and dispositional accounts of belief. We consider the person’s outward
assertion of p (or inward, if ourself), and the way in which he behaves,
reasons, gestures, feels, etc.; we take into account his decisions,
emotions, habits, and even inaction. Of course neither a person’s
actions nor his utterances are infallible signs of belief, but they do
offer fairly reliable correlations. The various kinds of indica-tors
for belief should be used to supplement and qualify each other. One’s
own avowals of belief have a presumptive authority in determining what
he believes, but those avowals can be defeated by cautious and
relatively thorough observation of his other behavioral indicators. To
put it simply: over time, actions will speak louder than words.
Second, not all of our beliefs are formed con-sciously, rationally, and
with the giving of internal or external assent. To give assent to a
proposition is explicitly to spell out (inwardly or outwardly) how one
stands in respect to that proposition, thereby bringing one’s belief to
a conscious level of experience. However, there is no special logical
or conceptual connection between beliefs and their linguistic
expression. Holding a belief is not logically dependent upon a
willingness or competence to express that belief verbally to oneself or
others. Assent is not necessary to the mental state of belief. The
cognitive and affective aspects of belief can sometimes be separated in
a person and even be at odds with each other (e.g., hoping for what
cannot be, fearing what you know does not hurt, failing to feel
conviction in the face of strong proof). Accordingly we can easily
imagine situations where most of the affective manifestations of a
belief that p occur in S, and yet S does not assent to p, even when the
proposition is attended to in his mind. He does not notice that his
actions, emotions, assumptions, inferences, etc. are such as would be
expected symptoms of someone who accepts p. It is a false picture we
entertain of intelligent beings if we think of them as incessantly
talking to themselves internally and always making explicit (or
reporting on) their mental states and acts. A person’s condition can be
quite obviously belief-like, even when the (usual) assent-symptom of
belief is absent; most, if not all, of the other symptoms of belief are
evident. His behavior can hardly be explained without postulating in
him a belief that p. It would be an artificial imposition to erect a
terminological rule at this point, prohibiting us from saying that “S
believes p” under such circumstances.
That would only screen off the complexity of human nature and behavior
from us. We can certainly imagine, if we have not actually
encoun-tered, people who would protest that they do not hold beliefs
about the inferior human dignity of people from other races—and yet who
evidence just such an attitude in their social behavior nonetheless.
The fact that belief can be divorced from explicit assent shows us,
then, that there can be beliefs held by a person of which he is not
aware—not consciously entertaining in his mind by introspection. A
person can rely upon a proposition in his theoretical inferences and/or
practical plans (e.g., “There is sufficient gas in the car’s tank”)
without entertaining that proposition in mind; the proposition may not
come to mind until something goes wrong (e.g., when he ends up stranded
down the road). When I am surprised by meeting my previously
vacationing neighbor at the mall, it is hardly because I had consciously
inferred or entertained the proposition that he would not yet be back
from his travels. The fact is that our set of beliefs is expanded and
diminished throughout our waking moments (through sense experience,
casual reflection, etc.), and thus beliefs can be adopted without
concentrating on the adoption procedure or even being aware of its
results. Furthermore, it is quite clear that not everything that a
person believes can be simultaneously attended to by him in thought. We
must conclude that introspection and assent do not invariably accompany
a person’s each and every mental state or action.
Third, we must add that self-ascriptions of belief by way of assent—just
like disavowals of belief—are not incorrigible (i.e., there can be
overriding reasons to think them false) and therefore not infallible
(i.e., such reports can be mistaken). A person can be held to believe
something from which he dissents, and can be found not to believe
something to which he assents. To some appreciable extent we can be
mistaken about our own beliefs. This may seem surprising, but there are
after all limits on our self-knowledge, even though our own reports
about our beliefs (or pains, or perceptions, etc.) have a presumptive
authority and are granted a degree of accuracy.
We have seen that normally first-per-son, present-tense, occurrent
mental state beliefs are direct, far more reliable than the counterpart
beliefs about others, excellent evidence for the presence of the states
they “report,” . . . but they are like our beliefs about others in being
fallible, dubitable, corrigible, and testable.89
People may have the best word on what they believe, but they do not
logically have the last word (as in the example of racial prejudice
above). It is not hard to find examples in ordinary experi-ence of
someone believing something, but yet withholding, avoiding or
suppressing internal and external assent to it. We also have ready
examples of someone believing that he believes something, although in
fact he does not believe it. Such examples can only be explained away or
recategorized by the ex post facto imposition of artificial
conditions upon what we call “belief.” People can and do sometimes come
to realize, on the evidence in their behavior, that their previous
avowals (or disavowals) of a belief were mistaken.
