The Case for Determinism
Brand Blanshard
I am a determinist. None of the arguments offered on the other side seem
of much weight except one form of the moral argument, and that itself is
far from decisive. Perhaps the most useful thing I can do in this paper
is explain why the commoner arguments for indeterminism do not, to my
mind, carry conviction. In the course of this explanation the brand of
determinism to which I am inclined should become gradually apparent.
But first a definition or two. Determinism is easier to define than
indeterminism, and at first glance there seems to be no difficulty in
saying what one means by it. It is the view that all events are caused.
But unless one also says what one means by “event” and “caused,” there
is likely to be trouble later. Do I include among events not only
changes but the lack of change, not only the fall of the water over the
cataract’s edge, but the persistence of ice in the frozen river? The
answer is “Yes.” By an event I mean any change or persistence of state
or position. And what is meant by saying that an event is caused? The
natural answer is that the event is so connected with some preceding
event that unless the latter had occurred the former would not have
occurred. Indeterminism means the denial of this. And the denial of
this is the statement that there is at least one event to which no
preceding event is necessary. But that gets us into trouble at once,
for it is doubtful if any indeterminist would want to make such an
assertion. What he wants to say is that his decision to tell the truth
is undetermined, not that there is no preceding event necessary to it.
He would not contend, for example, that he could tell the truth if he
had never been born. No, the casual statement to which the
indeterminist takes exception is a different one. He is not saying that
there is any event to which some namable antecedents are not necessary;
he is saying that there are some events whose antecedents do not make
them necessary. He is not denying that all consequents have necessary
antecedents; he is denying that all antecedents have necessary
consequents. He is saying that the state of things just before he
decided to tell the truth might have been exactly what it was and yet he
might have decided to tell a lie.
By determinism, then, I mean the view that every event A is so
connected with a later event B that, given A, B must
occur. By indeterminism I mean the view that there is some event B
that is not so connected with any previous event A that, given
A, it must occur. Now, what is meant here by “must”? We cannot in
the end evade that question, but I hope you will not take it as an
evasion if at this point I am content to let you fill in the blank in
any way you wish. Make it a logical “must,” if you care to, or a
physical or metaphysical “must,” or even the watered-down “must” that
means “A is always in fact followed by B.” We can discuss
the issue usefully though we leave ourselves some latitude on this
point.
With these definitions in mind, let us ask what are the most important
grounds for indeterminism. This is not the same as asking what commonly
moves people to be indeterminists; the answer to that seems to me all
too easy. Everyone vaguely knows that to be undetermined is to be free,
and everyone wants to be free. My question is rather, When reflective
people accept the indeterminist view nowadays, what considerations seem
most cogent to them? It seems to me that there are three: first, the
stubborn feeling of freedom, which seems to resist all dialectical
solvents; second, the conviction that natural science itself has now
gone over to the indeterminist side; and, third, that determinism would
make nonsense of moral responsibility. The third of these seems to me
the most important, but I must try to explain why none of them seem to
me conclusive.
One of the clearest heads that ever devoted itself to this old issue was
Henry Sidgwick. Sidgwick noted that, if at any given moment we stop to
think about it, we always feel as if more than one course were open to
us, that we could speak or be silent, lift our hand or not lift it. If
the determinist is right, this must be an illusion, of course, for
whatever we might have done, there must have been a cause, given which
we had to do what we did. Now, a mere intuitive assurance about
ourselves may be a very weak ground for belief; Freud has shown us that
we may be profoundly deceived about how we really feel or why we act as
we do. But the curious point is that, though a man who hates his father
without knowing it can usually be shown that he does and can often be
cured of his feeling, no amount of dialectic seems to shake our feeling
of being free to perform either of two proposed acts. By this feeling
of being free I do not mean merely the freedom to do what we choose. No
one on either side questions that we have that sort of freedom, but it
is obviously not the sort of freedom that the indeterminist wants, since
it is consistent with determinism of the most rigid sort. The real
issue, so far as the will is concerned, is not whether we can do what we
choose to do, but whether we can choose our own choice, whether the
choice itself issues in accordance with law from some antecedent. And
the feeling of freedom that is relevant as evidence is the feeling of an
open future as regards the choice itself. After the noise of argument
has died down, a sort of intuition stubbornly remains that we can not
only lift our hand if we choose, but that the choice itself is open to
us. It this not an impressive fact?
