The
Howison Lecture for 1954. University of California Publications in
Philosophy, Vol. XXVIII, June 7, 1955, 93-112.
Posted
May 9, 2008
The Impasse in Ethics
and a Way Out
Brand Blanshard
I
Philosophy is sometimes thought the least progressive of intellectual
disciplines. Some departments in the field still use an introductory
textbook twenty-three centuries old. But however slowly philosophy
moved in earlier times, its pace has been greatly accelerated in the
years since the turn of the century. At that time there were at least
two disciplines in the field that seemed to have reached some
stability—logic and ethics. In a comparatively few years both subjects
have been torn down and reconstructed from the foundations. In the
first quarter of the century came Principia Mathematica, which
did more, I suppose, to transform the theory and practice of logic than
any other work since Aristotle. In the second quarter the same
root-and-branch reconstruction was attempted in ethics.
Thirty years ago it looked as if ethics had entered on a period of
Augustan calm. Something like general agreement seemed to be in sight.
Paulsen in Germany, Janet in France, Moore, Rashdall, and McTaggart in
Britain, Palmer, Fullerton, and Everett in America, all had been
converging toward the same position-described by Paulsen as
“teleological ethics” and by Hashdall as “ideal utilitarianism.” This
position was attractively simple and clear cut. Of the two chief
questions of ethics, What is good? and What is right? it held the first
to be primary: if you knew what kinds of experience were most worth
having, you could deduce what you ought to do; you ought to do whatever
was needful to produce the largest amount of good.
How were you to tell what was good? Certainly not by argument; if you
did not directly see that it was better to be happy than unhappy, no
further evidence would help. This did not mean that there was anything
irrational or arbitrary about your insights, any more than about saying
that in a parallelogram the opposite sides must be equal. You saw by an
intuition which was itself an act of intelligence that happiness must
have this further character.
Was happiness the only kind of experience that was thus intrinsically
good? No; by almost universal agreement, hedonism was rejected. Wisdom
and beauty and love, for example, had a goodness that was clearly not
exhausted by the happiness they brought with them. And what was this
goodness that such experiences had in common? It was nothing sensible
like yellow or sweet; it was not a natural quality at all if that meant
something that could be observed and measured scientifically.
Furthermore, it was so simple as to be beyond all logical analysis. It
was one of those fundamental notions like time and existence about which
we can say extraordinarily little, in spite of being perfectly familiar
with them. The position could be summed up in its rule of practice:
always so act as to produce the largest amount of intrinsic goodness,
goodness being a simple nonnatural quality that belonged self-evidently
to experiences of various kinds.
Now I do not think that the doctrine, put in this form, will stand.
Nevertheless, if there is any ethical theory toward which we can claim
a convergence of abler minds from Plato and Aristotle down, I think it
is this; and what I want to consider is how much of it is left after the
attacks of recent years. It has been subjected to three great waves of
criticism which many think have swept it finally away. First came the
attack of the deontologists, who held that the theory was mistaken in
basing the right on the good. Then came the emotivists, with their
contention that goodness was not a quality at all and therefore inhered
in nothing. Lastly came the naturalists, who insisted that even if
goodness were a quality it was a merely natural one, and therefore
ethics must give up its pretensions to being anything more than a
natural science. I lay no stress on the historical order of these
criticisms. The three waves came so close together that, whatever their
sequence, I feel free to deal with them in the order of convenience.
II
First, then, the deontologists. As early as 1912 H. A. Prichard of
Oxford began a revolt against the ruling ethics in an article that later
became famous, entitled “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?” His
answer to this question was Yes. The mistake lay in connecting duty
with interest or advantage, your own or anyone else’s. The ideal
utilitarians had argued that to ask what was your duty was to ask what
would produce the greatest good. Prichard admitted that in some
situations the answer to the second question would supply the answer to
the first. If the problem, for example, was what sort of scholarship to
endow, or what charity to support, it was only by knowing which would
carry with it the greatest good that you could know which you ought to
do. But suppose you had borrowed a book and promised to return it on a
certain day; would the question what you ought to do be settled by
knowing whether it would do more good to return it? Prichard said No.
It might be greatly to your advantage to keep it; would that justify
disregarding your promise? Obviously not; you should return it
nevertheless. If your duty was not thus based on your own advantage,
was it then based on the other man’s? No again; for he might have
forgotten the matter and felt no need of the book, so that your
advantage in keeping it would not be counterbalanced by any disadvantage
to him. Still, if you had promised to return it, return it you normally
should. The man of conscience who has made a promise does not stop to
calculate whether he or his friend or society is going to reap some
profit from his living up to it. He thinks it his business to live up
to it. If he is asked why, he does not turn to some balance sheet of
consequences; he says he ought to keep the promise because he made it;
period. In this, said Prichard, he is right. To justify keeping
promises by hunting for profit in so doing is not only futile; it is
wrong in principle, for it supposes that duty rests on prospective good,
whereas we can often see plainly that something is our duty when we have
no idea whether it will bring future good or not.