Fourth, the last thing about belief which calls for special mention is
its voluntariness. This may seem strange since we have above spoken of
belief as a propositional attitude which is “constrained” by the
evidence as seen by the person in question. The seeing of the evidence
as this or that—the taking of it in a particular way—constrains one to
believe as he does. Since I see myself as right-handed, I cannot
voluntarily and on the spot believe (genuinely) that I am left-handed.
Nobody can believe contrary to the way in which he sees the evidence,
to be sure. However, one can exercise some control over the way in
which he sees that evidence—directing his attention, giving prominence
to some matters over others, suppres-sing what he does not wish to
encounter, re-evaluating the significance of past considerations, etc.
If belief is like “seeing-as,” then we must also recognize that
seeing-as is somewhat subject to one’s will. A person is free to ignore
the grounds for a belief, in which case that belief is not compelled (in
an absolute sense) after all. A person cannot choose voluntarily and
arbitrarily to believe whatever he wishes, but he can nevertheless
freely doubt propositions, suspend judgment about them, voluntarily
inhibit extending inferences based on them, etc. Directing our thoughts
is a kind of doing, and by the directing of our attention we can
encourage or thwart our propensity to believe things. People are thus
free to fortify or undermine beliefs they have by voluntarily
concentrating on certain lines of evidence, ignoring others,
misconstruing yet others, etc. In such ways we can deliberately
cultivate a belief (whether about some matter or about ourselves and our
beliefs) which turns out contrary to the facts.
Everyone knows the experience of weighing or deliberating about the
options and then “taking the plunge” of assenting to one over the other.
We ordinarily take responsibility—and are held responsible—for our
beliefs. They are assessed as though we had some control over them; our
beliefs are evaluated as more or less reasonable, justifiable, and even
moral. We at times hear people declare “I cannot believe that” (e.g., a
close relative has been convicted of a heinous crime), but we all
realize that the “cannot” here should be interpreted as “will
not”—because one does not want it to be true, cannot emotionally afford
to admit it, thinks it is his duty to resist it, or lacks the
intellectual energy to rise to the occasion. In many ways, then, we
recognize the voluntary aspect of belief.
Given the preceding explanation of belief as such, and with the salient
features of belief just enumerated in mind, we can proceed to explicate
a non-paradoxical account of self-deception.
Incompatible Beliefs, Motivated Rationalization, and Self-Covering
Intention
We should maintain the appropriateness of modeling self-deception on
other-deception, contending that there is a common sense for the word
“deception” in both cases. This does not commit us to going to the
extreme of making self-deception a literal case of other-deception (the
same in every detail), as though we were dealing with a split
personality. Rather self-deception should be seen as a general parallel
to other-deception in certain specifiable ways. For instance, elements
of deception which are shared by both self-deception and other-deception
are the deceiver’s responsibility for causing the deceived to believe
falsely, the deceived holds (at least implicitly) an erroneous belief
about the deceiver’s beliefs, and the rationalization maneuvers taken in
the face of evidence brought to the attention of the deceiver by others.
Given the other-deception model, incompatible beliefs need to be
attributed to the self-deceiver on the basis of his behavior.
Self-deception is a conflict state in which S holds incompatible
beliefs, but the nature of this incompatibility needs to be noted. The
self-deceived person holds a first-order belief (viz., that p) which is
not a matter of personal indifference to himself, but somehow
distressing; he has a personal stake in (or against) p. Thus it is a
special kind of belief: one which S dreads, cannot face up to, or wishes
were otherwise since it brings some unpleasant truth before him.
