In the end, then, every political
right must be defended on moral grounds. But we cannot leave the matter
there. For moral and political rights are not simply identical; there
are many moral rights that no one would call political, for example, the
right to be spoken to courteously and the right of parents to the
consideration of their children. Political rights are rights that are,
or appropriately may be, guaranteed by government, that is, by enforced
law. Now it is clear that there are “rights” thus enforced by law for
which many who must heed them can find no moral justification at all.
But now for the real difficulty. The state claims the right, for
example, and enforces it by heavy penalties, to reach down into the
pockets of its citizens and take a large part of their income for its
own purposes. Many of these citizens are convinced not only that the
particular purposes for which the state will use this money are bad, but
also that an income tax as such is a policy opposed to the general good.
To tell these people that what they regard as a wicked tax imposed for
wicked purposes is a moral right, on all fours with the right to
truthful speech and civil treatment, is not unlikely to provoke jeers.
Clearly there is a missing link in the argument. These people are told
that it is a moral obligation to do what produces the greatest good.
They believe that a law passed by their government is inimical to the
public good, and are told that they should obey it nevertheless. That
may be a political obligation, but to call it a moral obligation looks
very much like self-contradiction. How is one to make out that it is
their moral duty to obey a law that they disapprove? This is probably
the most searching question in political theory.
I believe that the true answer to
this question has been given by philosophers over and over again, and
that it is not the exclusive property of any school. But it has had a
history so unfortunate as to rob it of much of its persua-siveness. It
was suggested by Rousseau, but, as presented by him, was so embedded in
mythology and bad argument that one can extract it only with difficulty
from his incoherent text. It was stated again by Hegel, but was made an
integral part of a system of logic and metaphysics which most
philosophers have found it impossible to accept; besides, it came to be
associated, partly by his own fault and partly not, with Prussian
nationalism, which after precipitating two wars, earned general
detestation. The doctrine was taken over from Hegel by the British
idealists and given a more judicious statement by T. H. Green, whose
Principles of Political Obligation remains, I think, the weightiest
work in English on political theory. It was presented again by
Bosanquet in The Philosophical Theory of the State, but with
needless obscurity and with certain expressions that sounded
suspiciously like endorsements of absolutism and nationalism. These
were seized upon by L. T. Hobhouse in his Metaphysical Theory of the
State and made the focal points of the most thorough-going attack
that has been made on the theory.
Rousseau called his version a theory
of the “general will”; Hegel and Bosanquet talked, instead, of the “real
will”; if the version about to be presented is to have a name, I should
prefer the “rational will.” It may be of interest to say that my own
conviction of the truth of the theory came through reading Hobhouse’s
attack on it. It had been so long out of favour and was mentioned with
such general deprecation that, having made no careful study of it, I had
come to think of it as pretty certainly indefensible. Its association
with the name of Hegel, and the many attempts to link Hegelianism with
Fascism did not help, though I follow Principal Knox in holding that the
occasional outbursts of Prussianism in Hegel are excrescences on his
system, and not organic to it. When I ap-proached the doctrine of the
real will, I began by reading the critics of the theory, expecting at
least to find some amusement in watching the work of demolition, and
thinking I should be more likely to find intelligibility among the
critics than among the exponents. The first two or three broadsides I
reviewed left me in mild surprise, for the target was still visibly
standing when the roar had subsided and the smoke cleared away. But
these were guns of low calibre. So I turned to Hobhouse, who had, I
understood, destroyed the theory utterly; and as I warmly admire his
work, I sat down to him expectantly. But as the arguments in the
heralded parade limped slowly past, a conviction gradually formed itself
in my mind. If this was really the best that could be said against the
theory of the real will, I had been deceived about it. Wave after wave
of argument broke against it only to leave it, so far as I could see,
standing aggressively intact. By the time I was half way through the
book, I had begun to think the case for it impregnable; at the
end, my conversion was complete. I thought then, and have never wavered
in thinking since, that this doctrine, if one penetrates through the
sorry form in which it has so often been expressed, and gets rid of
associations that cling to it like barnacles, offers the firmest
available core for political theory.
