From
Foundations of Christian Scholarship: Essays in the Van Til Perspective,
edited by Gary North, Ross House Books, Vallecito, CA, 1979,
191-239.
November 2, 2011
The Unsettled and Complex Character of Apologetics
The Basic Question of Method
The Socratic Outlook
The Christian Perspective
Paul’s Apologetic Method: Acts 17
An Overview of the History of Apologetics
The Reformation of Apologetics
Socrates
or Christ: The Reformation of Christian Apologetics (continued)
Greg Bahnsen
The Socratic Outlook
In
Plato’s eyes, Socrates was not a mere sage, cosmologist, or Sophist; he
was the philosopher par excellence.15 Plato’s esteem
is manifest in his description of Socrates as “the finest, most
intelligent, and moral man of his generation.”16 It was
clear even to the ancients that Socrates’ influence was sure to be
weighty, as evident in the testimony of Epictetus: “Even now, although
Socrates is dead, the memory of what he did or said while still alive is
just as helpful or even more so to men.”17
And
judging from the history of philosophy, Epictetus was correct.
Commending his immanentistic motif, Cicero taught that “Socrates was
the first to call philosophy down from the heavens.”18
Commending his foreshadowing of the Renaissance spirit, Erasmus placed
Socrates among the saints and prayed “Sancte Socrates, ora pro nobis!”
[Holy Socrates: pray for us!]19 Commending his anticipation
of Kant’s emphasis upon epistemic subjectivity, Werner Jaeger extolled
him as “the greatest teacher in European history.”20 And
commending his agreement with the modern spirit of autonomy, Antony Flew
presents Socrates’ discussion in Euthyphro as a paradigm of
philosophic argument and progress.21 Socrates provided a
foretaste of Idealism’s resolution of the debate between Parmenides
(static logic) and Heraclitus (historical flux), and yet by teaching the
role of prediction in the notion of knowledge, Socrates looked ahead to
Pragmatism; his independent spirit and reliance upon an inner voice were
a forecast of Existentialism, while his method of critical, dialectical
questioning anticipated linguistic Analysis.22 Obviously his
influence has been pervasive even though his apology before the Athenian
jury did not carry the day. “Indeed, his real defense, as Plato reports
it, was directed to future generations.”23 Throughout those
generations Socrates’ seminal teaching has gained an extensive hearing
among intellectual leaders, and through these implicit disciples
Socrates has even exercised sway over the major defenders of the
Christian faith.
Notwithstanding the fact that Socrates is popularly remembered per se
as a philosopher, the comparison between his method of defense and that
of Paul (or other scriptural writers) is not an uneven one. For
Socrates was an intensely religious thinker (despite the accusation
against him of atheism—which, in Athens, was closely allied to the
charge of treason against the democracy).24 Socrates was
religiously motivated and aimed to provide a religious apologetic. He
viewed himself as divinely commissioned to be “the Athenian gadfly.” In
the Apology, as related through Plato, Socrates recounted how he
would preface his critical discussions with men in Athens by asking if
they did not care for the perfection of their souls. Then Socrates
explained to the jury: “For know that the god commands me to do this,
and I believe that no greater good ever came to pass in the city than my
service to the god” (30a). His divine mission to teach philosophy so as
to perfect men’s souls was deadly serious; with words remarkably like
those of Peter in Acts 5:29, Socrates declared (29d),
If
you say to me, Socrates, this time . . . you shall be let off, but upon
one condition, that you are not to enquire and speculate in this way any
more, and that if you are caught doing so again you shall die;–if this
was the condition on which you let me go, I shall reply: Men of Athens I
honor and love you; but I shall obey God rather than you, and while I
have life and strength I shall never cease from the practice and
teaching of philosophy . . . .25
So
dedicated was Socrates to his divine calling that he would not accept
his legal option of exile as an alternative to execution (cf. Apology,
37; Crito); he explained that to leave Athens would be a betrayal
of his divine mission as a philosopher. In the Phaedo dialogue,
Plato recounted the final conversations between Socrates and his friends
shortly before the death sentence was executed upon him. Here we gain
insight to the high regard Socrates had for philosophy. He says only
those souls purified from bodily taint through philosophy (which aims to
behold truth with the eye of the soul) can escape the cycle of
reincarnation and pass into the company of the gods. Hence philosophy
is no mere academic discipline; it is a way of life and the path to
salvation. In philosophy, then, Socrates found his own self-established
version of “the way, the truth, and the life.”