Prichard’s essay was strangely disregarded, and, preoccupied with other
problems, he let many years go by without pressing his case. But the
case was taken up by two able colleagues, first by E. F. Carritt and a
little later by Sir David Ross, whose two books The Right and the
Good and Foundations of Ethics are among the finest examples
of lucid argument in ethical literature. Ross maintained that however
plausible the rule might seem of pursuing the greatest good, it was open
to the two most fatal objections that can be offered to an ethical rule:
at times adherence to it was plainly wrong, and at times violation of it
was plainly right. He held that of two prospective courses it was
sometimes our duty to choose the one that, so far as we could see, would
do less good and leave the world worse off. To utilitarians of every
stripe this was a shocking thesis. Yet Ross held that, far from being
bizarre or irresponsible, it was the requirement of ethical common
sense. The strength of this surprising view will be clearer if we work
it out in an example, and we may as well choose our example from a major
virtue, justice.
In a certain town an outbreak of lawlessness takes the form of repeated
brutal assaults. The epidemic has been growing rapidly, and the
offenders have clearly been encouraged by the failure of the law to
catch up with them. At last a certain X is apprehended. His record
suggests that he is the ringleader; his connection with the latest crime
seems clear; and he is brought for trial before a local judge. The case
against him is overwhelming. There is only one circumstance that stands
in the judge’s way. He happens to know with certainty that the accused
man, notorious offender and general pest that he is, in this particular
case is not guilty. The judge happens, and he alone, to have caught a
glimpse of him elsewhere at the time of the crime. What is the judge’s
duty? If duty were merely a matter of producing the greatest good,
would he not have to reason as follows: “By convicting this man and
dealing with him severely, I shall probably halt an epidemic of
violence, and thus not only promote the common security but also,
perhaps, save a number of lives. These are extremely important ends.
What is to be set against them? The suffering or at least loss of
freedom of a man who is innocent of the crime alleged. But, after all,
he richly deserves on other counts whatever he may get. Is not the
suffering of such a man a small price to pay for the checking of
lawlessness . . . Ah, but then,” the judge reflects, “am I not leaving
out a most important consequence? What about respect for my court and
for courts generally? If it became known that a judge might deliberately
convict a man he knew to be innocent, people would lose confidence that
courts would give them justice, that acquitted men were not really
criminals, and convicts not really martyrs. Such a loss of confidence
would be sheer disaster.” But then he considers further. “What would
produce the disaster is not my convicting this man but only a public
knowledge of the facts, and it lies within my power whether this
knowledge will ever get out. Only the culprit and I know the truth. As
for him, nobody will believe him, no matter what he says. As for me, I
need only keep silence. By giving my verdict against the culprit while
locking one detail in my own mind, I can at once avert any discredit
that might accrue to the court and promote the public security. And is
not that the aim of courts anyhow?”
This is the sort of reasoning into which we are led, Ross believes, by
the ethics of the greatest good of the greatest number. Can we accept
it? He insists that we cannot, and surely we must agree with him. Here
is a case in which we are far more certain of the wrongness of
convicting an innocent man than of any theory on the other side; we
should say that such an act was monstrous, let the theoretical chips
fall where they may. “Very well,” Ross would say, “let us see where
exactly they do fall. You agree that convicting the man would be
wrong.” “Of course.” “You agree that a mere calculation of
consequences would make it out to be right?” “Apparently so.” “You
agree that if the judge did justice in this case, the lawlessness would
probably increase?” “Yes.” “And that this would be a worse state of
things than the alternative?” “Yes, I suppose so.” “But the judge
ought to do justice anyhow?” “Yes, clearly.” “Well, then,” Ross would
conclude, “you have admitted my whole case. You have agreed that, in
essence, duty has nothing whatever to do with producing the greater
good, and that it may be a man’s duty to choose a course that will make
the world worse.”
Now I must confess that, in spite of the argument, I find this
conclusion incredible. I agree that the judge should acquit the
innocent man; I cannot agree that in so doing he would be making the
world worse. Where, then, is the error in Ross’s reasoning? Some have
tried to find it by throwing into the scale the judge’s motive. They
suggest that, even if convicting the innocent man did produce the better
results, the deliberate intention of the judge was in itself an evil
which must outweigh any later good. But this is futile. For what
counts in a motive morally is the desire to do right, and it is
conceivable that the judge, even in convicting an innocent man, did so
out of a sincere regard for duty. He may have been muddled, but muddle
is not sin. We should consider his action wrong nevertheless. Hence we
cannot charge the wrongness of the action upon the badness of its
motive. If we are to show, as against Ross, that its wrongness lies in
any badness connected with it, that badness must lie neither in
consequences merely, nor in the motive merely, nor in both together.
Then where?
The person who gives a true answer to this question works, I think,
under a disadvantage. He cannot point to any particular person, time,
or place as the residence of the good he has in mind; and yet he is
convinced that it is because of this good that justice should be done.