No, I do not think it is. The first reason is that when we are making a
choice our faces are always turned toward the future, toward the
consequences that one act or the other will bring us, never toward the
past with its possible sources of constraint. Hence these sources are
not noticed. Hence we remain unaware that we are under constraint at
all. Hence we feel free from such constraint. The case is almost as
simple as that. When you consider buying a new typewriter your thought
is fixed on the pleasure and advantage you would gain from it, or the
drain it would make on your budget. You are not delving into the causes
that led to your taking pleasure in the prospect of owning a typewriter
or to your having a complex about expenditure. You are too much
preoccupied with the ends to which the choice would be a means to give
any attention to the causes of which your choice may be an effect. But
that is no reason for thinking that if you did preoccupy yourself with
these causes you would not find them at work. You may remember that Sir
Francis Galton was so much impressed with this possibility that for some
time he kept account in a notebook of the occasions on which he made
important choices with a full measure of this feeling of freedom; then
shortly after each choice he turned his eye backward in search of
constraints that might have been acting on him stealthily. He found it
so easy to bring such constraining factors to light that he surrendered
to the determinist view.
But this, you may say, is not enough. Our preoccupation with the future
may show why we are not aware of the constraints acting on us, and hence
why we do not feel bound by them; it does not explain why our sense of
freedom persists after the constraints are disclosed to us. By
disclosing the causes of some fear, for example, psychoanalytic therapy
can remove the fear, and when these causes are brought to light, the
fear commonly does go. How is it, then, that when the causes of our
volition are brought to light volition continues to feel as free as
before? Does this not show that it is really independent of those
causes?
No again. The two cases are not parallel. The man with the panic fear
of dogs is investing all dogs with the qualities—remembered, though in
disguised form—of the monster that frightened him as a child. When this
monster and his relation to it are brought to light, so that they can be
dissociated from the Fidos and Towsers around him, the fear goes,
because its appropriate object has gone. It is quite different with our
feeling of freedom. We feel free, it was suggested, because we are not
aware of the forces acting on us. Now, in spite of the determinist’s
conviction that when a choice is made there are always causal influences
at work, he does not pretend to reveal the influences at work in our
present choice. The chooser’s face is always turned forward; his
present choice is always unique; and no matter how much he knows about
the will and the laws, his present choice always emerges out of deep
shadow. The determinist who buys a typewriter is as little interested
at the moment in the strings that may be pulling at him from his
physiological or subconscious cellars as his indeterminist colleague,
and hence feels just as free. Thus, whereas the new knowledge gained
through psychoanalysis does remove the grounds of fear, the knowledge
gained by the determinist is not at all of the sort that would remove
the grounds for the feeling of freedom. To make the persistence of this
feeling in the determinist an argument against his case is therefore a
confusion.
The second reason, I suggested, why so many thoughtful persons remain
indeterminists is that they are convinced that science has gone
indeterminist. Well, has it? If you follow Heisenberg, Eddington, and
Born, it has. If you follow Russell, Planck, and Einstein, it has not.
When such experts disagree it is no doubt folly for the layman to rush
in. But since I am discussing the main reasons why people stick to
indeterminism, and have admitted that the new physics is one of them, I
cannot afford to be quite prudent. Let me say, then, with much
hesitation that, as far as I can follow the argument, it provides no
good evidence for indeterminism even in the physical world, and that, if
it did, it would provide no good evidence for indeterminism in the realm
of will.
First as to physical indeterminism. Physicists now tell us that
descriptive statements about the behavior of bodies are really
statistical statements. It was known long ago that the pressure that
makes a football hard is not the simple quality one feels in pushing
something: it is the beating on the inner surface of the football of
millions of molecular bullets. We now know that each of these bullets
is a swarm of atoms, themselves normally swarms of still minuter
somethings, of which the proton and the electron are typical. The
physicist admits that the behavior of an enormous mass of these
particles, such as a billiard ball, is so stable that we may safely
consider it as governed by causal law. But that is no reason, he adds,
for assigning a like stability to the ultimate particles themselves.
Indeed, there is good reason, namely the principle of indeterminacy,
for saying that they sometimes act by mere chance. That principle tells
us that whereas, when we are talking about a billiard ball, we can say
that it has a certain momentum and direction at point S as a
result of having a certain momentum and direction at point A, we
can never say that sort of thing about an electron. Why? Because the
conditions of observation are such that, when they allow us to fix the
position exactly, they make it impossible to fix the momentum exactly.
