The Problem of
Consciousness:
A Debate with B. F.
Skinner
Brand
Blanshard
Opening Remarks by
Professor Blanshard
Behaviorism is the
view that mind can be adequately studied through the behavior of the
body. Sometimes it is offered as a method only, implying nothing as to
whether a distinct realm of consciousness exists. But it clearly cannot
stop there. If there are in fact conscious events distinct from bodily
events, a method that disregards them and confines itself to the body
cannot be adequate to the study of mind. If behaviorism is to be
adequate as a method, it must also be sound as a philosophy; it will
give us an adequate science of mind only if mental behavior is bodily
behavior. And this bold conclusion is one that both Watson and
Professor Skinner have had the courage to draw.
What is the
difference between the older and the newer behaviorism? It is not a
difference in philosophy; it is a difference in policy over what it is
in behavior that may be most profitably studied. Watson held that the
events to be studied under such heads as sensation, perception, and
imagination were events within the body, and particularly in the nervous
system; he held what Lovejoy called a hypodermic theory of
consciousness. Professor Skinner’s approach is different. Without
denying that events in the nervous system do largely determine behavior,
he is not much interested in them, for he holds that they are all
themselves conditioned by stimuli from the outside. The best course for
the psychologist, therefore, is to bypass these minute and often
conjectural nervous changes and to correlate observable stimuli directly
with observable bodily responses. This is the new program for
psychology, which is offered with the promise that if it could be
carried through, it would explain every kind of human behavior.
The layman will at
once have a question. Is he to understand that conscious motives,
feelings and ideas have no part in determining conduct or therefore in
explaining it? To this question Professor Skinner’s answer is
essentially the same as Watson’s: ideas, motives, feelings in the
traditional sense are not, even in principle, observable events, and
science can take no account of them. Does this mean that they may be
real events, though beyond scientific range? No. There are no events
that, if factual at all, are beyond the interest of science. Are we
then to dismiss distinctively conscious events altogether? Watson said
Yes, on the ground that he could find no such events in his testtubes.
Professor Skinner would put it less crudely, but I think his conclusion
is in substance the same. He says that to resort to “nonphysical
events” is to offer a “fictional explanation” (Skinner, 1953, references
at end); the belief in a mind or consciousness irreducible to any form
of bodily change seems to him an anachronism, a last lingering survival
of primitive animism (Skinner, 1953).
I believe this view
to be radically mistaken. I shall urge three points against it: (1)
that there is such a thing as consciousness, irreducible to physical
change; (2) that its denial, instead of according with modern science,
is in conflict with it; and (3) that to reject the efficacy of
consciousness makes nonsense of practical life (Blanshard, 1939).
First, then, there is
such a thing as consciousness, distinct from bodily change. For a
philosopher to be called upon to prove this is a strange sort of
challenge. Modem philosophy began with what I think is the valid
insight that consciousness is the most certain thing in the world.
Descartes showed that you can doubt with some plausibility the existence
of rocks and rivers; you can doubt the existence, at least when
unobserved, of your own hands and feet. But you cannot coherently doubt
that you are conscious, for to doubt it is to be conscious; you
establish the fact of consciousness in the very act of doubting it. The
behaviorist may reply that by “doubting” Descartes must have meant some
physical response, and in taking it for a form of consciousness he was
merely deluded. But this will not do either, for a delusion is clearly
a fact of consciousness; matter in motion cannot be deluded.
But the behaviorist
has persuaded himself that matter in motion is all there is. And if you
talk about sensing or perceiving or thinking, he is commonly prepared to
tell you what movements of matter you ought to mean by these words. For
Watson, a toothache was a change in a dental nerve. What is a toothache
for Professor Skinner? He says that when a person reports “my tooth
aches,” he is making a verbal response to an event within his body.
What sort of event? Though Professor Skinner adheres to his policy of
saying little about such events, this much seems to be clear: the event
is a physical event, a movement of matter, since it can be investigated
by science, and this is the only kind of event that science recognizes.