Salvation would be found, held Socrates, through the exercise of one’s
rational soul. For Socrates, the human mind is a spark of the wisdom
that is immanent in the universe.26 Socrates states in the
Alcibiades (133c), “Can we mention anything more divine about the
soul than what is concerned with knowledge and thought? Then this
aspect of it resembles God, and it is by looking toward that and
understanding all that is divine—God and wisdom—that a man will most
fully know himself.” Elsewhere he declared, “The soul is most like that
which is divine” (Phaedo, 80b). The logos was present within
man, and as Jaeger rightly observed, “in Socrates’ view, the soul is the
divine in man.” After a detailed examination of Socrates’ view of the
soul W. K. C. Guthrie wrote,
To
sum up, Socrates believed in a god who was the supreme mind . . . . Men
moreover had a special relation with him in that their own minds . . .
were, though less perfect than the mind of God, of the same nature, and
worked on the same principles. In fact, if one looked only to the
areté of the human soul and disregarded its shortcomings, the two
were identical.21
In
the Platonic dialogue, Symposium, Socrates taught that the
supreme life is that of the soul’s contemplation of ultimate beauty in
its absolute form; hereby a life of intellectual communion paves the way
for sharing in the divinity of love. In the inner center of mental
contemplation the soul encounters deity and discovers ethical virtue.
As Van Til notes:
He
could find no footing for morality except in the soul as somehow
participant in the laws of another, a higher world. . . . Socrates
sought for a principle of validity by means of his appeal to the logos
... by means of the idea of man’s participation in deity or in an
abstract principle of rationality, the logos.28
Whereas the Council of Chalcedon declared that in Christ the
eternal and temporal are united without intermixture, Socrates
proclaimed that the eternal and temporal are combined in man by
way of admixture.29 And so it is that Socrates was the
prophet of the religion of immanent reason. He had a divine commission
and a message to be proclaimed even upon pain of death—a message of
salvation through the incarnate logos, that is, the rational soul within
man. All of life and every thought had to be brought under obedience to
the lordship of man’s reason. Let there be no doubt then, that Socrates
was a religious apologist, just as J. T. Forbes recognized:
By
the testimony of his principal disciples, the whole life of Socrates was
pervaded by the thought of God. . . . It was the sane religion of one
who had found a faith that could bear the examination of his mind. . . .
As he comes before us, it is as one who has reasoned and wrought his way
to a rational creed.30
With
such a view of man’s rational faculty as outlined above, Socrates was
quite naturally led to exalt the intellect, to commend a neutral
methodology, and to insist upon autonomy as an
epistemological standard.
In
the Protagoras, Socrates established that virtue is not a skill,
but is knowledge; consequently, virtue can be taught. The same
conclusion was wrought in the Meno dialogue, where virtue is
identified with knowledge, and knowledge is taken to be a gift of the
gods. The result of Socrates’ stress upon the intellect and his
equation of virtue and knowledge was the doctrine that no man knowingly
does evil. This point is argued in the Gorgias. Socrates said that all
men desire to act for the sake of some good, and hence any man who acts
wrongly must be acting in ignorance of the evil he does (in which case
punishment should aim at rehabilitation through education). If “virtue
is the knowledge of the good,” then an unvirtuous act is one done
without knowledge of the good; thus no man deliberately or knowingly
does evil. Wrongdoing must be involuntary or, ignorant. In this
Socrates declared, against the testimony of Paul in Romans 7, that men
are not totally depraved—in which case man’s reason is not defective due
to the domination of sin. Indeed, just the opposite: man’s intellect,
as the faculty whereby knowledge is gained, must be viewed as virtuous.
Socrates exalted the intellect of man as the primary faculty, one which
as a charioteer must hold in check the horses of will and passion (Phaedrus);
all the particulars of human experience must be subordinated under the
ordering domination of the reason. Therefore, according to Socratic
anthropology, man’s reason is not steeped in sin, but man’s virtuous
intellect keeps control over his irrational drives. One can and must
trust his reason to guide him toward the good.
There are three notable characteristics of knowledge in the view of
Socrates. First, as he argued in the Meno, in the course of
endless reincarnations, men’s souls have become acquainted with the
eternal forms and thus know all things. When man comes to know
something in this life, then, it is not a matter of acquiring some new
thing but simply the recollection of something previously known. Hence
knowledge is innate in man.
