Susan K. Langer’s
Theory of Feeling and Mind
Peter
A. Bertocci
I find Susanne K. Langer’s Mind:
An Essay on Human Feeling, Volume I, fascinating. I am not
sure that my interpretation is correct, but the work of such a
sensitive, broadly cultivated philosopher warrants analysis. After
Volume II appears we shall have a form of naturalism that feeds on such
thinkers as James, Santayana, Bergson, Croce, and Whitehead, and is
inspired by a concern that the aesthetic life become a formative factor
in metaphysical theorizing.
While I cannot conclude that Langer
is successful so far in this formidable undertaking, I find myself not
only resonating to much that she sets out but also applauding the
attempt to develop a philosophy of mind in a new key. Surely, to decide
what we mean by mind without reference to the mind-in-art is myopic
philosophizing. No systematic metaphysician can but be grateful for the
attempt to show that in the nature of feeling as found in art there is a
kind of organization that will enable us to get beyond the persistent
frustrations created by a dualistic view of mind and body, and will
possibly give us a clue even to the dynamics of physical beings.
Does Langer
manage to balance herself on this philosophic tight-rope when it is so
easy to sway from the organic to the aesthetic and from
the aesthetic to the organic, and to do so because balance must
be achieved as one sways? The risk of a slip on this tight-rope is
great and I can only admire even when I think I see her lose her
balance. In the first part of this limited essay I shall discuss her
theory of feeling and mind generally; in the second and third parts I
shall be expounding and evaluating her attempt to escape dualism and to
account for the unity and continuity of mind respectively.
I. Is Feeling the Key
to the Mind-Body Problem?
Langer’s empiricism is restricted by
neither a theistic teleology nor by any scientific framework that
amputates problems which do not fit the Procrustean bed of its method.
Her central vision of man involves total qualitative difference between
man and animal. Poetry is no “mere” animal reaction formed by natural
selection. “Some animals are intelligent, but only man can be
intellectual” (pp. xvi, xvii).
Langer is unyielding in her
anti-reductionism; but she is also adamant in refusing to travel some
non-zoological bridge across the Rubicon between mind and body. Neither
an extension “upward” from the physical nor an extension “downward” from
the nonphysical will do. She places her trust in what she calls “a
biological theory of feeling” (pp. xviii, xix).
But why feeling? And why feeling as
expressed in art and not in religion or morality? First, because works
of art are always “images of the forms of feeling,” and their
expressiveness “can rise to the presentation of all aspects of mind and
human personality” (p. xviii). Second, because in such feeling she
thinks she can find a means of avoiding any sharp breaks between
mentality and vitality.
How does she manage this? As far as
I can see, by finding a common factor in organic life and in art. In her
own words:
The fact that expressive form is
always organic or “living” form made the biological foundation of
feeling probable. In the artist’s projection, feeling is a heightened
form of life; so any work expressing felt tensions, rhythms and
activities expresses their unfelt substructure of vital processes, which
is the whole of life. If vitality and feeling are conceived in this way
there is no sharp break, let alone metaphysical gap, between physical
and mental realities, yet there are thresholds where mentality begins,
and especially where human mentality transcends the animal level, and
mind, sensu stricto, emerges. (p. xix)
Of course there is much more in such
a summary statement than meets the eye. But it helps us to focus on the
underlying problem right away. Exactly what is involved in the relation
of the “heightening” of feeling in the artist’s projection and the
heightening of the tensions in the vital process? Is there enough
similarity or identity to justify this biological view of feeling? In
the last analysis it seems to me asserted as a hypothesis which will
presumably enable one to escape a metaphysical gap. Yet in almost the
same breath what is asserted is both continuity and a mild break between
the organic and the mental. For feeling as mentality transcends
vitality. Is what I have called a mild break not a break? Langer in
her anti-reductionism and in her resistance to identity theories of mind
and body calls for recognition of real discontinuity; yet in her
antidualism she insists on continuity. But in either case her direct
appeal is to the kind of feeling as expressed in art. Whether this way
of dealing with what for her are impasses is viable remains for us to
see.
(a) What is feeling? There
is no doubt that, for Langer, feeling is the mark of mentality. But how
is feeling defined? Ordinarily we think of that range of experiences
which we classify as pleasant or unpleasant. At the very outset Langer
rejects such a view as too restrictive. She admittedly uses feeling “in
the broad sense of whatever is felt in any way, as sensory stimulus or
inward tension, pain, emotion or intent,” as “the mark of mentality” (p.
4). Thus, organic activity as such, as in plants, is not mental, since
in them there is no perceiving and controlling of the environment as in
animals.
Langer asks us to
avoid another “basic misconception . . . the assumption of feelings
(sensations, emotions, etc.) as items or entities of any kind,
whether produced by physiological processes, or independent of them. . .
. This is a genuine metaphysical fallacy” (p. 19). Rather must we
realize that feeling is a verbal noun that originates in the verb “to
feel,” that is, “to do something, not to have something” (p. 20), such
as a feeling or a sensation.
It is this
reconstructed view of feeling that is to save us from physicalism and
dualism. It is proposed on the assumption that the existence of organic
life is the acceptable base for this non-entitative theory of feeling.
Hence Langer says: “What is felt [as the object of feel] is a
process, perhaps a large complex of processes, within the organism.
Some vital activities of great complexity and high intensity, usually
(perhaps always) involving nervous tissue, are felt; being felt is a
phase of the process itself. A phase is a mode of appearance, and not
an added factor” (p. 21).
What is important
about this phasal theory of feeling and mind must not escape us. “Being
felt,” is a phase that comes and goes in the organism. Langer compares
it to the redness that appears as a phase of certain degrees of heat in
the iron. Feeling is “an appearance which organic functions have only
for the organism in which they occur, if they have it at all” (p. 21).