On the point of greatest interest, Professor Skinner’s behaviorism is
thus at one with Watson’s.
And its major
difficulties are the same. The most obvious one is that the experience
of pain, for example, is self-evidently not the same thing as a physical
movement of any kind. That their identification is a confusion can be
shown in various ways. First their properties are different. If a pain
were any kind of physical motion, we could ask what its direction and
velocity were, whereas it makes no sense to talk of the direction or
velocity of a toothache. On the other hand, we speak of the pain as
dull or excruciating, while a dull or excruciating motion is meaningless
again.
Secondly, no
behaviorist behaves as if his theory were true. For example, he has
occasionally, like the rest of us, had to visit his dentist. The
dentist says, “Mr. B., this may be pretty painful; shall I use a little
cocaine?” “Yes, by all means,” says Mr. B. He clearly wants to avert
something; what? On his theory, it is a particular physical event,
about whose nature he is not very clear. But why should he select this
event for his aversion? There is nothing in it as a physical change to
make it more objectionable than a million others. What makes it
objectionable is plainly just one thing: it happens to carry with it, no
one knows why, an excruciating pain, which is as different from the
physical change that conditions it as are any two things in the world.
If the behaviorist admits that it is this he is trying to avert, he has
broken out of his behaviorism; if he denies it, his own conduct refutes
him.
Thirdly, he
continually deserts his program in his experimental practice. He agrees
that, as a psychologist, he is concerned with such events as feeling
rage or sorrow, as seeing colors and hearing sounds. What he insists on
is that these names be now given not to conscious experiences, which
cannot be scientifically studied, but to physical responses that can.
But what responses are these old names now to mean? It would be
ridiculous to give the name “rage” to the limp and drooping behavior of
sorrow; one must give it to the kind of behavior that we know as the
normal expression of rage. But what that implies is that even in
assigning the new terms, we must fall back on the old meanings. “Rage”
is now to mean the kind of behavior that we can link uniquely to the
emotion of rage. We must resort to the conscious state as our only
reliable index to the behavior that is supposed to supplant it. Perhaps
the oddest achievement of this kind is the Watsonian physiological
psychology. Watson would identify seeing blue with the response of the
optic nerve to a definite kind of stimulation, namely that of light
waves about seven microns long, and seeing red with the response to
waves about four microns long. But how did he know which of these
minutely different responses to call “seeing blue” and which “seeing
red”? It was by starting with the conscious sensation and then looking
for its nervous correlate—which meant, of course, that at every step of
his experimental inquiry he assumed the very difference between
sensation and nervous event which it was his main purpose to deny.
Behaviorists, old and
new, have been forced into inconsistency in another way. They are
concerned to explain why some responses are acquired and others stamped
out. A child, if it tastes sugar, will take it readily in the future,
and if given quinine will in the future avoid it. Why? Common sense
and traditional psychology answer, Because it finds one pleasant and the
other disagreeable. The behaviorist must profess not to know the
meaning of such words. “‘Pleasant’ or ‘satisfying’,” writes Professor
Skinner, “apparently do not refer to physical properties of reinforcing
events, since the physical sciences use neither these terms nor any
equivalents” (Skinner, 1953). The business of science is simply to
report that the sugar response is “reinforced” and the quinine response
“extinguished.” But why should sugar reinforce a response and quinine
inhibit it? There is nothing in the physical properties of either,
taken alone, that throws the least light on this. Hence even
behaviorists as skilful as Professor Skinner in excluding reference to
conscious experience find themselves willy-nilly using terms that mean
such experience—or else mean nothing at all. Professor Skinner writes,
for example, “though we have been reinforced with an excellent meal in a
new restaurant, a bad meal may reduce our patronage to zero”; and on the
next page, that in extinguishing a response, “the currently preferred
technique is punishment” (Skinner, 1953). Now do such terms as
“excellent,” “bad,” and “punishment” refer to pleasure and pain or not?
If not, they are wholly irrelevant in explaining why one response is
maintained and another dropped. If they do help in explaining this, as
Professor Skinner here implies that they do, it is because they are
drawing their force from an interpretation that behaviorism denies them.