Accordingly, S brings himself to deny that belief—not only to deny p
(about the distressing issue in question) but more significantly to deny
something about himself (namely, his believing p). Thus the analysis of
self-deception involves reference to iterated beliefs (i.e., beliefs
about one’s beliefs). While believing p, S comes to hold additionally a
(false) second-order belief about that belief—namely, that S does not
believe p. A person may believe that dogs are dangerous (first-order),
and may also believe (second-order) that this belief concerning dogs is
quite reasonable. A person may believe (first-order) that members of
other races are inferior and yet (second-order) believe about himself
that he does not believe in racial inferiority.90
It is important to note that the behavioral symptoms of believing p
overlap extensively with the behavioral symptoms of believing that you
believe p. In the examination of one’s actions, emotions, words, etc.
it will be found that they can easily be taken as indicators of both the
first-order and the second-order belief. Likewise, the behavioral
indicators for S not believing p readily shade back and forth into the
behavioral indicators for S believing (about himself) that he does not
believe p. A man who believes that dogs are dangerous engages in most
of the same inferences, reactions, emotions and behavior as a man who
believes that he believes dogs are dangerous. This helps us to
understand that the nature of the incompatibility of beliefs in
self-deception is not logical in nature, but behavioral and practical.
The first-order and second-order beliefs are not formally
contradictory, but the inferential and behavioral effects of the two
beliefs are in conflict with each other. The self-deceiver believes
something (which causes him distress) and gives evidence of believing
it; however, he brings himself to believe that he does not believe it
(which brings a measure of relief) and gives evidence that he does not
think of himself as believing it. S believes p, but his assent to it is
blocked by acquiring the (false) second-order belief that S does not
believe p. The incompatibility between these two beliefs is thus
practical in nature. They call for conflicting kinds of intellectual,
verbal, and behavioral responses.
Now S has an obvious interest at stake in maintaining the rationality of
his second-order belief (which brings him into a conflict state with his
first-order belief). This analysis of self-deception holds that it
comes about when, in the face of evidence adverse to his cherished
second-order belief (about himself), S engages in contrived and
pseudo-rational treatment of the evidence. That is, he manipulates,
suppresses, and rationalizes the evidence so as to support a belief
which is incompatible with his believing that p. He ignores the
obvious, focuses away from undesirable indicators, twists the
significance of evidence, goes to extreme measures to enforce his policy
of hiding his belief that p from himself and others. If he looked at
himself as others see him, he would have all the evidence he needs to
conclude that he believes that p, but he strains and strains to convince
himself that he does not believe that p.
This rationalizing activity, in order to count as self-deception and not
something else (e.g., a cavalier disagreement), must be given a
motivational explanation. S distorts the evidence in order to satisfy a
desire—namely, the desire to avoid the discomfort, distress, or pain
associated with believing that p. By means of it he enters into and
maintains self-deception, believing that he does not believe that p.
Actions or reactions which have the effect of achieving the special
state of incompatible beliefs traced above are referred to in statements
like “S is deceiving himself regarding p” (namely, by bringing himself
to believe about himself that he does not believe that p). Avowal of
the second-order belief about his not believing that p may function for
S as “the taking of a stand” on his identity as a person; it amounts to
a commitment to a particular conception of himself (although by no means
logically free from mistake).
As human actions, self-deceiving maneuvers may be purposively
engaged—done intentionally (although they need not be in all cases).
“Falling” into self-deception would no more be a uniquely human action
than falling into a pit. We should be concerned, then, to complete our
analysis by considering self-deception as something done on purpose
(i.e., “strong self-deception”). Only then could it be considered
morally culpable and, as such, of interest to Christian apologetics and
ethics.
The vexed questions of awareness and purpose in self-deception address
what is perhaps our underlying perplexity in making sense of the notion.
If S is intentionally trying to deceive himself (thus being conscious
of what he is up to), how could he ever be successful (making himself
believe contrary to that of which he is conscious)? This is what I
propose. While the self-deceiver is aware of the truth of p or sees it
as evidenced (i.e., p presents itself to S as the truth), and while his
belief that p is indicated by his behavior (i.e., relying upon it in his
theoretical or practical inferences), he will not give assent to p but
induces in himself—by controlling attention to the relevant evidence—an
incompatible (and false) belief that S does not believe p. Accordingly,
the self-deceiver is not aware that he holds incompatible beliefs; after
all, he does not believe that he believes that p, but believes of
himself that he does not believe p, thus avowing mistakenly and
only that he does not believe p. S should recognize the conflict
state of incompatible beliefs (if his self-knowledge were not
defective), but the strategy of hiding his dreaded belief prevents him
from doing so. If he did recognize the incompatibility of his genuine
beliefs, but did not resolve it, he would simply be vacillating or
irrational. Thus the self-deceiver is not personally aware that his
professed and cherished belief about himself (that he does not believe
that p) is false. He is not simply a liar.