Can he give any indication where it lies? Yes. Subject to an important
word of later comment, it lies in the set of relations that justice
would maintain between the judge, the prisoner, and the members of the
community. The judge is installed by those members to serve as their
intelligence and conscience in critical cases; his special business, to
which he pledged himself in accepting office, is to give judgment in
accordance with the evidence. Even if, in a given case, an unjust
judgment should lead to consequences as good as those of a just one, the
community in which justice is done is so far a better community. The
giving of a verdict against the evidence, from whatever motives, would
be a breach of faith not only with the prisoner but with the community
as a whole. It would involve at once the breaking of multiple
engagements, the telling to the public of an untruth, and the doing of
grave injustice. Now the keeping of engagements, the telling of truth,
and the doing of justice are essential parts of the community’s plan of
life. To violate them officially is to do far more than to injure a
particular person; it is to challenge and disrupt this plan of life as a
whole.
One may object that it will not disrupt this if the normal consequences
are cut off. But most men will not be convinced. They will say that
disruption may be a matter of logic as well as of consequences. To
forsake engagements, truth, and justice whenever a prospect of
particular advantage comes in view would be to weaken the claims of
these things throughout the range of our conduct; it would tear a huge
hole in the network of relations that makes society possible. This, I
think, is what really halts the plain man when he is invited to abandon
principle. It need not be any bad consequences on which he can put his
finger, nor yet the importance of anyone principle standing alone, for
he is ready to admit that in extreme cases an untruth must be told or a
promise broken. But even in these cases he violates principle with a
reluctance that is inexplicable if principles are simply means to
particular goods, and not wholly explicable even if they are taken, in
Ross’s way, as prima facie rules of right. What really moves us
is the sense—a vague sense, admitted—of remoter repercussions, of what
the breach of principle would mean for the fabric of our life as a
whole, a sense that if what is proposed were admitted, it would bring
down the house in which we are living about our ears. It is important,
we should all agree, that a crime wave should be discouraged. But it is
far more important to maintain those relations of honor, truthfulness,
and justice which touch our lives at a thousand points and make a
society like ours possible. If these things may be repudiated in their
own peculiar shrine, then, to put it crudely, anything goes. The
foundations of our communal life have caved in.
Ross denies this because he believes that, apart from its motives and
its consequences, there is nothing good in right action. He says
frankly that he “can see no intrinsic goodness attaching to the
life of a community merely because promises are kept in it.”1
But I doubt whether he can keep to this, even in his own thinking.
When he is criticizing the utilitarians, he offers a case that he
regards as decisive. Take two communities in which the amount of
happiness is the same, but which differ in one respect: in the first,
the material goods of life are distributed justly; in the second, they
are not. Ross argues that if the utilitarians are right it should make
no difference which community we choose, whereas it is obvious that we
ought to choose the former. I agree. But why ought we to choose
it? If it is not because justice would produce more happiness, is it
because justice is itself good? Ross could only say No; for in the mere
doing of justice, as in the mere keeping of promises, he would find no
good whatever. Is it then in the motives that would be at work in the
first community but not in the second? No again; for we may suppose
without inconsistency that in respect not only of happiness but also of
loyalty to duty the two communities are on the same level. Should we
still choose the first? I am sure that Hoss would say we should. But
once more, why? The natural answer is surely, “Because the first
community is better.” But this he cannot say. We ought to choose the
first, but for no reason at all. Though the first is not preferable, it
is still our duty to prefer it.
Now, with great admiration for Ross’s discernment, I cannot believe that
if he were asked why he would prefer the one to the other, he would
really be at his wit’s end, and able to say only, “You ought because you
ought.” I think he would naturally say, “You ought because a just
community is better than an unjust one.” And if so, he would be
admitting that even here the right derives from the good.
III
But the ideal utilitarian who thought that with this he had made out his
case was to receive a jolting surprise. It was hard to be told by
Prichard and Ross that his moral philosophy was based on a mistake. It
was far more dismaying to be told that his subject did not exist at all,
that there were no such things as judgments of good or evil, right or
wrong. This was the startling intelligence that was given him, with an
air of calm finality, by the new school of emotivists. To be sure, the
emotivists were subjectivists; and he had met subjectivists before. He
had read his Hume and his Westermarck, and was confident that the
weapons which had removed such Apollyons as these from his path could
deal with the pettier poltergeists that might appear in their train.
Hume had argued that the rightness of an action meant only that
society, viewing the action in the light of its consequences, felt an
emotion of approval toward it. But if this were offered as an account
of what people mean by “right,” it obviously would not do. The social
reformer insists that his cause is right, and goes on doing so while
knowing only too well that it is jeered at by almost everyone. He could
not possibly mean by its rightness that it now has general approval.
Nor was Hume’s case much strengthened by Westermarck, in spite of the
prodigious array of anthropological scholar-ship brought to bear on it.
According to Westermarck, the judgment of right or good was not a
statement that society approved of something; it was the statement that
one had approving feelings of one’s own.