Why should
behaviorists reject this interpretation? They answer, as we have seen,
that it is because it is vetoed by science, and they want above all
things to be scientific. “The methods of science,” writes Professor
Skinner, “have been enormously successful wherever they have been
tried. Let us then apply them to human affairs.” What Professor
Skinner seems here to be saying is that he is moved by the desire to
explain things scientifically, though he cannot mean by this what most
people mean. The behaviorists of the sixties, like the positivists of
the thirties, dismiss as meaningless all references that go beyond
physical things and events, entities that at least in principle can be
publicly observed. If there was anything purely psychical about us,
like old-fashioned desires and sensations, no one else could ever hope
to observe them, or therefore meaningfully speak of them.
This curious
“physicalism” of the early positivists has now been abandoned by the
positivists themselves; Ayer, Feigl, Hempel and Carnap have all
renounced it. Behaviorists apparently still cling to it. They still
think it demanded by science, though in fact it is deeply at odds with
science. That is my second thesis. It will be enough to support it
with a single instance.
Consider the
behaviorist treatment of images. Watson took the heroic course of
denying that there were such things, thereby, as someone remarked,
exalting a personal defect into an ontological principle. I shall not
pause to argue whether images exist; I shall assume that they do. No
one among us who is a fair visualizer will have any trouble in summoning
up, for example, the face of Einstein, with its cloud of white hair, its
moustache and wrinkles, and its sad, dark eyes. What is the behaviorist
to do with such images? He cannot say that when we talk of them, we
mean only certain motions among the particles in the brain, for we know
too well that we do not. Nor can he say, with common sense and
traditional psychology, that they exist in the realm of consciousness,
for now there is no such realm. Professor Skinner struggles manfully
with the problem, admitting that “perhaps the most difficult problem in
the analysis of behavior is raised by responses beginning ‘I see. ..’,
‘I hear. . .’, and so on, when customary stimuli are lacking” (Skinner,
1953). He recognizes that such reports may be true; he has read the
famous chapter of Galton in which a portrait painter is described whose
imagery was so vivid that he could paint from it after his sitter was
gone. Professor Skinner’s explanation of such performances is that
seeing is a response which may be conditioned to occur in the absence of
its normal stimulus, like the salivating of Pavlov’s dog. This is no
doubt true, but it leaves the critical question untouched. What is the
status of the imaginary or hallucinatory object that the subject
admittedly “sees”? It is in the physical world for on the behaviorist
account, there is nowhere else for it to be. But it is not in the
subject’s head, for no surgeon, nor the subject himself with the help of
mirrors, will ever find it there. And of course it is not in
consciousness; Professor Skinner avoids using the word “imagine” and
insists on using “see”, even in cases of hallucination. Now if the
object thus admittedly seen is not in consciousness and not in the head,
where is it? One can only conclude that it is out there in nature. But
if this conclusion is offered as consistent with modem physics, it is
not hard to predict the comment of the physicist. It would certainly be
eloquent, but it might not be quotable.
Images have always
offered special difficulty for the behaviorists, and I do not want to
exploit that difficulty unduly. So perhaps I should add that precisely
the same difficulty is occasioned by ordinary perception. Professor
Skinner uses the example of seeing a rainbow in the sky. What is it that
we are here responding to? He does not, as Watson did, develop the fact
of light waves impinging on nerve ends. He holds, and rightly, that
these are not what we see; what we are seeing is the reds, greens and
yellows of the bow in the sky. But then these reds, greens and yellows
are not really there at all. Would any responsible physicist admit for
a moment that they are? He would admit, of course, that the vibrations
are there, but that is a quite different matter. The whole modem
tradition of physics from Newton down has relegated the reds, greens,
and yellows to sensations, sense-data in our minds, caused indeed by
outer vibrations, but utterly different from them. Bertrand Russell did
attempt fifty years ago to work out a philosophy of science that would
place even colors, tastes, and smells out there in nature, but in his
last important book in philosophy (Russell, 1948), he comes full
circle. He holds that everything we directly perceive exists in
consciousness, and that the entire world of physical science is a
speculative construction built on that foundation. And about the
secondary qualities such as colors, sounds and smells, physics would
surely agree with him. Regarding these qualities, Professor Skinner
seems to me caught in a dilemma. If he puts them in physical nature, he
is at odds with science. If he puts them in consciousness, he abandons
behaviorism. And I doubt if he can find an ontological purgatory
between these two.