Suppose that we can determine the position of a moving particle with
more accuracy the shorter the wave length of light we use. But suppose
that the shorter the wave length, the more it interferes with the
momentum of the particle, making it leap unpredictably about. And
suppose there is no way of determining the position without in this way
leaving the momentum vague, or of determining the momentum without
leaving the position vague. It will then be impossible to state any
precise law that governs the particle’s movement. We can never say that
such-and-such a momentum at point A was necessarily followed by
such-and-such a momentum at point B, because these statements can
have no precise meaning, and can be given none, for either antecedent or
consequent. Hence to speak any longer of nature as governed ultimately
by causal laws—i.e., statements of precise connection between antecedent
and consequent—is simply out of the question.
This argument, as Sir David Ross has pointed out, may be interpreted in
different ways. It may be taken to say that, though the particle does
have a certain position and momentum, we can never tell, definitely and
for both at the same time, what they are. Many interpreters thus
understand the theory. But so taken, there is of course nothing in it
to throw the slightest doubt on the reign of causality. It is merely a
statement that in a certain region our knowledge of causal law has
limits. Secondly, the theory might be taken to mean that electrons are
not the sort of things that have position and momentum at all in the
ordinary sense, but are fields, perhaps, or widespreading waves. This,
too, has no suggestion of indeterminism. It would not mean that general
statements about the nature and behavior of electrons could not be made,
but only that such statements would not contain references to position
and momentum. Thirdly, the theory might mean that, though these
particles do have a position and a momentum, the position or momentum is
not definitely this rather than that. Even laymen must rise at this
point and protest, with all respect, that this is meaningless.
Vagueness in our thought of a position makes sense; vagueness of actual
position makes none. Or, finally, the argument may mean that, though
the particle does have a definite position and momentum, these cannot
even in theory be correlated with anything that went before. But how
could we possibly know this? The only ground for accepting it is that
we do not know of any such correlates. And that is no reason for
denying that any exist. Indeed, to deny this is to abandon the
established assumption and practice of science. Science has advanced in
the past precisely because, when things happened whose causes were
unknown, it was assumed that they had causes nevertheless. To assume
that a frustration of present knowledge, even one that looks permanent,
is a sign of chance in nature is both practically uncourageous and
theoretically a non sequitur.
But let us suppose that the Eddingtonians are right and that what has
been called “free will among the electrons” is the fact. Would that
imply indeterminism in the realm that most nearly concerns us, the realm
of choice? I cannot see that it would. The argument supposed to show
that it would is as follows: Psychical processes depend on physical
processes. But physical processes are themselves at bottom
unpredictable. Hence the psychical processes dependent on them must
share this unpredictability. Stated in the abstract, the argument
sounds impressive. But what does it actually come to? We are told
that, even if there is inconstancy in the behavior of single particles,
there is no observable inconstancy in the behavior of masses of them;
the particles of a billiard ball are never able to get together and go
on a spree simultaneously. Eddington admitted that they might, just as
he admitted that an army of monkeys with a million typewriters might
produce all the books in the British Museum, but he admitted also that
the chance of a billiard ball’s behaving in this way were so
astronomically remote that he would not believe it if he saw it.
The question of importance for us, then, is whether, if acts of choice
are dependent on physical processes at all, they depend on the behavior
of particles singly or on that of masses of particles. To this there
can be but one answer. They depend on mass behavior. An act of choice
is an extremely complex process. It involves the idea of one or more
ends, the association of that idea with more or less numerous other
ideas, the presence of desires and repulsions, and the operation of
habits and impulses; indeed, in those choices for which freedom is most
demanded, the whole personality seems to be at work. The cortical basis
for so complex a process must be extremely broad. But if it is, the
great mass of cells involved must, by the physicist’s admission, act
with a high stability, and the correlated psychical processes must show
a similar stability. But that is what we mean by action in accordance
with causal law. So, even if the physicists are right about the
unstable behavior of single particles, there is no reason whatever for
translating this theory into a doctrine of indeterminism for human
choice.
We come now to the third of the reasons commonly advanced in support of
indeterminism. This is that determinism makes a mess of morality. The
charge has taken many forms. We are told that determinism makes praise
and blame meaningless, punishment brutal, remorse pointless, amendment
hopeless, duty a deceit. All these allegations have been effectively
answered except the one about duty, where I admit I am not quite
satisfied. But none of them are in the form in which determinism most
troubles the plain man. What most affronts him, I think, is the
suggestion that he is only a machine, a big foolish clock that seems to
itself to be acting freely, but whose movements are controlled
completely by the wheels and weights inside, a Punch-and-Judy show whose
appearance of doing things because they are right or reasonable is a
sham because everything is mechanically regulated by wires from below.