It was against this position that G. E. Moore, in his little book on
ethics, offered arguments that came to be regarded as the definitive
refutation of subjectivism. Moore pointed out that if a moral judgment
states only how we feel about an act, we are landed in a nest of
absurdities. It would follow that on moral matters we were virtually
infallible, since we surely know how we feel about things. It would
follow that no two persons could ever agree in moral judgment, since if
Jones said an action was right all he meant was that he, Jones, had a
certain feeling about it; if Smith made the same remark, all he meant
was that he, Smith, had a certain feeling about it; and these were not
the same assertions. Further, Jones and Smith could not contradict each
other on these matters even if they tried. Smith’s statement that an
act was wrong would not contradict Jones’s statement that it was right;
it would merely record a different kind of feeling about it. And if
there is anything clear about our discussions of moral problems, said
Moore, it is that our beliefs do sometimes clash. A subjectivism which
tells us that such beliefs never do or can clash has ruled itself out by
its plain discordance with fact.
But now arose a kind of subjectivism undreamed of in Moore’s philosophy.
By agreement and difference he had meant agreement and difference in
opinion; and, to anyone who did mean that, the view that when two men
called an action right and wrong, respectively, they were not
contradicting each other must certainly seem absurd. But what if their
difference was not one of opinion at all but a diferrence merely in
attitude? Then these paradoxes about infallibility, agreement, and
difference would never arise. This was the new line taken by the
emotivists; “. . . sentences which simply express moral judgements,”
wrote Professor Ayer, “do not say anything. They are pure expressions
of feeling and as such do not come under the category of truth and
falsehood. They are unverifiable for the same reason as a cry of pain or
a word of command is unverifiable—because they do not express genuine
propositions.”2 The
emotivists held, like Prichard, that moral philosophy had been based on
a mistake, but the mistake was the more radical one of supposing our
judgments on moral matters to be judgments at all. When Ross called an
action right, they said, he was not stating a truth or even a falsehood;
he was asserting nothing whatever; he was merely expressing a feeling of
moral warmth toward the action. When G. E. Moore called the experience
of beauty intrinsically good, he was not saying something about the
experience, as he had always supposed he was, nor even about his own
feeling, as Westermarck suggested. He was only exclaiming about it; he
was saying “Hurrah for beauty!” The whole mass of our value judgments,
every assertion of right or wrong, good or evil, beauty or ugliness, is
thus removed at a stroke from the field of cognition into that of
emotion.
This theory, which has been called the “boo-hurrah” theory of ethics,
has been the most widely discussed ethical theory of the past two
decades; and its acceptance in one form or another by Russell and Ayer
in Britain, and by Carnap and Reichenbach in this country, has attracted
respectful attention to it. Though it is not an American product, the
fullest exposition of it must be placed to the credit of an American,
Charles L. Stevenson, of the University of Michigan.3
No one will deny that if true, it is extremely important.
The ideal utilitarians held that we could weigh the goods and evils
entailed by conduct against each other; indeed, that we could commonly
see the superiority of certain goods to others to be self-evidently
true, and this of course meant objectively true, in the sense that if
persons differed about it they could not both be right. This implied,
again, that at every moment of our waking lives there was some
objectively right act that we should try to find and do. It implied
that if two persons or two nations differed, there was always an
objectively right course waiting, so to speak, to be discovered, and
that tribunals had a ground on which to render impartial decisions. If
the emotivists were correct, all this was an illusion. The Japanese
felt enthusiasm about the attack at Pearl Harbor; we felt anger; but
there was no ethical character in the act, and no good or evil in the
consequence, that would justify either attitude, nor did it make sense
to say that there was any truth to be discovered as to the rightness or
wrongness of either side. As for the grounds on which an international
court might base judgments of guilt, we could only say that they did not
exist in fact, and could not even in theory. Such a court, if it tried
to pronounce judgment, would only be expressing another and third
feeling.
Can practical consequences of this kind be validly urged against the new
ethical theory? I do not think so. I do think that acceptance of the
theory would in fact discredit the notion of justice, interpersonal or
international, and that this would have unfortunate practical
consequences. But since I think that pragmatism too has been
discredited, I do not believe that any theory can be overthrown by
pragmatic considerations. The proposal must be dealt with, like other
theories, on the ground of its accordance or discordance with fact.
Where does it stand in this respect?
It offers itself as a statement of what is meant by judgments of value.
Does this signify what plain people actually mean, or what people mean
after they have critically examined their ideas? The two meanings may
of course be quite different. When the plain man says that grass is
green, he does not mean that its being green depends on the accident of
his seeing it; I think he assumes the green to be there whether anyone
sees it or not. When the college student whose innocence has been
corrupted by Berkeley says that grass is green, his meaning may be quite
different, namely, that there is something out there, not itself green,
which, when it works on his senses, makes him see green. Now emotivism
has been careless about telling us which meaning it has in mind. If it
is reporting the first kind of meaning, it has obviously missed the
mark. When the plain man calls murder “wrong” or suffering “bad” he
clearly does not imply that they would not be so apart from the accident
of his being aware of them; he would be puzzled, if not shocked, by any
such suggestion. He means to say something about murder and suffering
themselves. But of course the plain man may mean something which, if
considered in its implications, he would have no business to mean. The
question then is whether the plain man’s view, when considered in its
implications, is the more consistent with what the rest of our thought
and experience forces us to accept.
Now I think that it is the emotivist view which must yield. It would
require us to abandon ways of thinking which are far better grounded
than it is itself. Let me mention two of these which I have already put
in words and in print, apparently with no effect, on Matthew Arnold’s
desperate principle that “what I say three times is true.”