The critical question is whether one can try to deceive himself and not
be aware of such things. Can S engage in self-deception on purpose?
The common assumption is that if S purposes to do something, then he
must be aware of its character. In that case, if S purposely engaged in
the activity of self-deception (e.g., rationalizing the evidence so as
to hide a dreaded belief), it seems he would be aware that he is
attempting to deceive himself, and that would foil the effort—just as
much as if R realized that S were intending to mislead him from the
truth, S could not successfully deceive R. However, I argue that S’s
awareness of his aim to make the belief that p covert (by believing
something incompatible with it) need not undermine the success of his
effort at deception. What S thinks about in his purposeful attempt at
self-deception need not be deception-defeating, for the intention to
deceive oneself can be self-covering. That is, it is one of a
special class of human intentions which obscure awareness of themselves,
in which case S can purpose not only to hide his belief that p, but
also—to preserve his self-esteem as a rational agent—to hide his hiding
of it. The self-deceiver conceals his intention from himself, deceiving
himself about his intention to deceive himself.
To avoid an infinite regress of self-deceptions (about the self-deceived
intention to deceive oneself, etc.) in the case of “strong”
self-deception, it must be possible for an intention to be
self-covering. The intention to practice self-deception must obscure
itself in the process of obscuring S’s belief that p, and yet
without calling for a further intention regarding itself in this matter.
But can (some) intentions have two objects in this way? If so, the
intention to practice self-deception could have as its object both the
dreaded belief (to be covered) as well as the deceiving intention (also
to be covered). The fact that (some) intentions can indeed be
self-covering is obvious from the common experience of intending to go
to sleep. A person can purposely choose to go to sleep, doing the
things necessary to accomplishing that end (e.g., relaxing, lying down,
counting sheep, etc.). However, if he is successful in that intention,
he does not continue to be aware of the intention itself, or else he
would stay awake (aware). So then, there are intentions which cover
themselves when they are successfully performed, and there is no good
reason to refrain from classifying self-deception as that kind of
intention. When a person intentionally tries to deceive himself and is
aware of that intention at the outset,91 he is eventually
going to lose his awareness of what he is doing (i.e., “will fall
asleep” concerning it). If successful, the “strong” self-deceiver will
reach a point where he no longer looks back and spells out what he was
doing. Likewise, if you intend to put out your own eyes, at some point
in the process you can no longer visually examine (in a mirror) what is
going on. When self-deception is intentional, then, I propose that it
is a self-covering intention, such as we are familiar with in our
ordinary experience.
Summary
The analysis of self-deception fostered here maintains that when S
deceives himself:
1. S believes that p,
2. S is motivated to ignore, hide, deny (etc.) his belief that p, and
3. By misconstruing or rationalizing the evidence, S brings himself to
believe falsely that “S does not believe that p.”
In order to preserve something about his own self-conception, S engages
in motivated rationalization of the evidence so that he relies in his
theoretical and practical inferences on the proposition that he is not
relying in his theoretical and practical inferences on p. He is morally
culpable for this lie about himself because it is engaged intentionally,
and yet he may not be aware of his intention since it has become
habitual or, being self-covering, has become something he no longer
thinks about (like falling asleep). S obscures his dreaded belief that
p, as well as his intention to obscure it by rationalizing the evidence.
Self-deception involves deception of the self, by the self, about the
self, and for the sake of the self.
This analysis of self-deception in terms of iterated beliefs, corrigible
disavowals, motivated rationalization of evidence, and self-covering
intentions is adequate to explain the common illustrations of
self-deception which we encounter. Recall the example about Mrs. Jones.
The principal calls her to say that her son Johnny (her pride and joy,
her only child) has been caught stealing lunch money out of students’
desks. The evidence is plain that Johnny is a thief, and this is the
third time she has received such a call from the school. She has also
noticed money missing out of her own purse at home, and Johnny has been
coming home with expensive items from the store. Mrs. Jones shows the
affective symptoms of believing the proposition that Johnny is a thief.