Again, among the millions of biological processes that go unfelt in the
organism, one may say that “some activities, especially nervous ones,
above a certain (probably fluctuating) limen of intensity, enter into a
‘psychical phase’” (p. 22). The immediately following passage is
decisive:
This [psychical phase] is the phase
of being felt. It may develop suddenly, with great distinctness of
quality, location and value-character, for instance, in response to a
painful stimulus; or similarly, only with less precise location in the
organism, like a shock of terror; or a deeply engendered process may go
gradually, perhaps barely, into a psychical phase of vague
awareness—come and gone—a sense of weariness or a fleeting emotive
moment. The normal substrata of a “feeling-tone,” from which the more
acute tensions build up into specific experiences, is probably a dynamic
pattern of nervous activities playing freely across the limen of
sentience. (p. 22)
To summarize: the feeling phase of
the intra-organic process is, if I may so put it, the “announcement,”
the “product” of the organism’s own state. This capacity for feeling,
this being felt phase, is missing in inorganic things and plants.
Being felt includes a whole range of phasal events, moving from sensory
awareness and specificity of response to fleeting, vague or intense
emotive states (“terror” or “a sense of weariness”). My exposition will
continue in relation to several questions that this view of feeling, as
a solution to the mind-body problem, must confront.
(i) If there are
no feelings without intra-organic processes of a certain kind, and if
these processes, as felt, are in a certain phase, does the “being felt”
“appear” and “go” without modifying the processes? Will it do to answer
(as in the quotation above) that a phase is a mode of appearance and not
an added factor? It is one thing to say that like the redness of heated
iron it is not a thing, but, I must suggest, if it makes a difference it
is an added factor of some sort that the ascription “phasal” must not
deny. Hence I think it reasonable to ask, even
at this non-metaphysical level of analysis: What difference does “being
felt” (or mentality) make to the intra-organic processes to which it is
phasal or from which it “emerges” as phasal?
(ii) But is this view of feeling
capable of keeping both direct experience and hypothesized fact together
non-dualistically? Thus, to say that “the normal substrata
of ‘feeling-tone’ . . . is probably a dynamic pattern of nervous
activities playing freely across the limen of sentience” (p. 22), is to
be hypothetical, for certainly there is no direct experience of the
neural activities as defined by the physiologist. Being felt,
mentality, adds something to them; the spectre of unwanted duality
reappears. In a footnote on page 21 Langer says that, like William
James, she is looking for a generic term for mental states at large,
irrespective of their kind, but that unlike James she decided on feeling
where James decided on thoughts. One asks: Why? And the only plausible
answer seems to be that she thinks that feeling as she defines it can be
“in” intra-organic states. Interestingly enough, for James, in this
period, thoughts as states of consciousness are together as owned in
personal consciousness. But for Langer intra-organic processes are by
definition unaware of their “being felt” phase. The problem we face
here is whether Langer can point to any common factor that justifies the
word “feeling” or “feelings”—apart from the problem of unity-continuity
to be considered in section III below.
Further, if the neural activities as
such are not themselves aware of the feelings which occur, why should
feelings not be considered as epiphenomenal emergents despite
protestations to the contrary? But if feelings have no autonomy, can
they be possibly used to describe the experience, as phasal to our
mental life, of the autonomy of feeling we find in art? Let us take a
closer look.
(b) Is dualism
in fact avoided? Langer is proposing a feeling (psychical) phase of
a total organism that may be elaborated into the more specific
experiences of sense, emotion, and thought. She continues to warn us
against a substantive view of feeling, and yet seeks for some source of
such unity and change as we find in “feeling.” Hence she says, “it is
this transiency and general ability of the psychical phase that
accounts for the importance of
preconscious processes in the construction of such elaborate phenomena
as ideas, intentions, images and fantasies, and makes it not only
reasonable but obvious that they are rooted in the fabric of totally
unfelt activities which Freud reified with the substantive term “the
Unconscious” (p. 22, italics added). In place of a substantive
Unconscious, and of a substantive ego or consciousness, she seems to
root the transiency and lability of feelings in the fabric of
totally unfelt activities. But this fabric is presumably other than the
activities as felt, and as fabric it has some “structure” or unity. Why
is one kind of “fabric” more acceptable than another? And, in any case,
to repeat, what difference do fruits make to the roots?
I realize that metaphors like
“rooted in” must be seen for what they mean, and I suspect I am seeing a
problem where Langer sees none. For she goes on to claim that it is a
philosophical error to believe that “desires, ideas or emotions cannot
be psychologically engendered and psychologically modified if they are
essentially physiological processes” (p. 23, italics added). As
correction for this error she proposes: “As soon as feeling is regarded
as a phase of a physiological process instead of a product (perhaps a
by-product of it), a new metaphysical entity different from it, the
paradox of physical and psychical disappears; . . .” (p. 23). I stop
quoting in the middle of a sentence. I wonder first what it means to
say in one passage already quoted, that the felt are rooted in unfelt
activities, and in the next moment to say that they are in no sense a
product but essentially a physiological (unfelt) process? We are
back to the meaning of phasal. If the psychological is not a new
metaphysical entity, why does even the paradox die by calling it a phase
and then holding that in this phase there can be autonomous engendering
and modifying?
Again, if the psychological phase is
essentially physiological, the changes or modification in it
should, I would suppose, be essentially physiological, but this is
denied. We are in trouble with a theory in which the psyche is a phasal
spin-off, “in” or “of,” the physiological processes; and at the same
time is simply not defined or definable in physiological terms (such as
growth and decay). Langer’s feeling is not a physiological phase of
this sort, for presumably feeling as psychical can itself be
modified by
its own kind of phases. They do not
decay and grow in any physiological way.
I had another reason for stopping
midway in a sentence. Having arrived at the psychic as essentially
physiological, Langer now grants it the autonomy of its own elaboration.
“. . . for the thesis I hope to substantiate here is that the entire
psychological field—including human conception, responsible action,
rationality, knowledge—is a vast and branching development of feeling”
(p. 23).