First, emotivism is irreconcilable with our way of thinking of past or
future values. There is some plausibility in saying, as Christian
Scientists do, that when we judge our present suffering to be bad, we
are expressing our own attitude merely, and that if this attitude were
changed, there would be no badness to express. There is somewhat less
plausibility in saying that when we judge a current famine in India to
be bad, we are saying nothing about the famine but only expressing our
own feeling about it. But I submit that there is no plausibility at all
in saying that when we judge the suffering in Buchenwald to have been
bad, all we mean to express is our present feeling. On this
interpretation, the suffering did in fact occur, but nothing that we now
express when we call it bad could have belonged to the suffering when it
occurred; for all the statement expresses is present feeling, and that
did not come into being till after the suffering was over. According to
this ingenious theory, nothing bad has ever occurred, or at least it is
meaningless to say it has. To be sure, the record of the race has been
full of things that we have always supposed to be major ills—disease,
war, want, fear, frustration, to say nothing of the infinite silent
suffering of the animal world. On the emotivist theory, it would
literally be without meaning to say that any of this was bad when it
occurred, since all that the term “bad” expresses is the present feeling
of the speaker. I can only say that this seems to me absurd.
It may be replied that the absurdity lies in a misreading of the
emotivist’s theory. When he calls this past suffering “bad,” a simple
and sensible meaning is open to him, namely, that a hostile feeling was
felt toward these things by the people of the time. But this, innocent
enough on the surface, surrenders the whole emotivist case. For it
admits that what was supposed to be a mere expression of feeling is in
truth a judgment, a judgment about how people in fact felt in the past;
that, like other judgments, it may be true or false; and hence that the
emotivist view, which denies this of value statements, is itself false.
Thus the theory is in a dilemma. If it adheres to the view that value
statements express present feeling only, then it cannot consistently say
that anything evil has ever happened, which is absurd. If it takes the
natural way of avoiding this absurdity, it contradicts itself.
Unfortunately its case is no better when it deals with the future; it
cannot hold that anything good or evil ever will happen. Of course, in
their role as sensible men, emotivists, like other people, talk
occasionally of the good time that is coming. But as emotivists they
must at once remind themselves that when they call it a “good” time,
they are saying nothing that will characterize it when it comes; they
are giving vent to their present feeling, that and nothing more. Since
that present feeling is over with the moment, nothing expressed by the
word “good” can belong to the future event. Now it may be that whenever
we say that anything good or bad ever has happened or will happen, we
are really talking nonsense. But for my own part, I find this less
plausible than that this ingenious theory has somewhere gone off the
track.
My second difficulty with emotivism is this: it renders all our
attitudes arbitrary and groundless. Attitudes are divided by emotivists
into pro- and anti-attitudes; when we call something good, we express a
pro-attitude; when we call it bad, an anti-attitude. Now if we are asked
why we take a pro-attitude toward something, we should no doubt answer
that it is because of something good in the object which makes such an
attitude appropriate. Why should we view with favor our children’s
happiness and cultivation, and with disfavor their ignorance and misery?
The natural answer, surely, is that happiness and cultivation are good,
and ignorance and misery bad. It would be arbitrary and groundless to
favor something if there was nothing good about it, or to disfavor it if
there was nothing bad. But from this natural answer the emotivist is
cut off. For him the object is not favored because it is good; it is
good, in the only legitimate sense, because it is favored. In itself,
and apart from such favoring, it is perfectly neutral. There is nothing
good in enlightenment or happiness or dutifulness which can make it
appropriate to favor them, nothing bad in pain or disease or death that
could justify aversion to them. The only good or evil is that with
which we invest an object through the attitude itself. But this implies
that we can never justify our approval or disapproval of anything, that
no pro- or anti-attitude is more appropriate than any other, since all
attitudes are equally without foundation in what is there.
For one who holds this view, I should suppose that the natural policy
would be never to approve or disapprove of anything. But since that is
hardly practicable, the most prudent line would surely be to call
everything good, since this is all that is needed to make it good in the
only sense in which anything is so. We are told that Walt Whitman was so
well disposed toward the world that he could greet the Brooklyn
telephone directory or a list of the Maine lakes with “whoops of
blessing.” I commend this attitude to the emotivists. If it seems
somewhat undiscriminating, let us remember that in the nature of things
there are no values to discriminate, and that it is a very short-sighted
economy that settles for geese when it may as easily have swans.
The view of the emotivists that there is no such thing as an objective
good seems, therefore, less convincing to me than the ancient and
honorable prejudice that it does exist. So far, then, the great
tradition in ethics, which holds that right action lies in producing the
greatest good, remains still open to us.
IV
But now comes the third wave of criticism. It is directed at a side of
the older theory that we have not considered, its distinction between
the “is” and the “ought.” When the ideal utilitarians concluded that
duty lay in seeking not the greatest pleasure but the greatest good,
they had on their hands the curiously baffling question what they meant
by “good.” This was a character owned in common by all good things, but
what sort of character was it? Pleasure was a feeling that could be
observed, but what was this rarefied something called “goodness,” which
was neither pleasure, nor knowledge, nor beauty, nor love, but an
essence distilled from all of them?