Secondly, we find out in the Theaetetus that mere sense
perception is inadequate as a source of knowledge. There must be
something which is exempt from the constant, Heraclitean flux of
historical particulars that are perceived by the senses; otherwise there
could be no knowledge whatsoever. The world of sense experience is, as
recognized by Heraclitus, in continual movement or alteration. Yet
insofar as this world is known, it must be viewed against an unchanging
set of concepts having the character of the Parmenidean One. The
principle of unity as well as the principle of diversity must be
incorporated in knowledge. The absolute flux of historical particulars,
all diverse from each other, would be unknowable; however, the supremely
knowable, unifying forms or concepts of reason are purely abstract and
void of content. Therefore, knowledge is a combination of both the
changing and the unchanging. Knowledge combines sense perception with
an ordering judgment of the mind. Sense perception triggers a
recollection of permanent, immutable forms of the non-material realm
above history (cf. Phaedo, 75e). Socrates’ characteristic
contribution to the advance of epistemology, said Aristotle, was
twofold: (1) induction, and (2) general definition.31
Socrates was inductive because he moved from the many or particulars to
the one or universal; yet he aimed at logical precision by organizing
the particulars under general principles.32 Induction led to
general definition, for a definition consists of a collection of
essential (rather than accidental) attributes which are jointly
sufficient to delineate one class of objects from another. This general
definition was called the form (eidos) of the class, its
essential nature. In a unique and forceful way Socrates (as spokesman
for Plato) dialectically combined continuity (general principles)
and discontinuity (particular facts) in his epistemological theory.
Thirdly, according to Socrates (again in the Meno) knowledge
requires the ability to give the grounds upon which an answer is
established—the logos of any ousia mentioned. True opinion is
insufficient as a criterion of knowledge, for like the statue of
Daedalus, unless it is tied down it walks away. Holding an opinion
which is in fact correct, but being unable to give a reason for that
opinion, does not qualify as knowledge (cf. Symposium, 202a).
The proper grounding of true opinion is to be found in recollection of
the truth, a kind of intuitive or direct apprehension of the absolute
idea or form. Hereby true opinion is converted into completely adequate
knowledge.
Since Socrates viewed man’s reason as normal or untainted by the effects
of sin, because he had a rationalized view of knowledge and the inward
adequacy of man’s mind, he was led to extol intellectual independence
and neutrality in the search for truth. The philosopher supposedly has
learned to avoid the deceptions of sense perception and to refrain from
following the untrustworthy leading of emotions; for the philosopher,
the soul relies on its own intellectual capability. In the Phaedo,
Socrates taught that the soul “will calm passion, and follow reason, and
dwell in the contemplation of her, beholding the true and divine” (84a).
Expanding upon this in the Crito, Socrates described the
rational man as an independent thinker who is neutral in his approach to
truth. The philosopher should be a completely detached, rational
thinker who refuses to heed popular opinion in order to follow after the
truth wherever it may be. Here we find the self-sufficient, impartial,
intellectual. Hear the Socratic exhortation:
My
dear Crito, . . . we must examine the question whether we ought to do
this or not; for I am not only now but always a man who follows nothing
but the reasoning which on consideration seems to me best. . . . Then,
most excellent friend, we must not consider at all what the many will
say of us, but what he knows about right and wrong, the one man, and
truth herself will say.33
It
is significant that, having claimed that he followed nothing but reason
in his intellectual queries, Socrates came to the conclusion of his line
of thought and said, “Then, Crito, let be, and let us act in this way,
since it is in this way that God leads us.”34 Reason’s
leading is tacitly assumed to be God’s leading—in which case the
philosopher really is inwardly sufficient, and therefore he is in need
of no transcendent revelation in order to carry out the epistemological
enterprise. Moreover, nothing could be a more secure method of
countenancing and vindicating God’s thoughts than utter self-reliance
upon one’s reasoning ability. To such intellectual independence and
self-confidence Socrates was dedicated, advocating that men should
follow the critical test of reason alone: “The life not tested by
criticism is not worth living,” he declared in his Apology (38a).
Dogmatism is to be forever banished from philosophy in favor of a
completely detached, impartial, neutral search for truth and reality.