The doctrine is quite simple. It is
that men have a common moral end which is the object of their rational
will, that the state is a contrivance that they have worked out to help
them realize that end, and that its authority over them rests on its
being necessary for that end. If it is politically obligatory at times
to obey a law that one regards as bad, that is because the state could
not be run at all if the citizens could pick and choose which laws they
would obey. Ultimately, therefore, political obligation, even that of
obeying a morally bad law, is a moral obligation; and when, as
occasionally happens, it becomes a duty to disobey, the ground is still
the same. I believe that this simple doctrine is what all the
philosophers who have defended a “real” or “general” will, from Rousseau
to Bosanquet and even Hobhouse himself, have in fact been arguing for.
I shall not try to prove this by historical inquiry, for my prime
concern is not whether the doctrine I seem to find in them is actually
theirs, but whether it is true. The doctrine that does seem to me true
may be expanded and made more explicit in four propositions: First, we
can distinguish within our own minds between the end of our actual or
immediate will, and the end of our rational will, which is what on
reflection would commend itself as the greatest good. Secondly, this
rational end is the same for all men. Thirdly, this end, because a
common end, is the basis of our rights against each other. Fourthly,
the justification of the state, and its true office, lies in furthering
the realization of this end. Let us try to get these points clear.
It is puzzling at first to hear of a
real or rational will which can be set over against our actual will. Is
not our actual will our only will, and whatever goes beyond this, myth?
On the contrary, it is easy to see that what we have here is a
distinction of the first importance. A man goes to a dealer and buys a
motor-car. There is no dispute about his actual will; it is simply to
possess the car; that is what he immediately and unmistakably wants. Is
there any sense in saying that he has a further and rational will that
goes beyond this and might even veto it? Yes, undoubtedly; in fact,
unless we concede such a will we shall never understand what really
moves him. If possessing the car were an ultimate end, the question
“Why buy it?” would be meaningless. But the buyer would be the first to
insist that it was anything but meaningless, and if he were like other
eager buyers he would readily explain that the car was a means to all
sorts of advantages, personal, professional, and social, and these,
perhaps, means to still further advantages to a widening circle of
beneficiaries. In short, he wills to buy the car, but he wills it
subject to tacit conditions as to how it will contribute to an end
beyond itself. The evidence that these conditions exist lies in what
would dissuade him from the purchase. Convince him that through buying
the car he will not advance his business, that his son and daughter
being what they are, it will probably involve them in accidents, and
that if he carries the purchase through, he cannot move into the larger
house that is the family’s most pressing need, and he will not
improbably cut the whole business short. If his actual will were
self-contained, if it were the end of the line rather than a link in a
chain whose point of attachment lies far beyond it, all this would be
irrelevant. It is only because his explicit will is not exhaustive,
because its object is a means to a further end, or a piece in a larger
picture which is more fervently wanted than itself, that his immediate
will can admit such correction. He may hardly have known that he wanted
these ulterior things; at the moment of buying he was probably not
thinking of them; but if, the instant he sees how his will of the moment
bears on them, he sets that will aside, is it not natural to say that in
contrast to the objects of his actual will, they are the objects of his
real or rational will?
This line of reasoning, we may be
told, leads to an unplausible consequence. For if his present will is
thus open to correction by ulterior considerations of advantage to
himself and his family, these considerations themselves will in turn be
open to correction by still further con-siderations, for example, his
duty to his pro-fession, his community, and his country. “What you are
saying, then, is that the object of a man’s real or rational will is
that which an ideally competent reflection would show to be the greatest
good attainable in the circum-stances. No doubt with ideal powers this
is what he ought to will. But you are saying that he does in fact will
what he ideally ought to will, and that is absurd.”
I do not think it is. To be sure,
one may easily enough prove it absurd if one takes the two wills on the
same level of explicitness. If to will something must mean to will it
immediately and with full awareness, then the suggestion that we always
will what it would be best to will is absurd. Very well then; out with
the word “will”; we are not insisting on words; we are insisting on what
we take to be a fact, and one of the prime facts of the moral life.