Moore struggled for long with this question, and concluded that goodness
is not a character in the “natural” world at all. When you perceive a
rose, you can smell its sweetness, feel its softness, and see its shape
and color, but when you say the experience is good, are you reporting
another quality of the same kind? Clearly not, says Moore. All these
other qualities are sensible, but no one has ever seen or otherwise
sensed goodness, any more than he has seen the light that never was on
sea or land. Very well, if we cannot sense it or point to it, perhaps
we can specify it by defining it. But no, it turns out to be so simple
that it cannot be dissected into parts, and is therefore beyond
defining. Its meaning is perfectly clear; its presence is easy to
recognize; it is almost as familiar to us as our hands and feet, but we
cannot say what it is.
Here doubts began to arise. To be sure, there are other familiar
concepts that prove to be highly elusive when we try to pin them
down—time, for example, and existence, and being awake. But these are
all complex, while goodness is supposed to be simple. And if a term is
at once simple and constantly on our lips, one would expect that what it
refers to would be clear. Yet when moralists began to think about
Moore’s analysis, many of them had to report doubt whether they had ever
known such a quality and indeed whether there was any such quality to
know. It was a philosophic will-o’-the wisp that dissolved when one
tried to lay hold of it. These doubts were strengthened when, after a
time, Moore himself began to doubt; at one point he confessed that he
was as strongly drawn by the emotivist view as by his old view of
goodness as a quality. Now if, when an analysis of a common meaning is
offered, many or most qualified persons can find nothing in their
thought that answers to the analysis, the criticism is inevitable that
the analysis has failed to catch what is really meant.
With this criticism I agree. It is the first of the three criticisms of
the older position with which I have been able to agree. Like many
others, I find it hard to verify this nonnatural quality of goodness.
But my difficulty goes beyond this; I think that goods and bads are
more firmly rooted in human nature than the ideal utilitarians would
admit. They refused to admit that in the meaning of good any part was
played by the gratifying of human impulses, the satisfying of human
needs, or the fulfilling of human desires. They conceded that these
sometimes served as conditions of our finding something good, but the
goodness never consisted of them even in part: it was a quite distinct
nonnatural quality that supervened on these satisfactions. I cannot
resist the conviction that the connection between goodness and
fulfillment is more intimate than this. If that is a prejudice, it is
at least one that is shared by a large and highly respectable company,
which includes Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Hobbes, Spinoza, Hegel, Green,
and Mill. They all held that the goodness of anything was so bound up
with the fulfilling of needs or desires that such fullfillment entered
into, and supplied in whole or part the very meaning of, goodness. In
the present sense of the term they were all of them naturalists. In
that sense I am a naturalist too.
Since the question involves analysis, may I venture a remark about this
treacherous process? When Socrates set the fashion for Western thinkers
in defining ethical terms, his method was a straightforward one;
perceiving that even when we were uncertain what a term meant, we could
often point with confidence to varying examples of it, he proposed that
we discover our meaning by asking what it was in virtue of which we
recognized these as examples, and that we do this by bringing to light
what they had in common. This is regarded by some present-day analysts
as too crude a method; for it is possible, they say, to find a set of
characters that is always present when goodness is present, and yet is
not strictly what goodness means. The proof of this is that we may use
the word “goodness” significantly without any explicit thought of the
characters named; and, further, that the question whether a thing could
be good without these characters is not instantly seen to be
meaningless.
I suggest that when analysis reaches this stage it has become so refined
as to be self-defeating. Not only does the term “good” have no one
meaning (Dr. Ewing has recently distinguished ten meanings), but even
when used in the restricted sense of intrinsically good, I see no reason
to think that its meaning is either clear or simple. Words are used
very much as checks are used, to transfer accumulated stores, and the
fact that no inventory is made of these at the time of transfer does not
imply that the checks are irredeemable. Behind this term “good,” which
we bandy about so readily as a counter, there lies a massive wealth of
meaning which for most purposes may be taken for granted, but which the
analyst ignores at his peril. If he assumes that the word means only
what is explicitly present whenever it is used, the result will be a
triumph of precise and lucid superficiality, which must be repudiated at
the first glimpse of what lies in its hinterland.
Very well, if goodness is not a quality but rather a complex of
characters of which the word is merely the opening gate, what is
included in this complex? Let me make such answer as I have to give
with the help of a famous case in ethical history. John Stuart Mill,
you will recall, concluded that goodness meant pleasure. Hence any
state of mind that was intrinsically good, whether an experience of
beauty or of wisdom or of champagne, was good in the precise degree of
its pleasantness. This led to an attractively simple solution of nearly
all the problems of ethics, and Mill regarded it with some complacency.