In short, conclude Peterfreund and Denise: “The procedures of analysis
themselves must be metaphysically neutral, in the sense that they
involve the testing of philosophical proposals by universal standards of
reason. . . . This feature of neutrality is well illustrated in the
dialogues of Plato.”35
The
motto which Socrates set forth to the world was the Delphic inscription,
“Know thyself’ (e.g., Philebus, 48c), from which it is evident
that his challenge to relativistic and agnostic Sophism did not include
renunciation of the anthropocentricity of the Sophists. Socrates
countered the scepticism of the Sophists by stressing rational, inward
self-sufficiency as the crucial foundation of epistemology. Socrates
took the autonomous man as his starting point—the man who, as a law unto
himself, can adequately arrive at self-knowledge through rational
introspection and from that base move out to comprehend the truth beyond
him. The Sophist, Protagoras, said, “Man is the measure of all things,”
meaning that all sense experience is subjective and all laws are mere
conventions. That perspective led to scepticism and cynicism. In order
to restore objectivity to knowledge, Socrates appealed to reason, but
reason which was nevertheless man-centered or autonomous, just as it was
for the Sophists.
Thus, by appealing to reason, that is to the universal aspect in man,
Socrates saved the objectivity of both knowledge and ethics. He saved
both because saving one is, in effect, saving the other. Saving
knowledge is saving virtue, for knowledge is virtue. Thus Socrates was
a “restorer of faith.” . . . There is only one remedy for the ills of
thought, and that is, more thought. If thought, in its first inroads,
leads, as it always does, to scepticism and denial, the only course is,
not to suppress thought, but to found faith upon it. Socrates agreed
with the Sophists that the truth must be my truth, but mine “in my
capacity as a rational being.”36
Socrates did not take an approach fundamentally different from the
Sophists; he simply placed faith in man’s autonomous intellect (as a
spark from the wisdom or logos above the material world). Reason is a
divine element in man, worthy of religious trust and devotion. The
Sophists had not heeded this gospel, this good news which saves the
epistemological enterprise. “Socrates was destined to restore order out
of chaos because, though with Sophists appealing to the self, he
appealed to the self as carrying within itself the universal principle
of reason and order.”37 Like the Sophists, Socrates began
with man and centered his attention on man;38 unlike the
Sophists, he placed supreme confidence in reason as something within man
which participates in the abstract and universal laws of a higher world.39
Thus
it was appropriate that the Danish irrationalist, Søren Kierkegaard,
characterized Socrates as having a “passion of inwardness.” While
Socrates exalted reason and Kierkegaard deprecated its ultimate
usefulness, they both found it necessary to begin their respective
philosophies with man’s self-sufficient, inward experience of eternity
in time. Man’s inward autonomy was crucial to Socratic thinking. Van
Til explains that “the Socratic spirit of Inwardness” is “the
concentration of all interpretation upon man as the final reference
point.”40 Socrates took the knowledge of himself to be so
clear that he could use it as the basis for intelligibly interpreting
the world outside him. Man’s mind supposedly participates in the
abstract principle of absolute truth; a knowledge of the forms is innate
to man. Consequently, to understand anything at all, man has to look to
himself and autonomously interpret his experience in the authoritative
light of his own reason.
“Socrates sought to answer the sceptics in his day by thinking of the
individual soul as participant in an objective world of intelligence”;
however, as entrapped in the prison of the body, man’s soul (said Plato)
has to be lifted to this world of light by Diotima the inspired.41
Man in his individuality, man as discontinuous from others because of
his particular body, man in his character as participant in the
irrational flux of history, is made the sovereign judge of truth by
Socrates. But in order to determine the truth for himself, this man
must somehow loosen the shackles of the body and philosophically
contemplate the abstract, universal forms of the world of pure being.
In the long run, as Antony Flew has observed, knowledge for Socrates
ceases to have any connection with the historical world.42
In the Phaedo, Socrates says that the philosopher who seeks
knowledge is always pursuing death, seeing that the body hinders the
soul’s search for knowledge; the attempt to apprehend the forms and
thereby find knowledge is an attempt to leave behind the historical
world of particulars. Therefore, Van Til rightly parallels Socrates to
his Sophist opponents:
The
objectivity for knowledge and ethics . . . which Socrates found by
appealing to reason as the universal aspect in man, turns out to be an
empty form, and there is no connection of this abstract universal with
particulars except in terms of an irrational principle. In other words,
Socrates, as well as the Sophists, has finally come back to the realm of
pure contingency. Thus we are back to the Sophistic notion that in
practice there is no known validity to any moral law except what man,
irrational in his individuality, is willing to approve.43
Making man epistemologically autonomous requires the combination of
rationality and irrationality. For historical, particular man to know
anything he would finally have to cease being an individual man, and for
knowledge to be grasped by individual man it would have to cease being
universally objective truth in some suprahistorical realm. Socrates
attempted to make man the measure of truth, thereby trying to combine
oil and water—trying to mix universally rational truth into irrationally
particularized (historical) man. The autonomy involved in the Socratic
“passion for inwardness” could lead to nothing but a dialectical
epistemology.
