The Person, Obligation, and Value
Peter
A. Bertocci
[Before the text of the anthologized edition of the article, Bertocci
supplied this preface:]
Obligation, I have proposed, is neither the voice of God, nor the voice
of society, nor the voice of a person’s basic needs and abilities as
re-formed in his personality. “Oughting” is that imperative to the best
which a person experiences at choice point, once he reflects on the
alternatives he believes are open to him. The experience of obligation
is neither a cognition of some irreducible value-data, or prima facie,
or a priori obligations; nor is it an emotive response
symptomatic of the person’s affective-conative preferences.
“Oughting” has its own magisterial authority, as Bishop Butler said.
Yet Butler and the cognitivists, or ethical realists, do not take into
account adequately the fact that ‘cognitions’ of the best do change
while obligation to the best does not. Nor do they adequately see that
needs and wants, learned and acquired, are the raw material for choice
and do influence the range of actual preferences in the person’s moral
horizon. In the present chapter, I indicate how the authority of
oughting is related to the person’s decisions about what he ought to
become as he analyses the welter of claims and counter-claims that
confront him as a caring person.
*
* *
It is the theme
of this paper that a more adequate account of moral obligation and value
may be given if the experiences of obligation and of value are seen as
distinct, though complementary, phases within the matrix of personal
self-experience. It is to be suggested that “obligatoriness” is not an
attribute of any value-object per se, but a sui generis
quality of personal experience. Value-experiences, on the other hand,
become norms for persons, not because they are non-natural, but because,
critically selected, they become guides to creative fulfilment. On such
a view the emphasis of the deontologists on irreducible obligatoriness
is granted, but is relocated as a unique quality of personal
non-cognitive experiencing in choice situations. At the same time,
value may be defined in terms of experienced preference, or preferred
experience, and located in the person as he interacts with the
environment. These suggestions may be briefly amplified as follows:
1. Whatever
final metaphysical status is attributed to a person whether, for
example, he be a composition of electrical charges from which conscious
states emerge, whether he be a focus or centre of unconditional Being or
of an Absolute Spirit, whether he be a “substance” created with
delegated spontaneity by God—his existence as a knowing-agent is
presupposed in hypothesizing any theory about his metaphysical status.
Human knowing cannot go on—that is, sense-data cannot be interpreted,
logical and mathematical relations clarified, a perceptual world
organized, comparisons and contrasts drawn, conceptions entertained, and
experiences evaluated—unless remembering and constant present undergoing
or experiencing are inseparate aspects of the knowing process (H.
H. Price, Bowne, Brightman, Tennant). Thus, to be a person is,
minimally, to be an active-timebinding unity of experiencing.
Experiencing is used here to embrace that kind of durée or process which
can be stipulatively or ostensively defined as a unitas multiplex
(W. Stern) or sensing, remembering, thinking, feeling, willing, wanting,
and, as we shall see, oughting. It is a person who develops theories
about himself upon the basis—of what else but experiencing? Finally, if
a person knows that, wherever there is cognitive experiencing, what goes
on is a mental process of connecting and relating; if he knows that this
process is distinguishable from sensing, and that both thinking and
sensing are distinguishable from emotive and wanting processes, it is
because, as experienced, these activities have qualitatively different
psychic tones—for want of better words! Yet, so far as we know, each
experiential process is embedded inextricably in the unified matrix of
the kind we call a person. This largely phenomenological description of
personal experience must suffice as a background for the analysis of
moral obligation and value.
2. Among my
experiences as a person I note a peculiar experience of obligation.
This experience has been described in different ways and in terms which
seem not to do justice to the phenomenology of the experience. The
experience of obligation has suffered by being interpreted, rather than
described, in its own experienced light. For example, Freudians,
materialists, naturalists, and others have interpreted it in the context
of what it might be expected to be if the remainder of their theories of
human nature were to dictate. In their hands the experience “I ought”
becomes, generally speaking, a consolidated complex of desires,
especially of fear and approval, conditioned in a cultural milieu to
specific or general permissions and prohibitions. On such views,
however, the experience of obligatoriness, of oughting, if I may
coin the appropriate verb, turns out, on analysis, to be totally
explained by understanding what pressures in each case were brought to
form this monitor or censor.