My third thesis is
that behaviorism leaves a vacuum at the heart of our moral and practical
life. It makes us out to be hollow men in a wasteland. It tells us
that we are machines—enormously complicated machines, but in the end
nothing more. Let us assume for the moment that this is true, and ask
what would be the value of a world in which only such machines existed
and that unscientific embarrassment, consciousness, did not exist. The
answer I suggest is simple: it would have no value at all.
Consciousness, however frail and evanescent, is the seat of all goods
and evils, of all values of all kinds, and they would go out with it
like a candle.
Run down the list of
things which, in the opinion of major thinkers, make life worth living.
What are they? They are such things as pleasure or happiness, wisdom or
understanding, friendship, the sense of beauty, the sense of duty. All
of them, you will note, are forms of consciousness. The wisdom prized
by Spinoza was not that of a computer, even the giant one pictured by
the New Yorker which, to the dismay of its mechanics, is issuing
from its depths a slip reading “Cogito ergo sum.” What Spinoza meant
was conscious insight, the experience of understanding. The
pleasure stressed by Bentham and Mill, the friendship prized by
Epicurus, the beauty prized by Schopenhauer, were the experience
of these things; and when Kant put good will at the top of them, he
meant the conscious recognition and choice of duty. These men
would all have been bewildered by the suggestion that the goods they
spoke of lay in the play of nerves or limbs; they would have said that
if by some miracle an unconscious robot were to duplicate the story of
St. Francis or Casanova, there would be no good or evil about it. With
that judgment I agree. In an account of human conduct that confines
itself to physical change, everything of intrinsic value has been left
out.
Nor is that all. The
behaviorist is committed to ignoring not only the goods that give life
value, but also the motives that make men seek them.*
[* The criticism has been developed
in three recent books, Joseph Wood Krutch’s The Measure of Man,
Floyd W. Matson’s The Broken Image, and Jacques Barzun’s
Science the Glorious Entertainment. ] For him the only causes of
human behavior lie in its physical conditions. Professor Skinner points
out and deplores that it is a “common practice to explain behavior in
terms of an inner agent which lacks physical dimensions and is called
‘mental’ or ‘psychic’’’; he gives as an instance of this mistake the
remark about a lecturer that “what he says is often disorganized because
his ideas are confused” (Skinner, 1953). There can be “no violation,”
he says “of the fundamental principle of science which rules out ‘final
causes’” (Skinner, 1953). Conscious purposes and intentions, even if
they existed, could not affect bodily behavior; “since mental or psychic
events are asserted to lack the dimensions of physical science, we have
an additional reason for rejecting them” (Skinner, 1953).
Put abstractly in
this way, the doctrine seems not implausible. But consider what it
means in the concrete. Here are a few of the things that strictly and
literally follow: Your conscious interest or desire to hear a
discussion of behaviorism today had no part in making you come here.
St. Francis’s love for his fellows, if that means a feeling as distinct
from physical conditions, had no influence on how he treated them.
Hitler’s hatred of the Jews contributed nothing toward his orders to
have them exterminated. No gourmet has ever chosen one item on a menu
rather than another because of his desire for a pleasanter food.
Newton’s
theoretical interest had no part in keeping him at his desk, nor did his
ideas of gravitation ever affect in the slightest what he said or put
down on paper. No one has ever done anything because he saw it to be
his duty, or even because he mistakenly thought it to be his duty. The
novelists, dramatists, and historians of the world have been governed by
a unanimous illusion. They have represented Othello as moved to action
by feelings of jealousy, and Romeo by his love of Juliet, and Silas
Marner by his love of money, and Napoleon by his love of power, and
Churchill by his love of England. A psychologist with full understanding would have freed himself from
such delusions. He would see that all these “mental states” are equally
irrelevant in explaining how people behave.