Regarding Socratic inwardness, Van Til says, “This principle is that the
ultimate distinctions between true and false, right and wrong, are to be
made by man as ultimate.”44 Perhaps this anthropocentric,
autonomous epistemology is nowhere more clearly expressed by Socrates
than in the Euthyphro dialogue. The Euthyphro portrays
Socrates shortly before his trial in Athens. Socrates, having been
charged with corrupting the youth and with religious offenses, happened
to meet Euthyphro, who was piously bringing charges against his own
father, at the Porch of King Archon. Socrates asked Euthyphro to
instruct him in order that he might more adequately defend himself
against Meletus in court. Socrates inquired as to the distinction
between piety and impiety. When Euthyphro justified the piety of what
he was doing to his father by appealing to the fact that Zeus had
punished his own father, Cronos, for committing a similar crime,
Socrates treated the answer as merely one more report among many of what
happens in history. There is nothing special about the activity of the
gods. What is needed, said Socrates, is not an example of piety, but a
general statement of the essential characteristic of piety. Indeed,
general knowledge is crucial for correctly identifying the particular
cases. Hence Euthyphro offered a definition which is formally more
adequate: “What is pleasing to the gods is pious, and what is not
pleasing to them is impious.” Then the crucial reply of the dialogue
was rendered by Socrates: Do the gods love piety because it is pious,
or is it pious because the gods love it? Socrates holds that piety has
certain characteristics which make it pious in itself—irrespective of
what the gods may think about it. Thus man should seek a knowledge of
piety (or anything else) by self-sufficient, autonomous investigation
into the nature of things, not by relying upon the actions, attitudes,
or revelation of the gods. At best, the word or opinion of the gods is
just one hypothesis among many to be confirmed or discomfirmed by the
rational man. Man is the ultimate judge or discerner of goodness,
truth, and the like; as such, he can and must critically scrutinize even
the opinions of the gods. By what standard should truth or knowledge be
measured? The rational intellect of man, not the revelation of the
gods. To find the truth, man’s soul must look to itself; to regard the
word of an authority as anything more than incidental information would
conflict with the very idea of man’s knowledge as sufficient to itself.
Here
is illustrated, then, the Socratic exaltation of the intellect, the
absolute requirement of impartial or neutral investigation for the
truth, and the final epistemological standard of sheer autonomy.
Socrates was the prophet of the religion of sovereign, self-sufficient,
authoritative reason; to put it as Werner Jaeger does, Socrates was
the
apostle of moral liberty, bound by no dogma, fettered by no
traditions, standing free on his own feet, listening only to the
inner voice of conscience—preaching the new religion of this
world, and a heaven to be found in this life by our own spiritual
strength, not through grace but through tireless striving to perfect our
own nature.45
The
religion of this world has a definite doctrine of authority;
whether in epistemology or any other field, the voice of authority
must be found in man himself. Socrates would not have man
relinquish his autonomy at any cost. If man is to follow the gods, it
must be on man’s own terms—namely, that the gods first be scrutinized
and approved by the rational judgment of man. In Athens, the views of
deity were expressed through the public opinion of the democracy.
Socrates resisted such dogma in favor of a more self-conscious and
consistent religion of autonomy—for which he finally stood trial. J. T.
Forbes has aptly commented:
The
question of the seat of authority has lasted through the ages, and the
Socratic transference of it to the reflective reason, of which his very
discussions on piety and justice were the claim, demanded an insight and
moral earnestness too great for the mass of his fellows. [Yet] the
trend of progress of the human mind was with him.46
Socrates was a pioneer and religious apologist for the religion of the
world; his martyred blood served as just so much seed for spreading the
gospel of man’s epistemological self-authority, a dogma which he had
brought to purest expression.
With
this background to the influence, religion, and epistemology of
Socrates, we can now take note of the way in which Socrates carried on
his apologetic before the Athenian jury. The Apology, along with
Crito and Phaedo, forms a trilogy dealing with the final
days of Socrates. The enmity of Socrates’ accusers had been generated
by his disdain for the democracy and public opinion; Socrates practiced
a religious devotion to the pursuit of ultimate truth by following the
guidance of independent reason alone. The accusations brought by
Meletus had now put Socrates in the position of presenting an apology
for his faith. Five strands of defense can be traced in his apologetic
strategy.