She tries to avoid situations where she is likely to be reminded of his
dishonesty. She moves to a new neighborhood, transferring Johnny into a
new school, and refusing to put a phone in her new home. She keeps an
unusually attentive eye on her boy, but will not admit that she does so,
etc. Yet on the other hand, since nobody in the Jones family has ever
stooped to dishonesty, and Johnny is her one reason left for living in
the cruel world, she persuades herself that Johnny could not have done
the dishonest deeds reported by the principal. She forgets the past
evidence and supplies “more credible” explanations of present evidence
(e.g., money is missing from her purse because she is so careless or
forgetful). She goes out of her way to express confidence in her son to
others, makes a show of giving him mature responsibilities, and tries to
do only what one who believed in Johnny’s virtue would do. She avers
that she has a fine boy who is a joy to her, a regular paragon of
virtue. Nevertheless, she flies off the handle at him over trifling
matters (in a way unlike the way she related to him prior to the
principal’s phone calls). She astonishes and embarrasses others by
seizing on every oblique innuendo to defend Johnny’s honesty. When
neighbors get curious over her missing cash and Johnny’s new
acquisitions, Mrs. Jones fidgets, blushes, looks away, answers in
halting fashion or changes the subject. She treats the evidence
broached in an unusual and distorted way, all the while apparently
satisfying herself that her interpretations are quite plausible.
In this situation we find it very natural to express the view that Mrs.
Jones is self-deceived. The affective symptoms justify us in
attributing to her the belief that Johnny is a thief. Because she
cannot stand that thought with its attendant psychic discomfort, she is
motivated to hide this information from herself and direct her attention
to the evidence in odd ways. She dissents from believing her son is
dishonest. She claims the school officials had a vendetta against
Johnny and were framing the poor boy. She leans on implausible
interpretations of facts, ignores the best and most obvious indicators,
and brings herself to believe that she does not believe in Johnny’s
dishonesty. (She is not the mother of a crook!) She fools herself
about her awareness of the truth. The symptoms of this false
second-order belief are nearly identical with believing that it is not
the case that Johnny is a thief. She conceives of herself as trusting
this untrustworthy son, and while guarding herself against his
untrustworthiness she enthusiastically affirms her belief in him to
others. She meets all the criteria of self-deception as proposed above,
and we are able to describe what she is doing without resorting to
paradox.
The analysis of self-deception offered here not only is adequate to
account for mundane and well-known cases of self-deception, but more
importantly, it is adequate to explain Paul’s description in Romans 1 of
men who know (believe) that God exists and yet suppress that belief
unrighteously. The analysis thus strengthens, defends and advances the
cause of Van Til’s presuppositional apologetic.
All men know and hence believe that God exists. The revelational
evidence is so plain that nobody can avoid holding the conviction that
God exists, even though they may never explicitly assent to this belief.
We are justified in ascribing such a belief to men on the basis of
their observed behavior in reasoning (e.g., relying on the uniformity of
nature), in morals (e.g., holding to ethical absolutes in some fashion),
and in emotion (e.g., fearing death). Nevertheless, all men are
motivated in unrighteousness and by fear of judgment to ignore, hide,
and disavow any belief in the living and true God (either through
atheism or false religiosity). By misconstruing and rationalizing the
relevant, inescapable evidence around them (“suppressing it”), men bring
themselves to believe about themselves that they do not believe in God,
even though that second-order belief is false. Sinners can purposely
engage in this kind of activity, for they also deceive themselves about
their motivation in handling the evidence as they do and about their
real intentions, which are not noble or rational at all. Thereby they
“go to sleep” (as it were), forgetting their God. Because the evidence
is clear, and because the suppression of the truth is intentional, we
can properly conclude that all men are “without excuse” and bear full
responsibility for their sins of mind, speech, and conduct.
Given the elaboration of self-deception offered here, we can better
appreciate what Paul says in Romans 1, namely, that “knowing God,” all
men “suppress the truth in unrighteousness.” And we can assert
non-paradoxically that unbelievers culpably deceive themselves about
their Maker.