It may help to rephrase the
situation, and the predicament. For Langer what we usually call the
higher “mental” functions-like conceiving, acting responsibly,
reasoning—are not to be separated, as by a dualist, from the category of
physiological activities. For they and their neighbors—sense
perception, remembering, pleasant and unpleasant experience—are forms of
a psychic phase of certain levels of intra-organic processes. But,
surely in some sense, feeling is the common thread of many elaborated
phases that can be called by that name; for it provides some line of
continuity between the physiological unfelt processes and the “felt”
processes in their own branching developments. Thus, felt processes are
not physiological processes. But neither are they said to be forms of
something called “feeling.” Langer says explicitly: “There is not some
primitive form of feeling which is its ‘real’ form, any more than a bird
is ‘really’ an egg or water is ‘really’ vapor” (p. 23). Yet that she
wishes to grant feeling(s) autonomy is clear from her denial that “all
feeling is ‘really’ rationalization, all judgment ‘really’ emotional”
(p. 23).
Such assertions make Langer’s
intention and conclusions clear. But can they exonerate her from the
charge that there is more dualism in her emergent “phasalism” than she
seems to realize? For dualism is rooted in the realization that the
fabric of one kind of being (the physiological) is not the fabric of,
but systemically different from, another kind of being or activity, in
this instance “feeling.”
Furthermore, as
already hinted, Langer’s own image of a branching of feeling suggests
that there is something common to the branches which, so far, we have
not been able to designate. The problem remains even without this
image. “Feeling” here seems to include both too little—and too much. I
ask: What is it about “being felt” that is
applicable to such qualitative variety as sense, emotion, and reason,
for example? Langer has already rejected the notion of particular
phases of “primitive feeling,” and she clearly says: “Human emotion is
phylogenetically a higher development from simpler processes [not from
feeling], and reason is another one; human mentality is an unsurveyably
complex dynamism of their interactions with each other, and with several
further specialized forms of cerebral activity, implicating the whole
organic substructure” (p. 23). Yet even for this hierarchy of levels the
word “feeling” is used. The question persists: Why can we unify such
different processes as emotion, sensing, responsibility, and reason by
reference to “being felt”?
And the worst is
not yet. For Langer says that unfelt vital processes become psychical
only when they reach a certain state. But if this is so, why not simply
leave it that all the phases of “being felt” are, as the last quotation
suggests, different phases of intra-organic activities and then specify
what they are. But Langer seems unable to rest without reference to the
continuity of something called feeling. Note the passage: “As there are
many distinct nervous processes, some originating at the periphery of
the central nervous system, others within it, especially in its core
which is the brain, so there are many ways in which activities may be
felt. The most important distinction within the realm of feeling
is between what is felt as impact and what is felt as
autogenic action. The existence of these two fundamental modes of
feeling rests on the nature of vitality itself” (p. 23). The realm of
feeling has modes, or poles, if you will—the sensory-perceptual pole and
the emotion-responsibility pole.
I do not wish to gain critical
capital from difficulties in avoiding entitative language that is not so
intended. But I know not how to escape the conclusion that “feeling” is
used to characterize something common to phasal states of certain
intra-organic levels. Feeling, at the same time, involves new
developments that simply cannot be “caught” either in the descriptive
net of the physiologist or of the psychologist. This is a striking
weakness in a philosophical theory that seeks to discover relationships
among the sciences to which their over-restrictive methodology blinds
them. For the theory of feeling and mentality that results has no
recognizable basis in either.
Finally, the difficulties grow when
we ask the question: What do we know through feeling when it is thus
interpreted as being felt? Langer says: “What is felt is always
action in an organism, but some of it is felt in a special way, as
encounter . . .” (p. 24, italics added). This answer will hardly do.
It may well be that “being felt” has active organic processes as its
“what.” But surely this is not given as such in any vital or mental
state. Furthermore, in epistemic terms, we are being told that “being
felt” is at once a kind of being that is not identical with the organic
and yet can be aware of something, not itself, that is happening in the
organic. The feeling must be itself and yet “register” or “express” in
its being some kind of active response which its living system has to
the environment. If I am correct “being felt” is the kind of being that
can be itself and in some sense “represent” what is not itself. This
epistemic dualism is welcome to me. But does it fit a theory of
mentality which as a phasal stage of intra-organic processes is intended
to avoid the dualism of “representative” cognition?
A longer essay might press similar
related difficulties in this view of feeling. For if feeling
“expresses” in a psychical way, the improvisational, adaptive
ongoings in the vital organism, must it not have both its own relatively
autonomous life, and also be capable of adapting itself to its organism?
Such epistemic dualism favors the metaphysical dualism from which a
phasal theory of mind was to free us. Once more, we have been told that
feeling is a phasal phosphorescence of the dynamic interaction going on
at a certain level of vital process and also that feeling has a being
for itself, and, as it were, “branches out” on its own, as an agent in
the creative advance. (See pp. 27, 28.)
What has been gained, then, by
making “being felt” into an omnibus that carries every degree of
cognitive function and expresses every degree of telic tension and
direction? I close this section by quoting a passage that provides both
Langer’s perception of the gain, and confirmation, I think of my
interpretation and concern:
If one conceives the phenomenon of
being felt as a phase of vital processes, in which the living tissue
(probably the nerve or a neuronal assembly) feels its activity,
the problem . . . of how the nerve impulse can be “converted” into
thought and thought into nerve impulse . . .
becomes a different sort of problem. The question is not one of how a
physical process can be transformed into something non-physical in a
physical system, but how the phase of being felt is attained, and how
the process may pass into unfelt phases again, and furthermore how an
organic process in “psychical phase” may induce others which are
unfelt. . . . The proposed new concept of feeling, furthermore, permits
a new way of construing the greater concept of mind. Instead of
accepting “mind” as a metaphysical ultimate reality, distinct from the
physical reality which subsumes the brain, and asking how the two can
make “liaison,” one may hope to describe “mind” as a phenomenon in terms
of the highest physiological processes, especially those which have
psychical phases. (p. 29, italics added)
The reader will have to decide whether the questions I have asked do
indeed allow us the avoidance of the dualism here hopefully suggested.