Many theists (Butler,
Kant, J. Baillie, A. C. Garnett), on the other hand, have interpreted
the experience of obligation as ultimately a moral cognition of God’s
norms for men. On either “naturalistic” or theistic views, the
experience of oughting ends up as the experience in man of specific or
general imperatives originating beyond the individual experient’s
nature.
But do not such
accounts, though logically possible as theories, run contrary to what a
person actually feels when he experiences obligation? I am not denying
that conditioning is present in the total personality, nor am I denying
the possibility of God’s existence and effects in man’s life. But, to
limit myself here to the naturalistic social theory of obligation, I
must question whether ought, as experienced, is essentially the
introjection of social pressures and approvals. There is nothing
coercive, or permissive, in a strict sense, in the experience of felt
obligation. The different degrees of psychological compulsion I may
feel are not that which is present in oughting as such. I can never
fairly substitute the words “I must,” or “I may,” “I fear,” “I am
anxious,” as a description of what takes place when I feel “I ought.”
Again, prima
facie, when “I ought” is felt, social disapproval or approval may
accompany it, together with felt desires, fears, and anxieties. But,
prima facie, oughting is not felt as what is required by pressures
of desire from within or demands from others. For it itself is not felt
as a conative urge (“I want”), or as compulsion (“I must”). Oughting
has its own peculiar tone, its own kind of appeal or urgency, within
the context of wants, fears, and feeling-emotive tensions. When I say,
“I ought to do X,” the X may be what others approve or disapprove, but I
never feel I ought in connection with X unless I believe that what
others approve or disapprove is the best standard for me also. Let the
reader ask himself: “Do I feel ‘I ought’ about a command or demand which
I myself in no sense approve? On the other hand, if the command or
demand is deemed by me to be the best possible in this situation, or
most consistent with what I believe to be the best, do I not feel I
ought in connection with it, even if, in fact, I then fail to will
it?” In brief, the suggestion here is that the experience of obligation
is felt about any alternative or option approved by the person (whatever
his criterion of the good or the best may be).
We cannot
consider here the genesis of the experience, but must remind ourselves
that prima facie facts must be explained by genetic psychology
and must not be explained away. It is such a far cry from “I must,” or
“I want,” to “I ought,” that this writer would hold that the experience
of obligation is as primitive and irreducible as the experience of
wanting or thinking, and that it appears in the maturing person at that
point when he begins to contemplate and compare alternatives. Oughting
seems clearly to be present in adult experience when a choice-point is
confronted, and when the person judges which alternative is best. The
moment he decides which alternative is best, he feels: I ought to do it.
Thus we may conceptualize the experience of oughting in the words, “I
ought to do the best I know.”
Persons may
differ, owing to innate sensitivity or perceptivity, owing to
differences in personal learning and cultural influences, owing to
whatever the factors may turn out to be which influence the final
decision as to what is best. But is there ever a choice situation in
which a person does not feel obligated to the best as he sees it? A
theory of value-experience is, to be sure, crucial in the final decision
about what is best, but the contention here is twofold:
(a) that
whatever the theory of the value-object or objective by which one
determines the best, at choice-points a persistent, continuous
obligation to the conceived best is felt by the person. This is as
much a, part of his unlearned nature as thinking is, though neither is
present at birth. Furthermore, whatever the structure of value, or of
the universe may be—whether, for example, there be a good God or
not—“I ought to do the best I know.” As a person grows and reflects,
the meaning of “the best” may change, but the inner imperative to the
best possible is unwavering. This is not one ought among other
prima facie oughts (W. D. Ross), but the underlying and common
thrust of every other selected best or specific “ought to do.”
(b) This
experience of obligation, as such, cannot be conceived as a by-product
of the pressures of society, of the world, or of the rest of a
person’s nature upon him. The “ought to will the best I know” is as
irreducible at the level of choice as, say, the “will to live” is at
the level of sheer psychobiological conation.
Thus we are
simply not describing the personal structure of experience adequately
without adding such “oughting” to the distinguishable list of human
capacities. What is considered best may vary with maturity and
learning, just as the thoughts one thinks vary; “oughting to do the
best” is as unwavering as a magnetic needle toward the best in choice
situations, even though it must await decision rather than itself assert
some intuition of the best.