Notes
1
Most recently by John M. Frame in a chapter on “Cornelius Van Til” in
Handbook of Evangelical Theologians, ed. Walter A. Elwell (Grand
Rapids: Baker Books, 1993), pp. 163-165. Examining various discussions
of the unbeliever’s knowledge of God in Van Til’s writings, Frame says,
“It is difficult to make sense out of all this . . . . Contrary to Van
Til, a biblical apologetic need not exclude common notions or ideas, but
may legitimately draw conclusions from them.”
2
For Van Til’s place in the historical unfolding of the discipline see
Greg L. Bahnsen, “Socrates or Christ: The Reformation of Christian
Apologetics” in Foundations of Christian Scholarship: Essays in the
Van Til Perspective, ed. Gary North (Vallecito, California: Ross
House Books, 1976), pp. 191-239.
3
Cornelius Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, vol. 2 of
the series “In Defense of Biblical Christianity” (n.p.: den Dulk
Christian Foundation, 1969), p. 4.
4
Cornelius Van Til, “My Credo,” Jerusalem and Athens: Critical
Discussions on the Theology and Apologetics of Cornelius Van Til,
ed. E. R. Geehan (n.p.: Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co., 1971),
p. 20. Also note: “The only ‘proof’ of the Christian position is that
unless its truth is presupposed there is no possibility of ‘proving’
anything at all” (p. 21). For an illustration of how this argument is
put into practice, consult the “Bahnsen-Stein Debate” (at the University
of California, Irvine, in 1985), tapes #ASST from Covenant Media
Foundation at 1-800/553-3938.
5
Cornelius Van Til, An Introduction to Systematic Theology, vol. 5
of the series “In Defense of Biblical Christianity” (Phillipsburg, NJ:
Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co., 1974), p. 9.
6
Contrary to the unbalanced and misleading remark about ontological
priority in Jim Halsey, “A Preliminary Critique of Van Til: the
Theologian,” Westminster Theological Journal 39 (Fall, 1976):
122-130.
7
John W. Montgomery, “Once Upon an A Priori,” Jerusalem and Athens,
p. 391; Norman Geisler, Christian Apologetics (Grand Rapids:
Baker Book House, 1976), p. 56; R. C. Sproul, John Gerstner, and Arthur
Lindsley, Classical Apologetics: A Rational Defense of the Christian
Faith and a Critique of Presuppositional Apologetics (Grand Rapids:
Zondervan Publishing House, 1984), p. 184.
8
Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, p. 11.
9
Ibid., p. 205.
10
Cornelius Van Til, The Defense of the Faith (Philadelphia:
Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co., 1955), pp. 117-118, 131; cf.
pp. 125-126, 132. References throughout are to the first edition.
11
Ibid., p. 119.
12
Cornelieus Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge (n.p.:
Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co., 1969), p. 19; cf. The
Defense of the Faith, p. 197.
13
E.g., A Survey of Christian Epistemology, pp. 189, 201, 204, 206,
225; The Defense of the Faith, pp. 94, 110, 117, 119-120,
194-195, 198, 266-267, 279, 283.
14
Cornelius Van Til, Common Grace (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and
Reformed Publishing Co., 1947), p. 62.
15
Van Til,The Defense of the Faith, p. 396.
16
Ibid., p. 317.
17
Ibid., pp. 67, 290; cf. Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge,
pp. 43-44.
18
Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge, p. 13.
19
Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, p. xii.
20
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p. 355.
21
Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge, p. 22.
22
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p. 120; cf. p. 260.
23
Ibid., p. 103.
24
Ibid., p. 111.
25
Ibid., p. 173.
26
Ibid., pp. 173-174, 192.
27
Ibid., p. 257; cf. pp. 107, 109.
28
Ibid., p. 173; cf. p. 257.
29
Ibid., pp. 109, 111, emphasis added; cf. pp. 102, 115, 285, 305-306.
30
Ibid., p. 100 (cf. p. 26); Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge,
p. 46.
31
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, pp. 385-386.
32
Ibid., p. 110, emphasis added; cf. p. 112.
33
Van Til, An Introduction to Systematic Theology, p. 26. On the
preceding page he labels the problem “complex,” and on page 93 he speaks
of Romans 1:18-21 as “this most difficult passage.”
34
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, pp. 261-262.
35
Ibid., pp. 363-364.
36
Ibid, p. 66, emphasis added.
37
Ibid., p. 388, emphasis added.
38
Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge, p. 45.