Writers describe it variously. The theologian would say that at our
best we remain miserable sinners; the moralist that we never do our
whole duty; the poet that “what I sought to be, and was not, comforts
me.” However capricious or selfish or brutal a man may be in actual
behaviour, if we are right in calling him a moral being at all, what he
is trying to be and do is never exhausted in what he is. Whenever he
makes a judgment of better or worse, whenever he does anything because
he thinks he ought to do it, even when he thinks this without doing it,
he is recognizing a claim as prior to the wants of the moment and
conceding it the right to overrule them. A man may flout this claim to
any extent in practice, and protest that he neither recognizes it nor
tries to fulfil it. Is his protest to be accepted? Surely not. We
could point, if we knew him well enough, to a thousand actions that
belie his own report. He continually defers present good to a later and
greater good, corrects impulsive choices by reflection, recognizes the
force of another’s claim when at the moment he would prefer not to. In
doing so, he concedes the claim of a rational good upon him, a claim
which, if he is consistent, he must admit to have overwhelming force in
confirmation or in veto of the will of the moment. We agree that he
does know in detail the object of this larger will. We agree that it is
not a will at all in the simple straightforward sense in which the will
of the moment is such. But it remains a will in the extremely important
sense of an ideal to which the man by implication commits himself every
day of his life and whose claims he cannot repudiate without turning his
back upon himself.
If this is true, the distinction
must be accepted between a man’s actual will and his ulterior will, his
real or rational will. That was our first point. The others may be
dealt with more briefly.
The second was that the end or
object of the rational will is the same in everyone. This looks
questionable. But the fact is that we could not even argue with each
other with any point unless it were true. Consider the matter first on
the side of theory. When we argue, we both assume that there is a truth
to be found, that its discovery is our common end, and that there is a
standard way of gaining it. If we differ as to whether President
Madison preceded or followed President Monroe, we have no doubt that one
did precede the other, or that if the evidence is rightly assessed, it
will point one way. If this were really in doubt, there would be no
sense in arguing at all. What would be the use of your trying to
convince me if what was proof to you was in the end mere fallacy to me?
The very essence of your attempt to show me my mistake lies in appealing
to our common end, namely to grasp what fact and logic require, and if
you can show that in this respect or that I have fallen short of these
re-quirements, you expect me to see and acknowledge my error. Unless
our thinking is governed by the same ideal, unless what would ultimately
satisfy you as cogent evidence or conclusive proof is assumed to be the
same as what would satisfy me, argument is a waste of time. So long as
we do make that assumption, there is hope. Argument is the joint appeal
to a fundamental agreement in the hope of extending it to remove a
relatively superficial disagreement.
The same holds on the practical
side. Men expostulate with each other over wrongdoing just as they
argue over fact. Now when another expostulates with me over an action
that seems to him wrong, what sort of argument must he use if he is to
convince me? He must show me that the action I am considering will not,
as I suppose, subserve the sort of ends that we approve in common.
Suppose he finds me set on buying the motorcar, and thinks it a mad-cap
scheme; his argument will take essentially the following form: “You
think it of the first importance, don’t you, that one’s family should be
comfortably and healthfully housed?” “Yes.” “Well, if you buy the car,
you must sacrifice that end for occasional pleasures that you admit
yourself to be less important.” That is, he appeals to an end about
which he feels confident that I agree with him, and tries to show me
that the action I am proposing would defeat it rather than promote it.
If I were to betray to him that I had no interest whatever in the
welfare of my family, he would be at a loss how to proceed, for his
argument assumes that I attach the same value to this that other sane
men do. Put in the abstract, what he is saying is: “You agree with me
that E is the important thing at stake; if you do M you will jeopardize
it; if you do N you will get it; therefore you should do N.” Unless
there is some broad agreement on the ends that are worth pursuing,
neither of us would have any purchase on the thought of the other.
There is, to be sure, an element of
paradox in this view. If the Russians get involved with the Americans
in an argument over practical politics, does it really make sense to say
that they are both driving at the same ultimate end? Yes, I think it
does, and thinking so increases my hope in the work of an international
forum where they may meet and canvass their differences. Indeed,
considering the bitterness of their differences, their professed ends
are surprisingly near to identity. The Russians insist that they
believe as strongly as the “demo-cracies” in the dissemination of
knowledge, in freedom for the masses of the people, in the cultivation
of literature and the arts, and in the increase through applied
knowledge of the comfort, health, and happiness of mankind. Their
difference with the west is not in our accepting and their rejecting
these goods, for both parties avow devotion to them; the difference is
that whereas the communists think that capitalism is an atrociously bad
means to these ends and communism an exceedingly good one, the west
thinks that communism is a bungling and tyrannous means to them and a
“free economy” a more effective one. The United Nations has been
treated to many strange scenes and strange arguments, but it has not
yet, I think, been invited to listen to a plea for ignorance, misery,
and slavery as the true ends of man. Since all alike accept certain
ends, they can argue with some point about the means. If the Russians
were seeking ends that really had nothing in common with ours, if they
were aiming, for example, at unhappiness in widest commonalty spread,
discussion with them would take a remarkable form; when we offered an
argument to show that a Russian move was calculated to increase human
misery, we should be greeted at the end with applause and the
exclamation, “Bravo; you put our case admirably.” It is happily to be
doubted whether among sane and candid men this ultimate difference about
ends ever occurs.