This account of
the uniqueness of obligation may be buttressed by calling attention to
what a person feels when he obeys his “ought to the best” despite the
fact that stern social reprisals or personal disappointments ensue! He
may indeed feel fear and anxiety because of what may happen to him, yet
he still can “look himself in the mirror,” as we say, and feel what, for
want of other words, we may call moral approval. The surgeon who has
done his very best to save a patient when all was in vain, feels
miserable indeed. But he feels, together with disappointment, a “moral
approval.” The prophet may feel anxiety, but he still feels, and is
exalted by, the unique moral approval of: “I can do no other.” What
happens on the other hand, if a person does not will his chosen
ought-objective? He may feel social approval, and he may feel that
other ends are now secure—but he also feels moral guilt.
To feel guilty
is not to feel anxiety (though one may accompany the other), and it is
anomalous that so much psychology identifies the two. But there is, to
say the least, a component of fear in anxiety which is never present in
guilt as such. Anxiety may be produced by social pressure, but guilt
never. A professor may feel anxious lest he lose his position owing to
the publication of his investigations, but does he feel guilty if he
believes that publication is for the best? To take the surgeon again.
If his patient gets well despite an avoidable surgical error, he may
not feel the pointing finger of social disapproval. But on coolly
contemplating his avoidable actions, he will feel guilt—and may try to
wipe these feelings away by rationalization. For such reasons, then, we
may contend that moral approval and moral guilt are misconstrued if
reduced, respectively, to social approval and socially conditioned
anxiety.
It will be
noted that this analysis of obligation so far could be classified as
agreeing with deontologists like Ross, against utilitarian, “emotivist,”
Freudian, and many psychosociological reductions of personal-social
interaction. But it seems to me that deontologists, while properly
insisting on obligations as an impregnable “given” in human experience,
have erred, together with moral intuitionists like
Butler
or Hartmann. They have committed the cognitive fallacy in regard to the
experience of obligation. For “oughting” is no more a cognitive
experience than are “wanting” or logical thinking as such. The “object”
of oughting is its “objective” (the best), which may vary from situation
to situation in specific content, as a person decides what value is the
best. The “ought” imperative to “the best I know” is absolute and
unwavering. But there are no specific values, or “rights” which are
found by its nature to be “the best,” apart from learning or moral
experimentation. Even W. D. Ross grants this basic thesis by saying
that his special obligations are prima facie only, and in need of
further criticism; and he gives greater authority to the obligation to
optimize the good than to his other special obligations. At any rate,
as Mandelbaum has reminded the deontolo-gists, “the phenomenon of
obligation is not merely a matter of action-accordingly-to-rule.”1
3. How, then,
on this view does one come to know what values constitute the best? The
suggestion to be made is indebted to nonintuitionists in
value-theory—and especially Dewey, R. B. Perry, F. R. Tennant, and E. S.
Brightman. Here the emphasis is placed on the fact that what is deemed
the best value depends on the careful organization and systematic
criticism of actual value-undergoing on the part of persons, with a view
to discovering which ideal of personality and society will protect the
widest range and the highest quality of values open to man as he
interacts with his total environment. In a word, “the best” is not some
one quality or value independent of any enjoyed experience of desire or
interest, nor is it definable a priori or independently of
experienced and experienceable values. In every choice
situation, “the best” refers to some desired experience or experiences,
critically conceived (after comparison with other desired experiences,
and after assessment of foreseeable consequences), to the total
value-complex of which persons are deemed capable. Once a desired
experience is judged “the best” in a given situation, it immediately
becomes the object of obligation, until some other alternative takes its
place. Thus, once more, obligation to the best is invariable and
unwavering, but what constitutes the best may vary as the person’s
insight into values and their conditions grows.