The italicized clauses underscore my dilemma. For in the first clause I
am told that the tissue feels, when I thought feeling meant being felt.
In the second the feeling or psychic phase is given the autonomy that
grounds a dualist’s case. This construct of feeling was introduced to
break a hopeless impasse, and as “at least coherent with the rest of
biological inquiry and logically capable of solution” (p. 29). But if a
new kind of being—a psychical phase arising from unfelt phases and
inducing unfelt phases—is being introduced, and with novel epistemic
properties, why is this qualitative discontinuity, this shift to a new,
autonomous category of being and “activity,” more coherent even with
biological inquiry, let alone with feeling as expressed in art?
Indeed, one
wonders whether such psychic feeling that “stands, in fact, in the midst
of that vast biological field which lies between the lowliest organic
activities and the rise of mind” (p. 32) is hardly even a “bastard” kind
of mind, to adapt Plato’s expression. Has it been experienced on land
or sea by any person? This reconstruction of feeling, a turning point
in natural events (see p. 32), is supposed to permit “one to construe
the more impressive form of mentation—symbolic expression, imagination,
proposition, thought, religious conception, mathematical abstraction,
moral insight—as functions of [does this not mean product?] that most
complex of all organs, the human brain, with intense and prolonged
psychical phases” (p. 32). But surely such feelings, as we directly
experience them, are eviscerated in this reconstructed concept—a
Berkeleyan abstract idea if there ever was one.
II. Does Living Form
in Art Reflect or Parallel Organic Activity?
My dissatisfaction with Langer’s
view of feeling has centered on the contention that this reconstructed
view, proffered to provide a continuum between the vital and the mental,
actually loses continuity with anything persons experience as feeling.
The dissatisfaction does not decrease as I try to grasp the contention
in her important chapter, “On Living Form in Art and Nature.” (See pp.
199-244.) I had hoped that I would find in feeling as expressed in art
a basis for a better resolution of the problems of mind. But I continue
to find that when I expect Langer to show how the aesthetic does provide
a key to reasoning about the person as a whole, or to natural processes,
she sometimes moves from what must be a hypothetical view of vitality to
the more experiential theory of art, and sometimes from the latter to
the former. I no sooner think that the aesthetic will lead me to
understand the (non-aesthetic) natural than I find the kinship between
art and nature is controlled by the natural. And yet not quite; for her
view of the artistic expression of feeling at points seems to affect the
way in which the natural is conceived. Langer’s attempt to hold the
artistic and the natural together will be the focus of my analysis in
this section.
As we have already seen, “feeling is
a culmination of vital process.” But the question is whether we can
confidently continue: “. . . any articulated image of it [feeling] must
have the semblance of that vital process rising from deep, general
organic activities to intense and concerted acts, such as we perceive
directly in their psychical phases as impacts or felt actions” (p. 199).
But let us grant the control of the dynamism of the vital in “living
form” in art. Can the next sentence be readily granted, once we ask
what “reflects” means? “Every artistic form reflects the dynamism that
is constantly building up the life of feeling” (p. 199). Again, granted
that growth is the dynamism that “records itself in organic forms,” can
we readily go on to assert that this growth “is the source of
almost all familiar living shape” if we keep the meaning of
“growth” in aesthetic, moral, and religious experience before us?
And that we may
not is suggested by a sentence in the same context. “Hence the kinship
between organic and artistic form, though the latter need not be modeled
on any natural object at all” (p. 199, italics added). We have no
sooner been told that the dynamism in artistic form has kinship with the
growth-dynamism in the organic, than we are also told (what is also
repeated elsewhere) that artistic form “need not be modeled on any
natural object.” I take this to leave open the possibility that growth
as perceived in a work of art need not have kinship with, or reflect,
organic growth. The same Langer who wishes continuity with the
natural—no “sharp breaks”—is the aesthetician who cannot but recognize
the discontinuity of art. She says: “Elements in art have not the
character of things, but of acts. They are ‘active’, ‘act-like’.” And,
she continues, “in a broad sense which I find far more useful for
philosophical purposes, any unity of activity is an act” (p. 202).
The concept of act here broached is
the pervasive metaphysical category and it will concern us soon, but at
the moment we are concerned with whether the artistic form of feeling
controls her description of it.
Again, Langer’s insistence on
continuity with the organic keeps on obscuring the controlling image.
Thus she says: “All artistic elements whatsoever—all distinguishable
aspects of the created world—have formal properties which, in nature,
characterize acts. Inviolability, fusability, and the revival or
retention of past phases in succeeding ones are some of those
properties. Another very important one . . . is the relation of
elements to the whole, which is very complex. . . . Every element seems
to emanate from the context in which it exists” (p. 204). Here we are
told what we find in art and as characterizing acts in nature. But the
same passage continues to tell us that such elements are “a
manifestation of the internality of relations among created forms, which
is a principle of art, but not of life.” And Langer immediately
continues: “But it parallels a biological condition: in life,
every act is motivated by a complex of past and/or concomitant acts. . .
.” (p. 204, italics added).
My uneasiness
stems from my uncertainty as to what force is to be given to words like
“emanate,” “parallel,” “cognate,” and “echoes.” Again, in the same
context, Langer seems to set off from the dialectical
interdependence which creates both the unity of the work of art and its
rhythm. She is also impressed by the way in which the primary illusion
in a work of art, interacting with the variable secondary illusions that
come and go, nevertheless remains steady and complete. But now,
underscoring the richness of such potentiality in art, she boldly
continues:
In nature, such indefinite
potentiality is the essence of bodily existence, which feeds the
continuous burgeoning of life. Life is the progressive realization of
potential acts, and as every realized act changes the pattern and range
of what is possible, the living body is an ever-new constellation of
possibilities. In art the elusiveness of secondary illusions serves to
give the work of art as a whole something of the same character: it
seems to have a core from which all its elements emerge—figurations and
rhythms and all the qualities to which these give rise. (p. 206)
It must be emphasized that in these
passages Langer is fully aware of what is perceived in the art object on
its own as expressive form, as semblance. She does not identify,
for example, the individuality of a work of art with some “vital form”
or organic process, for that individuality is “a quality, as virtual as
all other artistic qualities” (p. 209). Nor does she suggest a
“one-to-one correspondence” between aesthetic form and vital form. In
view of this, one wonders whether the kinship and parallelism she
asserts to exist in living form in art and nature does so only because
so much is left out that would threaten such a claim.