But when his friend Carlyle began to berate it as a “pig” philosophy,
he had second thoughts. He asked himself the classic question: if he
had to choose between the life of a pig, supported in the style to which
Mr. Wodehouse’s Empress of Blandings was accustomed, or an equal period
in the life of a harassed and henpecked Socrates, would he elect the
porcine bliss or the philosophic struggle? Could he put his hand on his
heart and say that the pleasure of the Socratic life was certainly
greater? No. Did he have the slightest doubt, however, that it would be
better to be Socrates in any case? No again, Mill confessed, with that
honesty and candor that made him so persuasive. But then what became of
his theory that the good lay in pleasure alone? His answer, of course,
was that though the Socratic life might not contain more pleasure
than the other life, the pleasure it did contain was so much better, so
much higher in quality, as to outweigh any deficit in quantity. By
pretty general agreement, this did more credit to his heart than to his
head. You cannot consistently say that, with their pleasantness equal,
one experience is better than another, and also that their goodness lies
in their pleasantness alone. It was all too clear that Mill was making
two major mistakes at once: first, in identifying goodness with
pleasure; second, in trying to combine this view with the admission that
goodness was other than pleasure.
Several generations of teachers and students have triumphantly pointed
out Mill’s blunders. But many, even in doing so, have felt that his
sane and honest mind had carried him very near to the truth. I own to
being one of these. I am inclined to think that goodness consists in
two components, both of which Mill more or less clearly recognized, and
that if he had seen the parts they really play, his theory on this point
would have been beyond cavil.
In the first place, he recognized that pleasure, or, as I prefer to call
it, satisfaction, is present in every state of mind that is
intrinsically good, and is inseparable from the goodness. This, I
submit, remains true even if goodness is not exhausted by pleasure.
Take one example. We who are in academic life call knowledge or
understanding good. Suppose that at one stroke we could achieve what we
are seeking, and have at our command all the knowledge and understanding
of what James calls the “quarto and folio editions of mankind,” but with
this one proviso added, that we should find no pleasure, take no
satisfaction, in it. Would it have any value for us? I am not asking
whether we might still choose it for its consequences to ourselves or
others; that is a wholly different question. I am asking whether it
would have intrinsic value for us, and suggesting that it would not.
Indeed, this answer has over and over again been forced upon those who
tried to evade it. It was forced upon the Stoics, who, in seeking to rid
themselves of feeling, found that as they lived more exclusively in the
gray light of reason, everything else turned gray. It was forced upon
Mill himself by the nervous collapse of his earlier years, when, having
lost the power to enjoy as the result of intellectual overforcing, he
found that the goods for which he was living had suddenly turned to dust
and ashes. Enjoyment is not all there is to goodness; at this date
there is no need to stop over that. But it is so essential to any
experience we call good that if it vanishes, the value vanishes with it.
Secondly, Mill recognized that of two states which are equally pleasant
one may be better than the other, and through the example he took he set
our feet on the right road, though he somehow missed it himself. What
is it that makes the life of Socrates more worth living than that of the
pig, whether pleasanter or not? Surely not the quality of his pleasure,
whatever that may mean, but something more obvious, something indeed
that stares us in the face. It is simply that in the mind of a great
thinker we have a richer fulfillment of the faculties that make us men.
In respect to his intelligence, Socrates is more of a man than we are,
more of what we want to be. The power, the need, the desire, to know is
fundamental in all of us. Its presence at a certain level is a defining
mark of human nature; the fulfillment in exceptional measure is what
marks off the large mind from the little one.
The same fact marks off even a lowly human mind from the animal mind.
Mill’s essay appears to have been written before The Origin of
Species, though it was published a year or two later. We see now,
as he could not, that running through the whole development of mind, and
determining its course, there is a continuous drive, or, rather, set of
drives, of which human nature itself is only the most recent expression.
One of these is the impulse to know, which is central in human nature
because its roots run deep into animal nature. Even in the dim-witted
four-footed cousin that Mill referred to, and in the midst of notorious
appetites in other directions, it flickers up into a vagrant curiosity.
In the higher apes it is far more active. In man, with his power to
look before and after, it is more restless and inquiring still. And,
despite Housman’s gibe that the love of truth is the faintest of human
passions, in a few men it burns up into a devouring, illuminating flame
that seems to light up for miles ahead the road which intelligence must
travel. Contact with such a mind is self-revelation; we seem to see for
the first time that this is what we are really about, this is what we
have been trying to do all along; we catch a glimpse, as Arnold would
say, of “the hills where our life rose, and the sea where it goes.” A
great mind is a great mind because it does what we are all trying to do,
only better. In sum, when we say that it is better to be Socrates than
ourselves, and ourselves than a fool, and a fool than a pig, we are
saying that in Socrates we have a completer fulfillment of a set of
drives or impulses that are continuous from one extreme to the other.
To say of an experience that it is intrinsically good means, then, two
things: first, that it satisfies; and second, that it fulfills.
Pleasure without fulfillment, as Aristotle saw, is hardly possible.
Fulfillment without pleasure, as Mill saw, is valueless. Of two
experiences that equally fulfill, the one we enjoy more is the better.