First, there is the validation of the Oracle’s statement by factual
testing. Chaerephon had asked the Oracle at Delphi whether anyone was
wiser than Socrates, and he received “No” for his answer. That puzzled
Socrates, and so he set out to find a wiser man. Socrates took it to be
his religious duty to determine the Oracle’s meaning, to prove by
factual methods that the god was right. To establish that the Oracle
was neither lying nor incorrect, Socrates made it his job to expose the
ignorance of supposedly wise men in Athens—thereby corroborating that he
was, by recognition of his lack of wisdom, really the wisest of men,
just as the Oracle had said.
Secondly, in his apologetic strategy Socrates made use of the logical
test for coherence. Socrates had been charged with atheism or impiety;
as children, his audience had heard (for instance, in Aristophanes’
comedy, The Clouds) that Socrates pursued naturalistic scientific
investigations; additionally one of the youths whom Socrates had
corrupted, Alcibiades, had been blamed for the mutilation of the statues
of Hermes—the obscene adornments of every Athenian front doorway—on the
night before the military expedition to Sicily. These things might be
behind the charge of atheism. However, Socrates rehearsed that Meletus,
in the statement of the charges, had accused Socrates “of believing in
deities of his own invention instead of the gods recognized by the
State.” As demonstration of his own logical prowess, Socrates pointed
out that Meletus had contradicted himself. Socrates was charged
simultaneously for believing in no gods, and yet for believing in new
deities and supernatural activities (namely, the divine inner voice).
Socrates tied other logical knots in the prosecution’s case. By
questioning Meletus, Socrates got him to say that the best influence on
youth comes from the many citizens of Athens (rather than from the
individual, Socrates), but the best training in other fields (e.g.,
raising horses) comes from the one individual expert (rather than the
incompetent many). Moreover, it is unlikely that he would intentionally
corrupt the youth, for that would generate a corrupting influence upon
himself through his own associates. Thus, if indeed Socrates had
corrupted the youth, it must have been unintentional—in which case he
has an admonition coming, but not punishment. Logic was a tool in
Socrates’ arsenal.
Third, Socrates followed the apologetic line that the jury should take
into account the great benefit which his divine service has been to the
city. Socrates had urged men to put the welfare of their souls above
all else, and Socratic philosophy demonstrated how they should do this.
Therefore, if the Athenians executed Socrates, they would actually be
inflicting great harm on themselves. They would lose the restraining
voice of Socrates, asking “Are you not ashamed that you give your
attention to acquiring as much money as possible, and similarly with
reputation and honor, and give no attention or thought to truth and
understanding and the perfection of your soul?” (29e). Socrates
defended himself, then, by appealing to the elevated, noble, and
beneficial results of his service and outlook.
Fourth, Socrates took the apologetical approach of asking the jury to
examine the life of the speaker. Socrates had given loyal service to
the military. He had continually sought to follow the path of acting
rightly, whatever the personal outcome would be for him. He was not
fearful of death. He had given his life in the service of others, being
sent as a gadfly by God to Athens in order to keep it from becoming lazy
like a large thoroughbred horse. His sincerity is evident from the fact
that he lived in poverty, neglecting private affairs so as to fulfill
his divine duty. Obviously the religious philosophical outlook of
Socrates had transformed him into a praiseworthy individual, good
citizen, and public servant. And so he proclaimed in his defense, “You
will not easily find another like me, gentlemen, and if you take my
advice you will spare my life” (31a).
Finally, after the appeal to fact, logic, beneficial effect, and
personal betterment, Socrates came to use in his apology the appeal to
inner guidance. In answer to why he had not entered political service
which would have been consonant with his convictions (if sincerely
stated), Socrates claimed that he had been forbidden to carry his
convictions to that consistent outcome by a divine voice which
occasionally came to him. “Plato explicitly represents Socrates turning
to an inner voice (daimon)—a voice that is a product neither of
social conditioning nor of reason—at crucial moments of decision.”47
“There is no question whatever that he himself regarded it as Heaven
sent.”48 Socrates explained this inward, validating,
convicting voice in this way: “something divine and spiritual comes to
me. . . . I have had this from my childhood; it is a sort of voice that
comes to me, and when it comes it always holds me back from what I am
thinking of doing” (31d). Socrates even used this subjectivistic
apologetic to lend support to his four other lines of defense. At the
end of the trial, after the guilty verdict had been presented, Socrates
said that in nothing he had done or said that day had the inner voice
opposed him, even though in the past it sometimes would stop him in the
middle of a sentence. Thus his other apologetic devices received
subjective validation.