To explicate:
“Value,” to begin with, is the name for any desired human experience;
“disvalue” for any undesired or unwanted human experience. In this
sense, there are no values or disvalues of any kind without persons
undergoing experiences which are then deemed wanted or unwanted. As
experienced, the “value” is always at least a wanted state of a person
undergoing the experience. The wanting does not have to precede the
experiencing, for a person often finds himself experiencing a state
which he then wants to continue or discontinue. The “problem of value”
in a given life is always the problem of deciding which of desired
states (or undesired states) is to be chosen when there is a conflict
between the human states desired or undesired. In view of the fact that
persons grow and situations change, no assessment of value-experience is
intrinsically beyond question—no matter how convinced, psychologically,
a person may be about the asserted prima facie value of
“fittingness” of any experience. It is more cautious to say that we all
begin with prima facie value-claims, and that the problem is to
decide which “claims” are trustworthy.
What does the
word trustworthy mean in a value-situation? Where are the controls to
be sought? Within the person? Outside the person? The answer involves
both. First, a person has a fundamental structure common to other
persons, together with differences which constitute him a unique person
among other unique persons. No person knows exactly what he is and what
he can become. Second, every person interacts with other persons in a
non-human world, whose exact nature is not exactly known. Nevertheless,
within his own nature he discovers more dependable “structures” or
tendencies and abilities which he himself cannot constitute or create as
such, though they may be amenable to change within hard-to-define
limits. And he finds himself among other persons who bring him up amid
the values which they believe to be trustworthy for their natures in the
world as they conceive it.
Two
considerations emerge as crucial to an adequate theory of human
valuation.
(a) While
human valuations are aspects of human experience, they represent one’s
own interaction, on the basis of one’s own given ability and
sensitivity, with value-schemes and natures of other persons in this
kind of not-man-made world.
(b) A
value-claim, accordingly, is a joint-product, for whatever its final
worth, of the total nature of the person, as developed to a given
point, and of the total nature of the nurturant environment, as it
impinges upon him.
Put
differently: In making a value-claim, a person is making a claim about
what he believes at least possible to human experience in a given social
situation in a given world up to this time. In claiming certain
experiences to be valuable for him, he is also, until he is brought up
short by brute experience and reflection, suggesting that this
experience is valuable for others also. The stress here is on the fact
that in saying that values are related to persons and their structure
and growth-potential, we are not asserting that values are relative to
the individual in the sense that no standards at all can be found for
judging which value-claims are to be preferred to which other
value-claims. For the controls are fixed (but not all, or finally,
known) within the potentialities of human nature for wide varieties of
value-experience and within the possibilities allowed to human
experience by the non-human world.2
Value-experience, then, is indeed man-made in the sense that man can
“make” or “unmake” any value-experience (and its consequences) as he
wants. The biological, psychic, and spiritual potentialities in his
nature do not operate helter-skelter in their growth and fulfilment; nor
are they fulfilled without the encouragement, discourage-ment, or
nurturance and sustenance, by the actualities and possibilities open to
human nature in the world within which man lives. It is this world
which “allows” that vast experiences which are human responses to it.
It is this world which constitutes a realm of value-eligibility and
non-eligibility, for it demands responses adequate to its nature.
Value-claims are man-made, but neither man nor the total environment is
by any means totally man-made.
To come back,
then, to the problem of value-selection. Assessment of value-claims is
forced by the plethora of possible value-claims and the actual conflicts
which ensue if certain values are pursued and not others. By what are
we, or can we be, guided in value-selection? By the initial prima
facie quality of a value-experience, by the sequences and
consequences found as a result of actual human experimentation in
value-realization, by the interrelation of value-experiences with each
other, and by as careful an assessment as we can make of what further
value-experience may still be possible if certain selections and not
others are made. Each of these considerations involves us in making
“factual” statements about what is happening, has happened, and may
happen to human beings, given their nature, as so far known, in the kind
of universe, as so far understood, responded to, and appreciated. The
resulting criticized “real” values are statements of what is most
coherently believed to be possible in the light of what has been
possible to persons in this kind of world!
What we
actually do as we proceed to criticize value-claims is to take each
value-claim and criticize it by other claims of our own and in relation
to the claims of others. We judge each by its supportive, enhancing, or
undermining relation to other value-claims.