39
E.g., ibid, pp. 45, 46; Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p.
388.
40
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, pp. 120, 111.
41
Ibid., p. 259.
42
Ibid., pp. 257, 112, 111. (Interestingly, this type of example is common
in recent philosophical literature on self-deception.)
43
Ibid., p. 355.
44
Ibid., pp. 257, 111.
45
Ibid., p. 115.
46
E.g., ibid, p. 306; Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge, p.
42.
47
Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, p. 225.
48
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p. 191, emphasis added.
49
Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge, p. 46.
50
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p. 259; cf. A Christian
Theory of Knowledge, p. 42.
51
Ibid., p. 306.
52
Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, p. 4.
53
Van Til, The Defense of the Faith, p. 109.
54
It is because of the pivotal importance of the concept of self-deception
to presuppositional apo-logetics that I pursued an in depth analysis of
it for my doctoral dissertation in philosophy:
“A Condi-tional Resolution of the Apparent
Paradox of Self-Deception”
University of Southern
California, 1978. [available
in several formats
since March 3, 2011.--A.F.]. What follows is a brief synopsis.
55
Joseph Butler, Sermons (New York: Robert Carter & Bros., 1870
1729), p. xv.
56
Leo Tolstoy, War and Peace, vol. 1 (New York: Penguin Books,
1972), p. 698.
57
Raphael Demos, “Lying to Oneself,” Journal of Philosophy 57
(Sept. 1, 1960): 588-594.
58
Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes
(New York: Washington Square Press, 1956), p. 89.
59
John V. Canfield and Don F. Gustavson, “Self-Deception,: Analysis
23 (1962)32. Throughout this essay I will use “S” to stand for any
subject who knows or believes, and “p” for any proposition which is
known or believed.
60
Patrick Gardiner, “Error, Faith, and Self-Deception,” Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society 70 N.S. (1969-1970) 224-25.
61
Cf. Stanley Paluch, “Self-Deception,” Inquiry 10 (1967) 271-72;
David Pugmire, “ ‘Strong’ Self-Deception,” Inquiry 12 (1969)
339-46.
62
John Turk Saunders, “The Parados of Self-Deception,”
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (1975) 561.
63
Herbert Fingarette, Self-Deception (New York: Humanities, 1975)
561.
64
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Blue and Brown Books, (New York: Harper
Torch Books, 1958) 18; Philosophical Investigations (3rd ed.; New
York: Macmillan, 1968), sections 65-71.
65
Sadly we sometimes find both of the two preceding, artificial, and
philosophically unhelpful treatments in popular presentations of Van
Til’s position: e.g., Jim S. Halsey, For a Time Such as This
(Phillipsburg, New Jersey: Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing, 1978),
pp. 63, 66-68.
66
E.g., Paluch, “Self-Deception”; A. E. Murphy, The Theory of Practical
Reason (LaSalle: Open Court Publishing Co., 1965); T. S. Champlin,
“Self-Deception: A Reflexive Dilemma,” Philosophy 52 (July,
1977): 281-299.
67
E.g., H. O. Mounce, “Self-Deception,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, Supplemental Volume 35 (1971): 61-72.
68
E.g., Frederick A. Sigler, “Demos on Lying to Oneself,” The Journal
of Philosophy 59 (Aug. 2, 1962): 469-475; “Self-Deception,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41 (May, 1963): 29-43.
69
E.g., Canfield and Gustavson, “Self-Deception”; Terence Penelhum,
“Pleasure and Falsity,” Philosophy of Mind, ed. Stuart Hampshire
(New York: Harper and Row, 1966), pp. 242-266.
70
E.g., Richard Reilly, “Self-Deception: Resolving the Epistemological
Paradox,” The Personalist 57 (Autumn, 1976): 391.
71
E.g., James M. Shea, “Self-Deception,” Ph.D. dissertation, Cornell
University, 1966 (Ann Arbor, Michigan: Xerox University Microfilms
67-1411); Eugene Valberg, “Rationality and Self-Deception,” Ph.D.
dissertation, State University of New York at Buffalo, 1973 (Ann Arbor,
Michigan: Xerox University Microfilms 73-29,146).
72
E.g., Alan R. Drengson, “Self-Deception,” Ph.D. dissertation, University
of Oregon, 1971 (Ann Arbor, Michigan: Xerox University Microfilms,
72-14,723).