The third proposition is that our
rights against each other are based on our common ends. Smith borrows
money from Jones, and when the debt falls due, Jones claims the right to
repayment. On what ground? Not, surely, on the ground alone that it
furthers his own interest, since that might not be Smith’s, nor on the
ground alone that it is Smith’s interest; to say that would too often be
hypocritical and false. To get the key, we must ask another question,
Is Jones’s right to be repaid the same as Smith’s duty to pay? We have
seen that in substance it is, since a duty is the obverse side of a
right. When Jones presses his claim against Smith, he is therefore
insisting on Smith’s duty to repay. Why is it Smith’s duty to repay?
Duty, as we have seen, is always based on the production of good. What
is the good in this case? It is not merely Jones’s satisfaction in
getting his money back, though that will form part of the end for any
considerate debtor. It is also the maintenance in society of a state of
things in which promises are kept and debts repaid. When Jones presses
his claim against Smith, he is saying in effect, “You believe, do you
not, as I do, that this state of things is better than one in which
promises are broken and debts repudiated? Very well, if you do, your
only consistent course is to pay.” That this common end is the basis on
which Jones is urging his right may be clearly seen by his helplessness
if Smith rejects it. Suppose Smith rejoins, “I see no value whatever in
a state of things in which promises may be relied on or debts repaid;
this may be an end or good for you; it is not for me.” What could Jones
do? He could threaten him with the police, but that is not argument,
and no argument he could offer would carry the least validity for Smith.
To urge that Smith seek a good which for him was no good at all would
be absurd. Jones’s case in its entirety rests on the assumption that he
and Smith are seeking a common end, and that when the repayment of the
debt is seen to be required by that end, Smith will recognize it as his
duty and do it. But that he should so recognize and do it is precisely
what Jones is claiming as his right. To put it generally, your right
against me and my duty to you rest on an identical ground, namely their
necessity to our joint end.
Now for the fourth proposition: it
is because the state is the greatest of instruments to this common end
that it has such rights as it possesses over its citizens. The state is
more than a system of rights. If half a dozen hunters met by accident
in the woods, such rights would hold among them, but this could not make
them into a state. A state is a set of institutions—a legislature,
courts, police, a chief executive—designed to give effect to these
rights, to guarantee them in practice. The state is thus a means, not
an end. It is a system of brakes and prods applied in the interest of
reaching a goal beyond itself.
The simplest evidence for this lies
in the answer we naturally give to two related questions, Why should I
obey the law? and Why may I sometimes resist it? The answers to both
are the same, and they amount to an admission that the state is an
attempt at the embodiment of a common rational will, and is justified
only as the instrument of that will. Why should I obey the law by doing
anything so disagreeable as paying my income tax? Not because I have
to, since with enough cleverness I might evade it, nor because I can
point to any definite advantages to me or anyone else that would result
from this particular act. I should obey it if at all because it belongs
to a system of commands and restraints whose maintenance serves better
than any available alternative as an instrument for the common good.
It is needless to work this out in
detail. Everyone knows that a government is often a nuisance, whose
rules about parking cars, stopping at street lights, paying taxes,
keeping walks clear, and all the rest, are a source of endless major and
minor frustrations. We all believe, nevertheless, that though
government is a nuisance, it is a wholly indispensable nuisance. Why?
Because without it the main goods of life, and for that matter life
itself, would be insecure. If we can count on our house and its
contents not being taken away from us, if the shops that supply our
clothes and fuel and food are able to do their business, if there are
roads on which we can get about, schools to send our children to, courts
and police to deal with those who would take advantage of us, it is
because behind these arrangements, protecting and guaranteeing them, is
the power of the state. Without it we should be at the mercy of the
worst elements in our society. We may concede to communists and
anarchists that if the ends men are seeking in common could be realized
without the com-plex and expensive machinery of government, it should be
dispensed with. We cannot agree with them in supposing that, human
nature being what it is, there is any prospect whatever of attaining
these goods except with the aid of the state.