For example, it is not at all clear
to me that if “in art all motion is growth, although the lines and
volumes and tensions that seem to grow never reach any increased
dimensions” (p. 213), that such growth is the appearance of life.
Assuming that in art there is growth, decay, rise, crisis, cadence, do
these in art actually parallel “the phases of growth and decay, rise and
crisis [which] constitute the all inclusive ‘greatest rhythm’ of life .
. . .” (p. 213)? There may well be a tour de force in the
suggestion that the growth and decay, the rhythm of biological
life as interpreted biologically, is cognate or parallel or echoes
“living form” in the artistic sense, especially if we take living form
to include “an adventure in the growth and precision of feeling by
virtue of its expressibility” (p. 213).
I suggest another example of the
gaining of kinship through
what seems to be an association that in fact loses concrete continuity
to abstraction. Langer, elaborating a quasi-Kantian view of the “telic
directedness of creation without practical purpose” (p. 218), emphasizes
that in artistic creation there is “the recurrent progression from
potentiality to realization, every decision producing new possibilities
and offering new choices” (p. 219). And she understandably adds: “This
dynamic pattern belongs to art itself, because it is an inescapable
pattern of life. That is why a really ‘living’ work always seems
reasonable in every respect, yet not predictable, as though it could,
nevertheless, have been different” (p. 219).
However, in this context Langer also
emphasizes that in art we have a dialectic or polarity of freedom and
inevitability. This is not found as such in “the perpetual
advance of life from one situation to another” (p. 221), for as
articulated in art the dialectic is “completely abstracted from actual
life,” transformed, projected in sensuous terms. Here an artistic image
of dynamic unity and creativity is in mind; art in its expressiveness
actually gives us a dimension of being not discoverable elsewhere. But
once more she reverts to the organic parallel: “in art, as in life, and
nowhere else in the universe as we know it, we find the conditions of
necessity and freedom” (p. 221).
I would have
expected to read that in art, as not in life, we find necessity
and freedom, as these are revealed at the aesthetic level (assuming Kant
to be correct). For, one might press, aesthetic semblance in great art
is what it is; it is native to no other dimension of being, biological,
moral, intellectual, or religious.
It seems clear,
then, that when Langer keeps her gaze fixed on art, she sees a singular
kind of unity, organization, and growth. But in her concern to find
continuity between art and nature she presses for a parallelism or
kinship between artistic semblance and felt and unfelt activities, by
way of a “living form,” that in fact cannot be concretely assimilated
either to art, or life, or nature. As we found in our analysis of
feeling, the cost for this theoretical transaction is the loss of the
very singularity that was to help in illuminating nature and mind.
In a word, in this naturalism there
is an unwitting straddling of the way of emergence and the way of
reductionism. The
concern to stay with natural
categories forces Langer to appeal ultimately to biological categories
for clarification of feeling and “living form,” despite the promise to
illuminate nature and mind by the aesthetic-artistic phase of the
psychical. Yet even the vital level is itself hardly recognizable in
biological terms, owing to the influence of her aesthetic theorizing on
this analysis.
III. Art, Individuation, and Mind
In this last section, I turn
explicitly to the way in which the analysis of act suffers from the same
theoretical ambivalence and invites other difficulties. I shall pay
special attention to the treatment of individuation and continuity.
To begin with, in Langer’s view
there is in artistic individuation more than individuality or
uniqueness. Artistic individuation involves elaborations that are
integrated in, or subordinated to, unifying or individuating processes.
Thus, noting that “this dialectic of separation and connection is
typical of organic structure” (p. 228), Langer ties the artistic and the
organic together by saying that “in art is the image of individuating
force, unequal growth, which underlies all morphology and is the
fundamental mechanism of evolution; hence its power to raise artistic
expression to a level of complexity that reflects not only universal
vital rhythms, but particularly human ones” (p. 229, italics added).
Thus the dialectical individuating force underlying all morphology and
“the particularly human ones” are linked; and the artistic, in the last
analysis, finds the “ground” in the organic. And yet, despite this
linkage and grounding, there is something about artistic individuation
that defies identification with the organic. Thus Langer says: “The art
symbol, however, reflects the nature of mind as a culmination of life,
and what it directly exhibits, first of all, is the mysterious quality
of intangible elements which arise from the growth and activity of
the organism, yet do not seem entirely of its substance” (pp. 229,
230, italics added).
With this conception of continuity
and differentiation we are now familiar. Our concern is to ask how
Langer’s conception of artistic unity is related to the unity of the
act, her substitute for entitative substances in other systems.
(a) Langer’s account of the unity of an act
(i) In a work of art, there is, on
Langer’s view, “the semblance of substantiality,” that is, neither
substance, nor unreality. This would seem to mean that no semblance, no
projection exists in a work of art as a “thing.” They exist for a
creator or the perceiver of the work. If the motion of Shiva Nataraja
“seems perfected, not suspended,” in the actual image, if the “balletic
leap, for instance, may appear as soaring flight” (see illustrations,
pp. 234, 235), the seeming and appearing are aesthetically neither
physical motions nor biological motions. As appearance or seeming they
involve the psychic reality of creator and percipient.
But how, then, is this “substantial”
dimension of a work of art so dependent on the organic? Langer’s
phenomenology of art has no place in it for dimensions used by
biochemist or physiologist, since the semblance of substantiality cannot
be expressed in unfelt organic processes. Indeed, it is this
phenomenology that re-enforces her theory of mind-body. Note the
description of secondary illusions:
All secondary illusions, whether
they serve primarily to intensify the expressiveness of a piece or
whether they create a quintessential moment, have the same character of
coming into existence from nowhere, apart from the virtual substance of
the work (which is anchored in the primary illusion according to its
proper mode), and fading again into nothing. In their very nature,
therefore, they project the outstanding attribute of human mentality,
the termination of autonomous acts in psychical phases that
resemble those of perceptual acts in many respects, that is to say, the
occurrence of images. (p. 240, italics added.)