He has no objections to determinism as applied by physicists to atoms,
by himself to machines, or by his doctor to his body. He has an
emphatic objection to determinism as applied by anyone to his reflection
and his will, for this seems to make him a gigantic mechanical toy, or
worse, a sort of Frankenstein monster.
In this objection I think we must agree with the plain man. If anyone
were to show me that determinism involved either materialism or
mechanism, I would renounce it at once, for that would be equivalent, in
my opinion, to reducing it to absurdity. The “physicalism” once
proposed by Neurath and Carnap as a basis for the scientific study of
behavior I could not accept for a moment, because it is so dogmatically
anti-empirical. To use empirical methods means, for me, not to approach
nature with a preconceived notion as to what facts must be like, but to
be ready to consider all kinds of alleged facts on their merits. Among
these the introspectively observable fact or reflective choice, and the
inference to its existence in others, are particularly plain, however
different from anything that occurs in the realm of the material or the
publicly observable or the mechanically controlled.
Now, what can be meant by saying that such choice, though not determined
mechanically, is still determined? Are you suggesting, it will be
asked, that in the realm of reflection and choice there operates a
different kind of causality from any we know in the realm of bodies? My
answer is: Yes, just that. To put it more particularly, I am suggesting
(1) that even within the psychical realm there are different causal
levels, (2) that a causality of higher level may supervene on one of
lower level, and (3) that when causality of the highest level is at
work, we have precisely what the indeterminists, without knowing it,
want.
1. First, then, as to causal levels. I am assuming that even the
indeterminist would admit that most mental events are causally governed.
No one would want to deny that his stepping on a tack had something to
do with his feeling pain, or that his touching a flame had something to
do with his getting burned, or that his later thought of the flame had
something to do with his experience of its hotness. A law of
association is a causal law of mental events. In one respect it is like
a law of physical events: in neither case have we any light as to why
the consequent follows on the antecedent. Hume was right about the
billiard balls. He was right about the flame and the heat; we do not
see why something bright and yellow should also be hot. He was right
about association; we do not understand how one idea calls up another;
we only know that it does. Causality in all such cases means to us
little if anything more than a routine of regular sequence.
Is all mental causation like that? Surely not. Consider a musician
composing a piece or a logician making a deduction. Let us make our
musician a philosopher also, who after adding a bar pauses to ask
himself, “Why did I add just that?” Can we believe he would answer,
“Because whenever in the past I have had the preceding bars in mind,
they have always been followed by this bar”? What makes this suggestion
so inept is partly that he may never have thought of the preceding bars
before, partly that, if he had, the repetition of an old sequence would
be precisely what he would avoid. No, his answer, I think, would be
something like this: “I wrote what I did because it seemed the right
thing to do. I developed my theme in the manner demanded to carry it
through in an aesthetically satisfactory way.” In other words, the
constraint that was really at work in him was not that of association;
it was something that worked distinctly against association; it was the
constraint of an aesthetic ideal. And, if so, there is a causality of a
different level. It is idle to say that the musician is wholly in the
dark about it. He can see not only that B succeeded A; as
he looks back, he can see in large measure why it did.
It is the same with logical inference, only more clearly so. The
thinker starts, let us say, with the idea of a regular solid whose faces
are squares, and proceeds to develop in thought the further
characteristics that such a solid must possess. He constructs it in
imagination and then sees that it must have six faces, eight vertices,
and twelve edges. Is this association merely? It may be. It is, for
example, if he merely does in imagination what a child does when it
counts the edges on a lump of sugar. This is not inference and does not
feel like it. When a person, starting with the thought of a solid with
square faces, deduces that it must have eight vertices, and then asks
why he should have thought of that, the natural answer is, Because the
first property entails the second. Of course this is not the only
condition, but it seems to me contrary to introspectively plain fact to
say that it had nothing to do with the movement of thought. It is easy
to put this in such a way as to invite attack. If we say that the
condition of our thinking of B is the observed necessity between
A and B, we are assuming that B is already thought of as a
means of explaining how it comes to be thought of. But that is not what
I am saying. I am saying that in thinking at its best thought comes
under the constraint of necessities in its object, so that the objective
fact that A necessitates B partially determines our
passing in thought from A to B. Even when the explanation
is put in this form, the objection has been raised that necessity is a
timeless link between concepts, while causality is a temporal bond
between events, and that the two must be kept sharply apart. To which
the answer is: Distinct, yes; but always apart, no. A timeless relation
may serve perfectly well as the condition of a temporal passage. I hold
that in the course of our thinking we can easily verify this fact, and,
because I do, I am not put off by pronouncements about what we should
and should not be able to see.