Does it follow that since the state
is a necessary means to our major ends, we should in all circumstances
obey it, that we never have the right to rebel? Not at all. Our view
would not only justify disobedience in some cases; it would require it.
If the state is regarded, not as sacrosanct or an end in itself, but as
an instru-ment to certain great ends, then when it be-comes so corrupt
as to cut us off from those ends rather than further them, when it
serves its purpose so badly that it is better to risk chaos for the sake
of a better order than continue to suffer under the old, then resistance
becomes a right and a duty. This will be an extreme and desperate case,
since it will obviously be better as a rule to obey what we regard as a
bad law and try by persuasion to get it amended than to seek the
overthrow of the power which supports all laws alike. But there is no
doubt that when government has ceased to serve its major ends, the
people who have fashioned it to serve those ends have a right to replace
it with something that serves these better. In doing so, they will
appeal to the same ends that earlier led them to support it, and they
will do so with full consistency and justification. Thus the theory of
a rational will provides a natural and intelligible ground both for
obedience in normal cases and for disobedience in abnormal cases. It is
hard to conceive what better evidence could be offered for it.
Here then is a theory of political
obligation. It holds that each of us is seeking an end that goes beyond
the good of the moment, that besides his will of the moment for food,
drink, and comfort, he has a rational will directed far beyond these to
what would satisfy in the light of a fully critical reflection. The
nature of that end we have explored in earlier chapters. At best it is
conceived vaguely and pursued waveringly, but its presence nevertheless
is both the magnet that draws us on and the monitor that reproves when
we stray out of the way. This end, we have held, is the end of all men.
Because it is, each can justly claim of another that he should be loyal
to it; that is what we mean by a right. The state itself is an
arrangement accepted as a necessary means to this ultimate end, and on
this necessity rests its right to obedience.
This account of political obligation
seems to me at once simple and compelling. There is probably nothing
novel about it. Indeed I have suggested that it was what all the
defenders of a real and general will, from Rousseau to Bosanquet, were
in substance contending for. Rousseau maintained that in all men there
is a will toward the same moral end, that government is a device set up
by that will through a contract or agreement, that this will, as a
striving for the good is, by definition, never wrong, though even the
“will of all” may mistake what it really requires, and that its
requirements, even as to the structure of government, may vary greatly
with circum-stances. In these contentions I think Rousseau was right.
Unfortunately this core of sound teaching was embedded in a mass of
myths and mistakes that were as adventitious to it as moss to a stone.
Rousseau dimmed and confused a remarkable insight when he held that men
are animated by self-interest only, that the general will is aimed at a
queer, scarcely thinkable abstraction in which their selfish wills
coincide, and that the government can impose no burden and confer no
advantage except upon all alike. Indeed his doctrine as presented is so
incoherent that all one can hope to derive from it is a general drift—a
drift in the right direction nevertheless.
Something similar must be said of
Hegel. His insistence that an identical and rational end was working
itself out through individual minds, that every society showed in its
laws and customs the working of this will, and embodied it in differing
degrees, all this and much else that this astonishing intelligence had
to say about politics is true. Unfortunately he put himself in the
wrong with all manner of persons who would otherwise have been disposed
to listen by talking gratuitious nonsense about the state as der Gang
Gottes in der Welt, holding that the success of a state in
dominating others was somehow evidence of its right to do so, arguing
that the relations of states cannot be judged by moral standards, and
suggesting that the state is not only an attempt to embody reason, but,
in the case of the dominant state of the time, does embody it so fully
that the citizen will achieve his highest morality by conforming to it
and will have no case if he resists it. How far such doctrines belong
to the essence of Hegel’s political theory is a matter of dispute; I am
myself inclined to think that they are extraneous to it.1
But he cannot be acquitted of having said things that gave apparent
benediction to totalitarian violence and oppression, and anyone holding
a doctrine akin to his must be at pains to show that the charges heaped
upon it do not apply to his own. That the inspiration common to the
contract theories and to the Hegelians is really innocent of these
charges can be shown easily enough. It will pay us to look briefly at
the worst of the accusations.