Here
we have the five-point apologetic method of Socrates.
·
He was
dedicated to the autonomy of man’s reason and to neutrality in the
search for truth, wherever it should be found.
·
He
enthroned man’s intellect as the epistemological authority, even over
the opinions of deity.
·
He was
the rational man, unfettered by dogma and public opinion.
·
Whatever views were to be held had first to pass the scrutiny of his
self-sufficient mind.
·
His
apologetic strategy was both rational (appealing to logical coherence)
and irrational (appealing to subjectivistic conviction), factual
(verifying the Oracle’s words through experimentation) and pragmatic
(looking to the beneficial results, both public and personal, of his
practice and convictions).
As
Peterfreund and Denise rightly observe, Socrates’ efforts to meet his
own criterion of the critically examined life were “characterized by a
strange tension.”49 Somehow, he was simultaneously the
unique, self-determining, inner-directed adjudicator of all claims to
knowledge and the dispassionate, objective observer of that realm of
truth which unifies all minds. W. T. Jones says,
He
must have seemed to his fellow citizens more like a Sophist than
anything else. But he had a profound, and entirely un-Sophistic,
conviction of the reality of goodness, the goodness of reality, and the
immortality of the human soul. He combined an intensely realistic and
down-to-earth common sense with a passionate mysticism; a cool and
dispassionate scepticism about ordinary beliefs and opinions with a deep
religious sense.50
Socrates could claim in one and the same dialogue (as he did in the
Meno) that he was both as ignorant as his opponents and yet
omniscient as a result of his preexistent awareness of the forms. He
claimed to accept nothing except upon critical and reasonable scrutiny,
and yet he accepted the authority of the expert (as in the Crito)
and followed the leading of a non-rational daimon (as evidenced
in the Apology). He said that nobody knows about death, and yet
that he knew enough not to fear it (cf. Apology, 29a). His
autonomous apologetic was a strange combination of omnicompetent reason
and mysticism, faith in himself alone, yet ready trust in the divine.
To protect his autonomy Socrates was forced back and forth between the
poles of rationality and irrationality. “What Socrates did was to
rationalize the known, and to make the mysterious the divine.”51
This
procedure is virtually identical with the two-step apologetic method of
Roman Catholicism and Arminianism (represented by Aquinas and Butler
respectively). The field of knowledge is dichotomized into truths known
by reason and truths known by “faith.” At the outset, the apologist
proceeds with self-sufficient reason to establish general truths about
God or a probability in favor of them, but after this first level is
built, the apologist then completes the edifice by appeals to faith and
revelation. Supposedly a set area of the known can be rationalized, but
the remainder must be relegated to divine mystery. A dialectical dance
between rationality and irrationality always results from taking an
autonomous, neutral approach to apologetics; such an approach is
inherently destructive of the concept of authority in Christianity.
Speaking of the Romanist and Arminian notion of authority, Van Til
says:
But
such a concept of authority resembles that which Socrates referred to in
The Symposium when he spoke of Diotima the inspired. When the
effort at rational interpretation failed him, Socrates took refuge in
mythology as a second best. The “hunch” of the wise is the best that is
available to man with respect to that which he cannot reach by the
methods of autonomous reason. No “wise man” ought to object to such a
conception of the “supernatural.” . . . If the Roman Catholic method of
apologetic for Christianity is followed then Christianity itself must be
so reduced as to make it acceptable to the natural man. . . . The
natural man need only to reason consistently along the lines of his
starting point and method in order to reduce each of the Christian
doctrines that are presented to him to naturalistic proportions.52
Socrates transferred the seat of authority to man’s autonomous reason;
Roman Catholic and Arminian apologetics follow suit, thereby evidencing
the justice of J. T. Forbes’s earlier comment about the Socratic view of
reason and authority: “The trend of progress of the human mind was with
him.”
Notes
15
The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards (New York:
Macmillan, 1967), VI, 216.
16
Phaedo, 118.
17
Discourses, IV, I, 169.
18
Tusculan Disputations, V, 4, 10.
19
Cited by Werner Jaeger, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1945), II, book 3.
20
Ibid.