The
verification of a value-judgment (whether it refers to biological,
social, intellectual, aesthetic, or religious value-claims), consists in
understanding its relation to other value-experiences and their probable
relation to the developing potentialities of human nature in the total
environment. “The best,” concretely defined, will, accordingly, consist
of some interrelated system of value-experiences deemed to protect
creative growth in value-realization open to persons in this kind of
world. Thus, any theory of “the best” is also a theory of what persons
can and ought to be in this kind of universe.
4. To suggest
the outcome of these brief reflections: The obligation is being
experienced when the person is confronted by a choice-situation in which
wanted (and unwanted) experiences are in competition. The total
situation, in minimal terms, may be characterized thus: I want A, but I
also want B (and possibly other conflicting wants). I cannot have both.
As I reflect upon these varied value-claims in the light of all I know
about myself and others in the world as I conceive it, as I reflect upon
the quality and the foreseeable consequences of these value-claims, I
decide (let us assume) that A is better than B. As soon as the judgment
is made, I feel: I ought to will A and not B. If I will A and find
unforeseen disagreeable consequences and disap-provals, I am
disappointed and even anxious, but I do not feel guilty. If I will B
(less than the best I know), I may find unforeseen good consequences and
approvals which gratify me, but I feel guilty. But always my choice of
the best is guided by growing knowledge of the optimum-maximum range of
values which for ever constitute the obligatory, and of human
development. A person is morally good to the extent that he
consistently wills the best he knows.
But he can be
morally good without being happy or “fulfilled” (summum bonum).
He approaches fulfilment in so far as he creatively realizes and
coherently orchestrates those values which bring the total potential of
his human nature into creative interaction with the activities,
achievements, and possibilities of other human beings and of the total
environment. Thus, both the moral good and the summum bonum
involve creative growth of persons, and the kind of good which they can
achieve is a fact to be properly assessed in any adequate theory of the
universe.
The limitations
of space forbid a consideration of the metaphysics of value and of the
relation of values to God—indeed, too much of what has been said must
sound too dogmatic, though the hope is that it will be taken as
programmatic. But until we know what we mean by the word “good” and
what the ideal of human existence is, we cannot think clearly about the
existence and, especially, the goodness of God. On the other hand, as
the writer has suggested elsewhere, if knowledge-seeking and finding, if
creative moral fulfilment in compassionate love and forgiveness, if the
poignant joys and “peak-experiences” open to us in aesthetic and
religious experiences are to be taken as any part of the evidence for an
adequate metaphysics, then we may indeed find in the very possibility
that persons can enjoy and incarnate such values grounds for reasonable
faith in the goodness of God.3
Notes
1
M. Mandelbaum, The Phenomenology of Moral Experience,
Glencoe,
Ill.:
The Free Press, 1955, p. 52. I am glad to note many parallel
developments to basic contentions in this paper in Mandelbaum’s
excellent and original treatment. Thus the view of obligation here has
much in common with Mandelbaum’s, though there is more “perceptual
intuitionism” in his conception of “the fitting” than there is here in
the “ought to the best.” I would contend that the “fitting” which he
makes the object of obligation consists of a judgment, “This is more
fitting than that,” in the phenomenological situation confronting the
deciding person. There is a tendency in Mandelbaum’s thought to
assimilate the moral situation of choice to the aesthetic situation or
“Gestalt” in which there is “demand” without choice. Moral obligation,
as I see it, presupposes not merely an apprehended relation of
fittingness, but the reflective decision that one line of action will be
more “fitting” than any other in the totally envisioned situation
(though this would seem to be granted in some passages) (cf. pp. 69-70,
81). Nor am I clear that it is the condition of a feeling of obligation
that the value (objective) “must appear as independent of our
inclinations or desires” (p. 85). What I experience as the “condition
of obligation” is simply that one alternative, be it desired or anything
else, is deemed better than any other; but “oughting” is not geared even
as a prima facie tendency (Ross) to a specific right, or to any specific
perception of what is fitting.
2
I am glad to note at this point and at others, agreement in B.
Blanshard’s Howison Lecture, The Impasse in Ethics and a Way Out
(Berkeley, University of California Press, 1954).
3
See the author’s “Can the Goodness of God be Empirically Grounded?” in
The Journal of Bible and Religion, Volume 25, April 1957,
pp. 99-105.
Posted October 13, 2007
Peter A. Bertocci page