The theory, it is said, would not
only justify but glorify wrong. If the state is the instrument of the
general will, and the general will is a will to the moral end itself,
what embodies this will must be right. Hence whatever the state does,
however tyrannous and brutal, is to receive our benediction. Each of us
is supposed to realize, Hobhouse says,
That in society he is in the pre-sence
of a being infinitely higher than himself, contemplating a rea-son much
more exalted than his own. His business is not to endea-vour to remodel
society, but to think how wonderfully good and rational is the social
life he knows, with its Pharisees and publicans, its gin-palaces, its
millions of young men led out to the slaughter, and he is to give thanks
daily. . . . . [Such a doctrine] instead of seeking to realize the
ideal, idealizes the real.2
Harold Laski wrote in similar vein:
For him [Bosanquet] the good is
always being realized. The subserving of our real will with the will of
the state is taken to mean that the best that can happen to us is in
fact happening at each mo-ment.3
Now if the doctrine of the rational
will is examined, not in the light of occasional foolish phrases, but in
the light of its essential drift, one can see that not only does the
above inference fail to follow; the only legitimate inference is quite
the opposite.
The real will goes beyond the actual
will; it does so everywhere and always. That is the point of the
contrast between them. The good that would completely satisfy me is
never achieved in this act or that. To recognize the real will is to
arouse discontent with what is, to indict the good I have actually
achieved in the light of what might be. To say, in the individual
case, that the recognition of the real will meant somehow glorifying the
actual would be so patently contrary to the point of the distinction as
to wear its falsity on its face. How is the case different when we turn
to the will of a community? The recognition of a real will is the
recognition that there is a greatest good for that community and that it
is the business of the citizens to regulate their communal life so that
this good may be as fully embodied as possible. The very insistence on
the distinction implies that it is not so embodied now. To be sure, the
doctrine implies that one is ordinarily to obey the law, but, as we have
seen, one cannot so much as state the reason for that obedience without
acknowledging an authority above the law, which we may invoke against
the law itself if that should fail.
The second charge against the theory
is that it would give the state a power over the individual which is
complete and beyond appeal. If he dares to call it in question, he is
told that the maintenance of this state and its laws is what his real
will desires, and that if he appeals from Philip drunk to Philip sober
within himself, he will see that he has no case. To some critics of the
general will, this is the least pardonable part of the doctrine. Mr
Laski thinks it absurd to say that
constraint is not the use of force
by the state against the individual, but only its imposition upon him of
the will which his real will desires. . . . Most of us, I think, would
argue that the revolutionist is never conscious that the government
which imprisons him is giving his true self freedom. What he
experiences is constraint; and he regards that as a denial of his
liberty. To tell him that he is made free when he is prevented from
fulfilling the purpose he regards as the raison d’etre of his
existence is, I would suggest, to deprive words of all their meaning.4
The climax of absurdity is thought to be reached when the theory touches
punishment. It is bad enough to say, when a law is passed which we
tried to prevent, that the law is what we really wanted, and to compel
us on this ground to obey it; but it is one degree worse to tell us,
when we have been put in jail for resisting it, that we were really
hungering and thirsting for incarceration at hard labour. To take this
line is to cut from under our feet any ground to stand on in protest; it
is to reduce us to the level of children who are to be told by persons
wiser than they what is good for them and what is not. And it is to
outlaw resistance to tyranny as the manifestation of wayward self-will.
Most of us would agree with the
temper of this remonstrance; at least I should myself. For anyone,
however high in authority to presume to tell others over their protests
what is good for them is a repellent and dangerous business. But there
are several things to be said about it.
First, the problem here involved is
not peculiar to the theory advocated; it confronts every theory and form
of government that is worth considering. It is the business of
government as such to find and promote the good of its people. But
there are nearly always persons, sincere and high-minded persons, who
believe that what the government proposes is neither for their own good
nor anyone else’s, and who are prepared to resist its mandates. In such
cases, what is the government to do? It has commonly put coercion upon
them in the interest of the many. It is not easy to see any
alternative. If this leads to tragedy, it may be inevitable tragedy;
indeed, as Hegel pointed out regarding Socrates, it is tragic because so
inevitable.
