Brand
Blanshard
American
philosophers seem to be even more fond than their British colleagues of
expressing themselves in co-operative volumes. The new realists, the
critical realists, the idealists, the pragmatists, and the materialists
have all done it with varying degrees of success. In this volume it is
attempted still again, this time by fourteen members of the Association
for Realistic Philosophy.
What is meant by
“Realistic Philosophy”? The shortest answer is that it is philosophy in
the tradition of Aristotle and Aquinas. In metaphysics it holds that
the fundamental idea is that of being, which can be discussed without
reference to special kinds of being; that material and immaterial being
both exist, and hence that materialism and idealism are alike false;
that the task of metaphysics is to clear up such ancient but still
pressing problems as those of essence and existence, substance and
accident, cause and effect. In epistemology, the view is that things
can be known as they are in themselves. This does not imply that what
we are directly aware of is the thing, as it was for Berkeley and the
new realists, nor that it is a copy of the thing, as it is for most
representationists. Knowledge is described as “an intentional relation
terminating in the externally existent thing.” In logic, the current
mathematical discipline is held to derive from a “howler,” namely that
the relations dealt with in logic are the relations of real things, the
most general forms to be found in the actual world. Wittgenstein, for
example, thought that the structure of true propositions was a “picture”
of what held among real objects. In contrast with this, the realists
hold that genuinely logical relations such as subject and predicate, and
the sort of identity that holds between concepts, have no part in the
existent world at all, but are purely “intentional relations” produced
by the thinking mind. In ethics, the leading ideas are that each of us
is given by nature certain tendencies or capacities, that the good life
lies in fulfilling these capacities, and that conflicts between goods
must be settled by reference to a communal good or greatest total
fulfilment. To anyone who could see what this was, rights and duties
would be governed by self-evident natural laws.
This is the
position. What is perhaps more interesting about it is its frank,
vigorous, and rather belligerent return to metaphysics. The fashionable
empiricism and linguisticism of the time are brushed aside. Not that
the writers are ignorant of these movements; more than one of them
challenge empiricism on its own ground. In Professor Wild’s admirable
essay on “Phenomenology and Metaphysics,” he raises the question whether
the neo-Humian analysis of everything into qualities in relation is
empirically sound, and concludes that it clearly is not. If one is to
be empirical, in any respectable sense, one must take the pains to look
at what is there. And when Mr. Wild opens his eyes on a landscape, for
example, he finds two things very conspicuously there which Hume and his
followers failed, or refused, to see—two factors or elements which are
present in all experience and are essential to it, but which have been
overlooked because of preconceptions. These two are existence and
awareness.
When one sees an
apple, one sees an existent apple. Between an apple of imagination and
one that exists, there is all the difference in the world. It is idle
to say, as Hume did, that the difference is only one of degree, that is,
of comparative vividness; Kant cut off that line of thought by showing
that existence was no sort of quality. The imaginary apple may have all
the qualities of the existent one, and the latter will still be a world
apart from it, simply by the fact of existing. No difference is more
important than this; none is more obvious; and yet the empiricist cannot
see it, because of his traditional blinkers. If you ask him to
distinguish the existence of a quality from its “what” or character, he
at once starts looking for some other “what,” which is just what
existence is not. Of course, whatever exists does have some character,
but that is not to say that existence itself is a character. It is what
Wild calls a “philosophical protocol,” a datum that is ultimate,
unanalyzable, and certain, but at the same time non-qualitative.
He takes the same
view of awareness. The Humians examined consciousness and reported
nothing there but impressions and their copies. They were so preoccupied
with the objects of awareness that they managed to overlook the gigantic
fact of awareness itself. This awareness is no more a character than
existence is; it is another philosophical protocol. It tends to be
overlooked precisely because, like existence, it is a datum we have
always with us; whenever we are aware of anything we are also aware of
our awareness of it; for human beings at least, to be conscious is to be
self-conscious. But we are not aware of the object and of our awareness
of it in the same way. Though they are equally certain data, they
differ absolutely; the one may be an apple that we can sense; the other
is an “intentional” mental act which is neither a quality nor a
quantity, neither a thing nor a sense-datum, and yet is apprehended as
certainly as anything is. To see in the perception of an apple only a
set of qualities is like looking at a suspension bridge and seeing
nothing but the footway; the conspicuous structures that flank it at
either end—existence at the farther end and awareness at the nearer—are
simply disregarded.
The implication of
this view are developed with subtlety in several of the essays, and it
may not be invidious to give special praise to those of Manley Thompson
of Chicago on “The Distinction between Thing and Property,” and Francis
Parker of Haverford on “Realistic Epistemology”; both are admirably firm
and precise in their analysis. Indeed when the foreign reader considers
that these fourteen philosophers represent only one small corner of the
American field, he is likely to be impressed by the volume and vigour of
speculative thought in America. Much of it, as this book suggests, is taking a very different line
from that dominant in
Britain.
The second half of
the book, dealing with realistic value theory, is not quite so closely
reasoned nor so consistent, part with part, as the first half. British
readers may find special interest, however, in the spirited defence of
Plato by Robert Jordan against the criticisms of Professor Popper, and
in the essay on “Natural Law and the Problem of Asia” by Charles Malik,
the American-educated minister from Lebanon, who is the Chairman of the
U.N. Commission on Human Rights.
There are three
schools of present-day thought, apart from the school producing this
book, that will find much in it to applaud. They are the
existentialists, who will approve the stress on existence as irreducible
to essence; the Roman Catholic philosophers, who will be pleased that a
group of non-Catholics have found so much to appropriate in the Thomist
tradition; and the phenomenologists, who will find that the influence of
Husserl is very strong. Other readers will have more difficulty with the
argument. I must confess that, competent and effectively stated as it
is, I do not find it quite convincing at the crucial point. That point
is whether in that which individuates, in Aristotelian matter, in
existence, in substance, in the “that” as opposed to the “what,” there
is an element which, though real, is absolutely characterless. These
writers think there is. They believe that you cannot in principle
discover what makes anything an individual by specifying its relations
in time and space, or even its relations to everything else in the
universe; existence falls wholly outside the realm of essence. Of
course the critical realists, like Santayana, hold this too. But they
add that what we perceive is always essence and never existence, while
these realists insist that we perceive existence as truly and obviously
as we do the natures of things. It may be so. This is no place to
argue the matter out. I can only remark first, that the consequences of
distinguishing an essence from an individual by comparative concreteness
of content do not seem to me so disastrous as they are here made out to
be; and, secondly, that if existence is so obviously different from
essence—though not different in kind, since it has no kind—it is curious
that schools as far apart as the Humians, the new realists, and the
Hegelians should all have made the same gigantic blunder and failed
altogether to see it. This point, I grant, is a weak one, for what
philosophers can fail to see is portentous. And readers will at least
find here the best argument I know to show that on this matter there has
been nothing less than an epidemic of blindness in recent philosophy.
Posted April 13, 2008
Back
to Blanshard page