Of two experiences that we equally enjoy, the one that fulfills more is
the better. Of course fulfillment does not mean meeting our demands for
enlightenment only; it means meeting all the other demands of our nature
so far as they can be met without mutual suppression. The quiver of
human nature is full of arrows of desire, big and little, desires that
are fashioned from what we are, desires for food and drink and play and
friends and things of beauty. If anything fulfills and satisfies such
demands, it is ipso facto good; if it is utterly out of relation
to such demands, no one would think of calling it good.
It may be said that there are impulses in human nature whose indulgence
is evil, such as those of aggression and fear. But Professor Pepper has
shown fine insight, I think, in pointing out that these are not drives
with ends of their own; they are summoned up when other drives are
frustrated, and are nature’s means of intensifying these or safeguarding
them. When they do get out of hand and must be suppressed, it is not
because they are evil in themselves but because their fulfillment would
block other fulfillments. The doctrine that men are naturally evil, so
current in some theological circles, is thus the precise reverse of the
truth. To fulfill and satisfy what nature prompts is not only good; it
is what goodness means.
I have been speaking about goodness; but in thus conceiving goodness we
are also defining the nature of duty. Moralists have taken a strange
delight at times not only in making duty a “stern daughter of the voice
of God” but also in placing it “at enmity with joy,” in setting it up as
a hard-faced, alien censor of the natural man and his interests. There
are followers among us of that morbid prophet Kierkegaard who glory in
the thought that duty may demand of us what common sense and reflection
alike would brand as outrageous: “ours not to reason why, ours but to do
and die.” Against this reactionary irrationalism I would plead for the
naturalness of duty. Duty is no unintelligible command laid on us from
without. It is the voice of our own nature, the imperative of our own
reason, telling us that if our central strivings and those of others,
the ends that nature itself has set before us, are to be fulfilled, we
must act thus and not otherwise. This is not to deprive duty of its
force but to bring it home to us as authentic and reasonable. To the
man who declines to recognize duty we offer not some dubious authority
or a threat about the future, but a simple question or two. “Do you
want health, understanding, friendship?” “Yes, of course; they are what
make life worth while.” “If it is good that you should have them, is
there any ground for denying that it is good for others to have them?”
“No.” “Do you agree that course X is a necessary means if these things
that make life worth living are to be achieved?” “Yes, so it appears.”
“Then you cannot reject course X without repudiating your own reason
and the central demands of your own nature.”
V
It is time to bring our threads together. We saw that the great
tradition in ethics appeared to have ended in an impasse after two
thousand years. The rule of that ethics was so to live as to produce
the most good. This rule has been met in our day by three attacks: the
first against its goal, the second against its objectivity, the third
against its notion of goodness. The first attack, delivered from
Oxford, sought to show by such examples as that of the judge and the
innocent man that it is sometimes our duty to produce less than the
greatest good. To this I replied that the goods achieved by convicting
innocence would be far outweighed by the evil of destroying the pattern
of society in which justice was done. You may have felt when I made that
reply that there was something dubious about it, that a pattern of
society could hardly itself be intrinsically good. We have now seen
that, strictly speaking, that is true, that nothing is good but
consciousness, and consciousness in the joint form of the satisfaction
and fulfillment of impulse. It is because the general satisfaction and
fulfillment of our nature is bound up inextricably with a pattern of
society in which justice is done that this pattern must be held
inviolable. The right to freedom from arbitrary hurt to our persons,
our possessions, our actions, or our name is one of the plainest
conditions of that fullness of life in which its goodness is now seen to
consist. To encourage those in power to violate that pattern at will
for local expediencies is to seek a special good by an act which would
in principle put all goods in jeopardy; it would be like the dog’s
dropping of its bone for the shadow in the river. There is, of course,
nothing new in this contention. If I am not mistaken, it is a return to
the vision of Plato, who held that in the end the justification of every
act lay in its place in the form of the good life.
Is this life objectively good? Running alongside the great
tradition which from Plato down has held that it was, there has been a
secondary tradition, stretching from Callicles to Russell, which held
that it was not, and that goodness is as variable as man’s fluctuating
feeling. We have seen that in the latest and probably most formidable
shape which that theory has taken it conflicts with universal ways of
thinking about right and wrong. But we saw when we turned to the third
and final criticism that this theory is by no means groundless.
Goodness is dependent on the feeling and impulse of conscious minds.
It consists in the satisfaction and fulfillment of human nature. Does
this destroy the objectivity of our judgments of good and evil? On the
contrary, it provides a clear meaning for their objective truth and
frees that truth from any dependence on individual thought or feeling.
It bridges the chasm between fact and value. It enlists science,
especially psychology, in the service of morals. It answers sensitively
to our reflective judgments of better and worse. It naturalizes duty,
and rationalizes its authority. It offers a standard responsive alike
to men’s deeper identities and to the surface differences of nature and
desire. In a time when skepticism about personal morality and pessimism
about international morality seem to be the order of the day, it holds
that to be moral is in the end to be natural and reasonable and sane.
Notes
1
W. David Ross, Foundations of Ethics (Oxford, Clarendon Press,
1939), p. 142.
2
Alfred J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic (2d ed.; London, Victor
Gollancz, Ltd., 1948), pp. 108-109.
3
Ethics and Language (New Haven, Yale University Press, 1944).
Back to Blanshard page