Secondly, is such coercion
necessarily tyranny? The theory of the general will regards government
as an instrument to the common end of the greatest good. Can the
citizens instruct their government in detail as to what this good
consists in? Not if Burke’s famous speech to the electors at Bristol is
sound, and on this point it is hardly questionable. Government is not,
or not merely, for the execution of mandates given; it is largely for
the discovery of what mandates ought to be given. Now if a citizen wants
a government, if he approves on the whole the method by which it gained
power, if he has commissioned it to ascertain and promote as best it can
the community’s good, then in a quite intelligible sense its decisions
are his decisions. He has willed that it should make them for him.
What if one of these decisions
conflicts with a preference of his own? Can it reasonably be said that
his real will is here conflicting with his actual or particular will,
and that he himself is willing that this particular will should be set
aside? Mr Laski thought this absurd.
The Nonconformist who paid his
education rate under the Act of 1902 did not do so because his real will
approved of the Act. He did so because he took the view that, on
balance, it was better to put up with one bad law than to challenge the
authority from which all laws derive.5
This assents to our view in substance while rejecting it in words. The
Nonconformist preferred, we are told, to keep the government in
existence, even though it thwarted some of his desires, because he
thought that better on balance. We accept this account and are
proposing to call this preference his real will. Mr Laski thinks that
so naming it is confusing. I do not see where the confusion lies. It
is admitted on both sides that the Nonconformist wants the law not to
be. It is admitted on both sides that he wants still more that the
instrument which made the law should remain in being, in spite of its
cost to himself. Where is the confusion in saying that what he
admittedly wants most is his real will? We are not denying any facts or
taking illicit advantage of him in saying this. We are not denying that
he dislikes the law. We are proposing that theory should stay true to
fact in noting that his desires are not of equal strength or importance.
If he wills the machinery of government at the well-known cost of
occasional thwartings of his and others’ wishes, there is, or need be,
no confusion in saying that it is his real will that these thwartings
should be imposed.
Even the ridicule about punishment
does not stand up very well under scrutiny. It rests again upon putting
all facts on the same level. When a motor policeman holds me up for
careless driving, it is superficially absurd to say that I want to be
held up and fined. But is this more than superficial? What citizen who
takes his citizenship seriously has not in his heart, however colourful
his actual language, given the policeman full marks for doing just what
he did? Nobody wants to be held up when in a hurry; nobody wants to get
a “ticket”; but men have been known to go away thankful that an agency
of theirs is so impartially on the alert in serving the interest of the
community. In such cases, would the critics say that it is absurd and
contrary to fact to be thankful that one’s will has been frustrated?
But the “absurd” fact does occur.
Thirdly, while regarding government
as the instrument of the general will is admittedly dangerous, it is
less dangerous than its alternatives. Any conception of government will
give grounds for injustice if used insincerely; but sincerity assumed,
it is hard to conceive a criterion of governmental behaviour less likely
to lead to oppression than reference to what the citizens genuinely
want. It rules out ab initio all abuses based on power, and all
government in the interest of a single man or class. The will which is
to be expressed and to which government is responsible is conceived as
working in every citizen and hence entitling him to be considered; and
the content of that will can be ascertained only by remaining close to
its source.
Fourthly, we repeat that if in the
attempts to determine and achieve the common end a government blunders
into cruelty, it is absurd to lay this cruelty at the door of the theory
itself. As well interdict the aim to be rational, with the schools that
subserve this aim, because if we pursue it we stumble at times into
fallacy, as decry the pursuit through government of a common good
because men at times misconstrue its demands. No other theory of
government would bow to such criticism, and neither need this. Suffice
it to say that in any state whose members take this high pursuit
seriously there will be a constant pressure toward legal and social
amendment. Men who believe in a common end and a common reason will
naturally seek to make them prevail; and that such prevalence would
transform society needs no arguing.
Notes
1 For a discussion of the rights and
wrongs of this issue, see the papers by T. M. Knox, E. F. Carritt, and
others in Philosophy, Vol. XV (1940), pp. 51-63, 190-6, 219-20,
313-7.
2 Metaphysical Theory of the State,
87, 112.
3 Aristotelian Society Proc.,
1928, 56. C. E. M. Joad took a similar line in his Guide to the
Philosophy of Morals and Politics, 598.
4 The State in Theory and Practice,
59—60.
5 The State in Theory and Practice,
59.
Back
to Blanshard page