In this passage the autonomy of the
aesthetic experience as part of the phasal psychic is stressed, and in
this context we are left without any doubt that Langer wishes to “gain
some biological and psychological insights through the suggestiveness of
artistic forms” (p. 244). It is clear that because a symbol always
presents its import in simplified form, and because art is “incomparably
simpler than life” (p. 244), we can find in it suggestive analogies for
the biological and psychological phenomena. Even more specifically,
Langer says that “the theory of art is really a prolegomenon to the much
greater undertaking of constructing a concept of mind adequate to the living
actuality” (p. 244). My thesis has been that Langer in fact loses the
singularity and the autonomy of the aesthetic when she turns around and
regards the psychic and artistic semblance as a reflection of organic
activities with which it has kinship. (See also pp. 199, 214, 219, 221.)
(ii) The question that remains, once
we are clear about individuation and “substance” in art and the
aesthetic experience as such, is whether it does affect Langer’s
conception of the unity and continuity of “act,” the ultimate ontic unit
of Natura naturans. The act is a theoretical construct. It is
needed in part because “there is little doubt that every attempt to
produce life from lifeless substances, without any vital germ to animate
them, has so far met with failure” (p. 258). We must therefore not
identify the inorganic with the living.
Furthermore, while others have
succumbed to the temptation to talk of progressive phases in the realm
of life, because it is so difficult to find clear-cut boundaries in the
evolutionary plant and animal, Langer prefers to regard phases as only
pragmatic. What must be realized is that “the continuous process is not
composed of discrete episodes, but it has peaks of activity which are
centers of recognizable phases, though these have no precise start or
finish lines. What we need, then, by way of analytic terms are units
with definite centers and labile limits” (p. 260). But there is no
point in talking about a center of a phenomenon unless it is indivisible
and has “internal structure” which locates it in the continuum of life.
(iii) Langer adds that such a
“fecund and elastic concept” can describe a broad spectrum of natural
events at least on the earth. Acts “arise where there is already some
fairly constant movement going on,” which, on accelerating to a certain
point, reaches a point of change in which the movement subsides and the
“consummation of the act” takes place (p. 261). “The subsequent phase,
the conclusion or cadence, is the most variable aspect of the total
process. It may be graduated or abrupt, seen as a clearly identifiable
course, or merge almost at once into other acts, or sink smoothly,
imperceptibly back into the minutely structured general flow of events
from which the act took rise. An act may subsume another act, or even
many other acts” (p. 261).
It is this broad concept of acts
which forms the basis of the psychic within the wider realm of zoology
especially. Acts are clearly non-entitative; they are analyzable yet
indivisible, and partially autonomous units which form the “intricate
dynamism of life” and become more and more concentrated and intense,
finally reaching “the phase of being felt, which I have termed
‘psychical’” (p. 260). As Langer goes on to indicate, this emergent act
is essentially telic, but need not be conscious; it may extend
“downward” to the “limits of distinguishability” (p. 264).
It is this telic activity that
defines the intrinsic unity of the act. “What gives every act its
indivisible wholeness is that its initial phase is the building up of a
tension, a store of energy that has to be spent; all subsequent phases
are modes of meting out that charge, and the end of the act is the
complete resolution of the tension” (p. 268).
(iv) If we now ask what is the key
that guides this conception of act-ive unity, the influence of Langer’s
theory of art is clear. Once more rejecting both mechanical and “soul”
models, she suggests “that the artist’s symbolic projection provides a
principle of analysis . . . the principle of distinguishing within a
dynamic whole . . . articulated elements, which nonetheless are
indivisible within themselves, and inalienable from the whole, if they
are not to give up their identity” (pp. 272, 273).
(b) Is Langer’s account of the unity and continuity of acts adequate?
(i) Granted the tensive unity of the
act, what makes possible the continuation of acts? We have already seen
that Langer rejects the “initial assumption of a physical, psychical, or
‘psychophysical’ entity, the subject, agent, or individual” (p. 307), in
favor of the functional concept of individuation. This process
consists of acts, each motivated by a vital situation, “a moment in the
frontal advance of antecedent acts composed of more and more closely
linked elements, ultimately a texture of activities” (p. 311). Since
“the development of beings with minds is probably the highest
individuation the world has known” (p. 312), the critical problem is to
show how both the telic unity and continuity of mind is to be conceived.
For Langer some non-vital chemical
transformations may be “act-like,” but they are not bona fide
acts because “they do not develop into a self-continuing system of
actions proliferating and differentiating in more and more centralized
and interdependent ways; that is they do not enter into the constitution
of an agent” (p. 314). But what is an agent? “An agent is a complex of
actions, and all actions that belong to that complex are acts of that
agent. All true acts, therefore, are to some extent involved with other
acts...” (pp. 314, 315). This means that the unity of the acts does not
originate in “act-like” chemical actions. Indeed there is no explanation
of “how some of the [“act-like”] chemical actions... ever became
involved with each other so as to form centers of activity which
maintained themselves for a while amid the changes of forming and
dissolving compounds around them” (p. 315). The most Langer suggests is
that such “centers” need not have been self-perpetuating from the
beginning, and “the first proto-organisms might have been of short
duration” (p. 315).
The appearance of agent-unity in a
world where there was at best only act-like chemical change does not
seem to bother Langer. Any such concern, she thinks, stems from the
metaphysical failure of thinking of life as something—a spark of
life—that somehow came from outside the purely physical stream, to make
liaison with the lifeless matter there (p. 316). “The escape from the
dilemma” is “to abandon the metaphysical dualism of ultimate
substantiae, and try to make the logically more amenable system of
physical, chemical and electrical events yield a functional
explanation of vital and—in due course—of mental phenomena” (p. 316,
italics added).