73
E.g., Charles B. Daniels, “Self-Deception and Interpersonal Deception,”
The Personalist 55 (Summer, 1974): 244-252.
74
E.g., D. W. Hamlyn, “Self-Deception,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, Supplemental Volume 35 (1971): 45-60.
75
E.g., Eric J. Lerner, “The Emotions of Self-Deception,” Ph.D.
dissertation, Cornell University, 1975 (Ann Arbor, Michigan: Xerox
University Microfilms, 75-27,038); Sigler, “An Analysis of
Self-Deception,” Nous 2 (May, 1968): 147-164.
76
E.g., John King-Farlow, “Self-deceivers and Sartrian Seducers,”
Analysis 23 (June, 1963): 131-136.
77
E.g., Bela Szabados, “Rorty on Belief in Self-Deception,” Inquiry
17 (Winter, 1974): 464-473; “Self-Deception,” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 4 (September, 1974): 51-68.
78
E.g., Demos, “Lying to Oneself”
79
E.g., Charles D. Bruce, “An Investigation of Self-Deception,” Ph.D.
dissertation, Michigan State University, 1975 (Ann Arbor, Michigan:
Xerox University Microfilms, 75-20,815).
80
E.g., Pugmire, “‘Strong’ Self-Deception”
81
E.g., Gardiner, “Error, Faith, and Self-Deception”
82
E.g., Hamlyn, “Self-Deception”
83
E.g., Saunders, “The Paradox of Self-Deception”
84
E.g., Fingarette, Self-Deception
85
This is especially evident in many treatments of doxastic logic in our
day.
86
Cf. Knowledge and Belief, ed. A. Phillips Griffith (London:
Oxford University Press, 1967); H. H. Price, Belief (London:
George Allen and Unwin, 1969); Robert J. Ackermann, Belief and
Knowledge (Garden City, New York: Anchor Books of Doubleday and Co.,
1972); Belief, Knowledge, and Truth, eds. Robert R. Ammerman and
Marcus G. Singer (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1970); D. M.
Armstrong, Belief, Truth and Knowledge (London: Cambridge
University Press, 1973); J. O. Urmson, “Parenthetical Verbs,” Essays
in Conceptual Analysis, ed. Antony Flew (New York: St. Martin’s
Press, 1956), pp. 192-212; Mitchell Ginsberg, Mind and Belief:
Psychological Ascription and the Concept of Belief (New York:
Humanities Press, 1972); Paul Helm, The Varieties of Belief (New
York: Humanities Press, 1973); F. P. Ramsey, “Last Papers,” The
Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, ed. R. B.
Braithwaite (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1931 1954).
87
Cf. especially the works by Armstrong, Ramsey and Price cited in the
previous footnote.
88
This characterization enables us to distinguish believing from related
notions. Thought is not action-guiding, and judgment is a mental act
rather than state. Hope adds to a propositional belief a valuational
belief pertaining to the proposition. We are only “under an impression”
when the evidence for the proposition cannot be readily adduced. We say
we “suspect that p” when p is deemed a relevant possibility and treated
in hypothetical fashion in our inferences. Suspicion, supposition,
surmise, opinion, thinking and conviction represent degrees of
confidence with which the belief is held (although in common parlance
“belief” itself can denote a particular level on such a scale); they are
distinguished by their varying causal efficacy in guiding one’s
theoretical and practical inferences.
89
Robert Audi, “The Limits of Self-Knowledge,” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 4, no. 2 (December, 1974): 266.
90
Notice that this analysis does not affirm a logical contradiction in S’s
beliefs or a logical contradiction about S. The claim is not that S
believes p and not-p. Nor is the formula that (S believes p) and it is
not the case that (S believes p). We are dealing with two levels of
believing: one is about p, the other is about S. Now then, although it
is not necessary, S’s denial of his belief that p can sometimes take the
form of—or be facilitated by—S coming to believe not-p (as a way of
counteracting S’s belief that p), but even here the appearance of
logical contradiction is avoidable. Rather than saying that S believes p
and not-p, it should be said that (S believes p) and (S believes not-p).
91
When any human activity becomes habitual, one might not always be
fully conscious or aware of what he is purposely doing.
Greg L. Bahnsen page