21
An Introduction to Western Philosophy (London: Thames and Hudson,
1971), p. 28.
22
S. P. Peterfreund and T. C. Denise, Contemporary Philosophy and Its
Origins (New Jersey: D. Van Nostrand, 1967), pp. 63-69, 123-124,
182-185,232-239.
23
W. T. Jones, A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Harcourt,
Brace, and World, 1952), I, 96.
24
Ibid., pp. 58,95-96. The actual indictment, recorded for us by
both Xenophon and Diogenes Laertius, read, “Socrates is guilty of
refusing to recognize the gods recognized by the state and introducing
other, new divinities. He is also guilty of corrupting the youth.”
Because the state was a religious institution dedicated to Athena, the
charge of “irreligion” could apply to any offense against the state.
Socrates was a critic of the traditional establishment education (cf.
Aristophanes’ The Clouds) and thereby a corruptor of youth;
Socrates saw this as the real issue, as evidenced by his conversation in
the Euthyphro (2c-3d). Zeller states that, while it was not the
primary motive, “Socrates, it is true, fell as a sacrifice to the
democratic reaction which followed the overthrow of the Thirty. . . .
His guilt was sought first of all in the undermining of the morality and
religion of his country . . . “(Die Philosophie der Griechen, 2.
Teil, I. Abteilung, Sokrates . . . , 5. Auflage, Leipzig, 1922,
p. 217).
25
B. Jowett, trans., The Dialogues of Plato (New York: Random
House, 1937), I, 412. The reader should note that in the account of
Socrates which follows I have not attempted to separate the historical
Socrates from Socrates-the spokesman-for-Plato. Such a delicate and
debated task would be tangential to this essay. For present purposes,
the view of “Socrates” given herein stems uncritically from the Platonic
dialogues; thus “Socrates” tends to become a label for a
Platonic-Socratic hybrid. This is adequate for the purposes of contrast
with the scriptural outlook.
26
Cf. Xenophon, Memorabilia I, iv, 8.
27
W. K. C. Guthrie, Socrates (Cambridge: University Press, 1971),
p. 156.
28
Christian Theistic Ethics, In Defense of the Faith, vol. III
(Nutley, N. J.: den Dulk Christian Foundation, 1971), p. 183.
29
Ct. Cornelius Van Til, A Survey of Christian Epistemology, In
Defense of the Faith, vol. II (Nutley, N. J.: den Dulk Christian
Foundation, 1969), p. 31.
30
J. T. Forbes, Socrates (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1905),
pp. 212, 213. No less an authority than W. K. C. Guthrie has said with
respect to the religious character of Socrates’ thought: “Belief in a
special, direct relation between himself and divine forces must be
accepted in any account of his mentality which lays claim to
completeness” (Socrates, p. 84).
31
Metaphysics, 1078b, 27.
32
Francis N. Lee, A Christian Introduction to the History of Philosophy
(Nutley, N. J.: Craig Press, 1969), p. 83.
33
H. N. Fowler, tr., Crito, in the Loeb Classical Library
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1924), at 46b.
34
Ibid.,
54e, emphasis my own.
35
Peterfreund and Denise, op. cit., p. 237.
36
Van Til, Christian Theistic Ethics, pp. 160, 161.
37
Ibid., p. 159.
38
Lee, p. 81.
39
Cf. Herman Dooyeweerd, A New Critique of Theoretical Thought,
tr., D. H. Freeman and H. De Jongste (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and
Reformed, 1955), I, 51, 355.
40
Cornelius Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge (Philadelphia:
Presbyterian and Reformed, 1969), p. 144.
41
Ibid., p. 153.
42
Flew,
p. 77.
43
Christian Theistic Ethics, p. 162.
44
Ibid., p. 173.
45
Jaeger, loc. cit., emphasis mine.
46
Forbes, op. cit., p. 270.
47
Peterfreund and Denise, op. cit., p. 184.
48
J. T. Forbes, op. cit., p. 221. Guthrie says, “he put himself
unreservedly in the hands of what he sincerely believed to be an
inspiration from heaven” (op. cit., p. 163).
49
Peterfrund and Denise, op. cit., p. 183.
50
Jones, op. cit., p. 93.
51
Forbes, op. cit., p. 230.
52
The Defense of the Faith (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and
Reformed, 1955), p. 127.
Next:
The
Christian Perspective
Return to beginning of
Socrates or Christ: The Reformation of Christian Apologetics
Greg L. Bahnsen page