I confess that the force of
“logically more amenable” is lost on me. I wonder also whether
functional explanation is here really explanatory. Is the “break”
between the “act-like” chemical and the bona fide vital somehow
really overcome by a “shift” (however small) from the chemical to the
vital? Is there anything more than verbal in the claim that “the
heightening” of chemical action supplants “the incursion of an
ontologically unique “living spark” (p. 316)? And will her resort to
phenomena, like the “stabilizing,” “concentrating,” “perpetuating” of
non-vital activities, actually support the shift from the “act-like” to
the act? We are simply admonished not to think of life as some essence
that any given physical object possesses, but as “a wide, varied and
unbelievably complex functional pattern” (p. 313), that appears here and
there on earth. We are supposed to be satisfied by thinking of the
telic impulse that defines act as the consequent of acceleration,
ferment, or heightening of non-telic electro-chemical events.
(ii) Let us set these qualms aside
and assume the arrival of the telic impulse, without which no selective
unity is possible. How is the continuity of the agent forthcoming? The
answer seems to be that the sequence between telic acts is the
continuity. “Rhythmic concatenation is what really holds an organism
together from moment to moment; it is a dynamic pattern, i.e., a pattern
of events into which acts and act-like phenomena very readily fall: a
sequence wherein the subsiding phase, or cadence, of one act (or similar
element) is the up-take for its successor” (p. 323). But what is
rhythm? “The essence of rhythm is the alternation of tension building
up to a crisis, and ebbing away in a gradu-ated course of relaxation
whereby a new build-up of tension is prepared and driven to the next
crisis, which necessitates the next cadence” (p. 324).
To summarize: the vital element
manages to sustain itself in its own aim even as it integrates or
amalgamates other acts into its own life. The impulsive act dies if it
cannot accept them in any way. Again, within the lifetime of one
act—which is all that is at issue at the moment—unity maintains itself
by its capacity to survive interplay with other acts in its ambient.
(iii) If this is a fair account,
then I wonder whether we must not avoid the imagery of one act
fulfilling itself and, in perishing, passing its act-ive unity on to the
next “moment.” For what does “passing itself” on mean? I can see that
an act may wither and die; and that it can (as happens in individuating
organization with other acts) live in harmony with other acts (rhythm).
But how can it “pass itself” on to a future that is not there yet to
receive it? Again, from the point of view of any one actual moment
there is no future being to which one’s identity may be “passed.” This
image is probably born of our tendency to look back from any present act
and, distinguishing different stages in a line of
development, picture its history as a string, or series of
acts whose identity has somehow remained. We then say that moment “a”
has passed on its identity to the next moment “b.” I submit—and I
realize that much in
Whitehead
and
Hartshorne support Langer
here—that such a transaction does not and cannot take place.
I am suggesting that in a non-entitative
view of substance—which I, like Langer, find reasonable—the process of
self-sustaining identity is no simple process of passing on
self-identity. I am urging that if any act is a unified now,
then it cannot pass itself on to a future that is non-existent. Only
one other non-substantive alternative seems open to me, and I make bold
to suggest it, all too briefly, here.
(iv) A unified act can indeed be its
own “drop” of being, and its own kind of being. That is, it is
telic in its own active unity together with whatever limits of
flexibility (potentiality) help to define its scope. I assume, agreeing
with Langer, that its unity is not the mere collection of other acts; I
assume too that its monadic “windows” are open to its ambient, namely,
other acts (or the conditions of acts). This means that what
future it will have—if it has any at all—depends solely on its capacity
to maintain its own unified qualitative being even as it selectively
responds to what is consistent with its own continuance. An act does
not pass on its unity after (presumable) self-fulfillment. Given
its own complex unity it responds selectively to its ambient and in fact
maintains its self-identity without being static, and thus achieves
continuity.
This basic paradigm of the
continuity of unified act, which I find in my self-experience, is not
picturable as “passing on.” The phases of this continuity are phases in
the being of an act (or agent) which in responding to its ambient simply
finds that it has survived as a dynamic, self-identifying telic unity.
If, with Langer, we give up entitative unities, we cannot substitute a
process in which unit-acts have continuity because they pass their unity
on from one moment to another. Acts may, of course, die, or pass out of
being. But once they come into being (whatever the process), they have
only one alternative: either they proceed to fulfill the
impulsive nature that activates their potential, or they die. If they
do continue in their unity (survive), it is because
they are able to meet both internal demands for variation and to survive
the interchange with their present vital, psychic, and non-vital
environment.
But now the whole model of
successive identity needs revision. We must not succumb to spatializing
serial identity, that is, to think of continuance in terms of “passing
on” our identity from one point in a series to another. Nor can we
think of self-identity as we experience it in ourselves as a
mathematical or logical identity—two equals two. It is identity
provided in the fact of telic change. The growth is always from within
the identity of a unitas-multiplex-unified and telic from its
inception—and able to sustain its complex unity at every moment in its
history, but not as an inflexible, rigid, completely unchanging “core.”
Yet, despite the conflicts within its complex nature, and despite the
challenges to its very being, its task is to nourish itself and grow in
an ambient that is basically supportive.
There is no image that will quite
do. But I can say that any active unity is pregnant with its own
future, in the sense that its future will be affected by its own
capacity to “ingest” and transform what it has been able to assimilate
to itself from the ambient. But the future act is not the offspring of
the pregnant now that dies in the future. The “future” is the
“mother” who is pregnant, whose “offspring” are its present in another
phase of its unity-in-variety. The best example of this is, as I have
hinted, my experience of myself. For I am not the (mathematical) same
from moment to moment; yet I know my experience as mine, I suggest, not
because I pass myself on from one moment to another, but because I am
able to maintain, and re-form and enrich within limits, the telic unity
that constituted me from the beginning of my being.
(v) In trying to suggest a different
model for the continuity of any one primitive act-ive unity, I have
already been talking about individuation through involvement—what Langer
calls the rhythmic concatenation of acts into a more or less harmonious
whole. But in passing I wish to make what is not a facile confession.