2. My second point about the causal levels is that our mental processes
seldom move on one level alone. The higher is always supervening on the
lower and taking over partial control. Though brokenly and imperfectly
rational, rational creatures we still are. It must be admitted that
most of our so-called thinking moves by association, and is hardly
thinking at all. But even in the dullest of us “bright shoots of
everlastingness,” strands of necessity, aesthetic or logical, from time
to time appear. “The quarto and folio editions of mankind” can follow
the argument with fewer lapses than most of us; in the texts of the
greatest of all dramas, we are told, there was seldom a blot or erasure;
but Ben Jonson added, and no doubt rightly, that there ought to have
been a thousand. The effort of both thought and art is to escape the
arbitrary, the merely personal, everything that, causal and capricious,
is irrelevant, and to keep to lines appointed by the whole that one is
constructing. I do not suggest that logical and aesthetic necessity are
the same. I do say that they are both to be distinguished from
association or habit as representing a different level of control. That
control is never complete; all creation in thought or art is successful
in degree only. It is successful in the degree to which it ceases to be
an expression of merely personal impulses and becomes the instrument of
a necessity lying in its own subject matter.
3. This brings us to our last point. Since moral choice, like thought
and art, moves on different causal levels, it achieves freedom, just as
they do, only when it is determined by its own appropriate necessity.
Most of our so-called choices are so clearly brought about by
association, impulse, and feeling that the judicious indeterminist will
raise no issue about them. When we decide to get a drink of water, to
take another nibble of chocolate, to go to bed at the usual hour, the
forces at work are too plain to be denied. It is not acts like these on
which the indeterminist takes his stand. It is rather on those where,
with habit, impulse, and association prompting us powerfully to do X,
we see that we ought to do Y and therefore do it. To suppose that
in such cases we are still the puppets of habit and impulse seems to the
indeterminist palpably false.
So it does to us. Surely about this the indeterminist is right. Action
impelled by the sense of duty, as Kant perceived, is action on a
different level from anything mechanical or associative. But Kant was
mistaken in supposing that when we were determined by reason we were not
determined at all. This supposition seems to me wholly unwarranted.
The determination is still there, but, since it is a determination by
the moral necessities of the case, it is just what the moral man wants
and thus is the equivalent of freedom. For the moral man, like the
logician and the artist, is really seeking self-surrender. Through him
as through the others an impersonal ideal is working, and to the extent
that this ideal takes possession of him and molds him according to its
pattern, he feels free and is free.
The logician is most fully himself when the wind gets into his sails and
carries him effortlessly along the line of his calculations. Many an
artist and musician have left it on record that their best work was done
when the whole they were creating took the brush or pen away from them
and completed the work itself. It determined them, but they were free,
because to be determined by this whole was at once the secret of their
craft and the end of their desire. This is the condition of the moral
man also. He has caught a vision, dimmer perhaps than that of the
logician or the artist, but equally objective and compelling. It is a
vision of the good. This good necessitates certain things, not as means
to ends merely, for that is not usually a necessary link, but as
integral parts of itself. It requires that he should put love above
hate, that he should regard his neighbor’s good as of like value with
his own, that he should repair injuries, and express gratitude, and
respect promises, and revere truth. Of course it does not guide him
infallibly. On the values of a particular case he may easily be
mistaken. But that no more shows that there are no values present to be
estimated, and no ideal demanding a special mode of action, than the
fact that we make a mistake in adding figures shows that there are no
figures to be added, or a right way of adding them. In both instances
what we want is control by the objective requirements of the case. The
saint, like the thinker and the artist, has often said this in so many
words. I feel most free, said St. Paul, precisely when I am most a
slave.
We have now dealt, as best we can in a restricted space, with the three
commonest objections to determinism. They all seem to admit of answers.
To the objection that we always feel free, we answer that it is natural
to feel so, even if we are determined, since our faces are set toward
results and not toward causes, and the causes of present action always
elude us. To the objection that science has gone indeterminist, we
answer that that is only one interpretation of recent discoveries, and
not the most plausible one, and that, even if it were true, it would not
carry with it indeterminism for human choice. To the objection that
determinism would reduce us to the level of mechanical puppets, we
answer that though we are puppets in part we live, as Aristotle said, on
various levels. And so far as causality in reflection, art, and moral
choice involves control by immanent ideal, mechanism has passed over
into that rational determinism that is the best kind of freedom.
Posted December 14, 2011
Back
to Blanshard page