I do not claim to know the technical how of interaction between
the act and its varied ambient, and that is not an issue here. I, like
any non-monistic philosopher who disclaims that beings are modes of any One, be it
Matter or Mind, am faced with the necessity for holding to interaction,
at some point, as an ultimate kind of relation in which active units of
being are involved. Without appealing to pre-established harmony I am
trying to protect both that intrinsic unity, which, as Leibniz says so
well, cannot come into being bit by bit, and also to open the monadic
windows in a way that does not lose the self-identity in change. Langer,
I think, is trying to do the same thing. Our disagreement about the
“break” or “shift” from non-vital act to vital act does not affect the
agreement that the act is a unity and a telic one. But it seems to me
that on her account of self-continuity, self-identity would not be
preserved. I also think that her account of individuation, of the
organization of acts so that they constitute organisms of some degree of
complexity, will not quite do. But the issue is not how
interaction occurs, but the way in which we are to conceive the rhythmic
concatenation that “really holds an organism together from moment to
moment” (p. 323).
(vi) We have already noted that at
the very beginning of the life process Langer postulates “strong ruling
tendencies toward organization, which led to increasing interdependence
[involvement] of actions and eventuated in the formation of biological
mechanisms” (pp. 322, 323). These self-sustaining, living, act-ive
systems are self-propagating; “Every event is prepared by progressively
changing conditions of the integral whole” (p. 322). On Langer’s
view, then, individuation presupposes integration of functions, that is,
“establishment of self-contained, stabile, vitally active systems” (p.
342). Well and good. If we ask: Is such individuation an assembly, a
collection, of convergent lines? The answer is negative. Langer’s
emphasis on subordination, on dovetailing of activities within the
system, on the exclusion of some activities from any particular phase or
stage of the system, suggests a continuing system. But is the
individuation a momentary marriage of convenience, or, to change the
figure, a convenient hierarchy established among the lines of
activities, with the result that the unity is functional only in terms
of the purposes of our description? Or is it indeed a more complex
agent-unity that has an integrity of its own, a new autonomous unity in
relation to all else?
I cannot say with certainty. I
suspect that Langer would decry the latter as suggesting something
entitative, and would not be pleased with the former as suggesting
something too mechanical. But her ontogeny of individuation leaves much
to be desired, although her manner of speaking may belie her intent.
She does speak of a build-up of systems of activities that initially
need not have belonged together. But her rejection of the mechanical
model does not keep her from thinking of elementary acts as somehow
going into the making of new wholes. It is indeed an advance to think
of these elements as dynamic acts, themselves complex unities. But
elementary dynamic acts nevertheless “make up” activities; and at any
moment “many” elementary activities go into the make-up of a new
“individuated” system. Thus, individuation tends to be more of a
functional collection than perhaps she intends.
No doubt many instances we call
“individuation” are no more than such “parasitical” unities. But I make
a counter-suggestion to describe the new systems that are new complex
unities. Why not consider individuation the development of a unified
holistic agency of which what Langer calls acts are not component
unities but rather distinctions discernible within the complexity of the
wholistic [sic] agency? On this view, there is no interaction
within a whole that in fact is a convenient get-to-gether for mutual
survival. Again, on this view there are no acts which come to arrange
themselves in wholes because they are in fact subservient slaves of a
dominant telic agency which guarantees their survival. Rather is any
agent-activity, however complex or simple it may be, a complex
unity—within which we may be able to distinguish pseudo-”acts.” But as a
complex unity to which other “acts” have contributed, it does not
“contain” them, or “order” them as slaves, or as instrumentalities. For
it is what it is by its own creative response to them; and that
response constitutes it a more complex and, at the same time, a richer
unity. Thus, an agent-whole is never a convenient built-up; it is
given, and given as complex in different degrees of scope. It
may be host to, be helped or hindered by parasites; but they are not
“parts” of it. They have so interacted with it that its richer unity is
its own growth as an agent-whole.
If we do not grant this different
model of individuation, are we not left with unities, called agencies,
which are relatively
accidental, accepted by all components until a more convenient one is
available? Is not this suggested by such passages as the following:
“The power of on-going rhythmic acts, and the entrainment of smaller
cycles by larger ones, is the main principle of integration in organic
structure” (p. 354)? Strife is justice, said Heraclitus. I should wish
to contend (and often I think Langer does) that the justice of unity is
its strife—and especially if artistic experience is to be used as a
paradigm.
(vii) Much more needs to be said of
course. But in closing perhaps I can summarize the counter-suggestive
view of unity and self-continuity of act and individuation—what I might
call temporalistic self-sustaining unity. Any organic or psychic
act-unity (or agency) worthy of the name, is sufficiently complex, both
as actual and potential, to enable it to interact with its ambient in a
way consistent with its own given telic potential. If it cannot, it
dies; it goes out of being. But if it lives it maintains its
self-identity as far as possible, not simply by conserving itself, but
by “increasing” itself. Again, its own existence at any moment hangs on
whether, in its interplay with its ambient, it can maintain itself
against destruction, on the one hand, and creatively sustain its own
being by selecting among the nurturant elements in its ambient not as
its slaves but renewing itself because of the interaction.
This capacity for self-renewal, for
creativity within limits, is a metaphysical postulate that requires
further justification. But unless something like it is hypothesized,
one is hard put to account for the unity and continuity, the
continuity-within-dynamic-unity, that we do find, I would suggest, both
in our experience of ourselves as persons, and in the forms our
experience takes when we are “engaged” in aesthetic creation and
appreciation. It is this quality of personal agency—reflected in
artistic and moral experience in particular—that “shines by its own
light.” I prefer to face the problems in dualism (if need be) than
surrender to even a fascinating attempt to understand it as a form of
the organic. Nevertheless, I look forward to the metaphysical vision
Susanne Langer will spread before us in her second volume. For in such
systematic integration the human venture in metaphysics is inspired and
sustained.
Peter A. Bertocci page