Of course this
disparity between the judgment of the world and that of the behaviorist
does not prove the behaviorist wrong. But it does show who must assume
the burden of proof. And if one asks which is the more probable: that
every major moralist, historian, and man of letters has been talking
nonsense about human life, or that a set of brilliant young
psychologists should have been carried away by excess of zeal, one
cannot hesitate long.
References
1. Skinner, B. F.,
Science and Human Behavior (MacMillan, 1953), pp. 278, 29, 81, 70,
71, 265-6, 30 31.
2. Russell, Bertrand,
Human Knowledge, Its Scope, and Limits (London:
Allen and Unwin), 1948.
3. Blanshard, Brand,
The Nature of Thought (London: Allen and Unwin; N.Y.: Humanities
Press, 1939); Chapter IX is an examination of the older behaviorism.
Reply by Professor Skinner
Professor Blanshard
correctly paraphrases the behavioristic principle that ideas, motives,
and feelings have no part in determining conduct and therefore no part
in explaining it, but he is wrong in saying that it is because these
things are not observable. No major behaviorist has ever argued that
science must limit itself to public events. The physicalism of the
logical positivist has never been good behaviorism, as I pointed out
twenty years ago (Skinner, 1945).1
In an adequate science of behavior nothing that determines conduct can
be overlooked no matter how difficult of access it may be. To make
inferences about private events is not to abandon or destroy an
“objective” position. As a behaviorist, however, I question the nature
of such events and their role in the prediction and control of behavior.
I do not expect to
find answers in any “hypodermic” theory of consciousness. It is the
introspective psychologist who would escape from dualism through
physiology. The organism is not empty, and it is important to study
what goes on inside it, but most physiologists are looking for the wrong
things. No matter how much they may improve their techniques, they will
never find sensations, thoughts, or acts of will. On that point
Professor Blanshard and I agree, but I do not agree that mental events
are thereby shown to be irreducible to physical change.
Behaviorism
begins with the assumption that the world is made of only one kind of
stuff—dealt with most successfully by physics but well enough for most
purposes by common sense. Organisms are part of that world, and their
processes are therefore physical processes. In studying behavior,
especially the behavior of men, we exhibit further instances of the
thing we are studying. In thus behaving about behaving we may raise
some tricky problems, but they have their counterparts in “thinking
about thinking.” A special problem arises from the inescapable fact
that a small part of the universe is enclosed within the skin of each of
us. It is not different in kind from the rest of the universe, but
because our contact with it is intimate and in some ways exclusive, it
receives special consideration. It is said to be known in a special
way, to contain the immediately given, to be the first thing a man knows
and according to some the only thing he can really know. Philosophers,
following Descartes, begin with it in their analysis of mind. Almost
everyone seems to begin with it in explaining his own behavior. There
is, however, another possible starting point—the behavior of what Max
Meyer used to call the
Other-One. As a
scientific analysis grows more effective, we no longer explain that
behavior in terms of inner events. The world within the skin of the
Other-One loses its preferred status. But what about the so-called
introspective evidence?
Let us consider a few
examples. The so-called conative aspects of consciousness have
to do with the initiation and direction of action. A man is said to
act when he wills to do so and to act in a given way to fulfill a
purpose. A competing, external explanation is suggested by the concept
of the stimulus. In determining which response will occur and when, a
stimulus usurps some conative functions. But a great deal of behavior
is not simply elicited by stimuli. It is true that stimulus-response
theorists still try to leave the initiation and selection of behavior to
a “total stimulating situation,” but we often know that such a situation
has acted as a stimulus only after the fact. In the concept of operant
behavior, not to be confused with stimulus-response theories, the
stimulus is merely the occasion for action. The initiation and
selection of a response are matters concerning its probability, and
probability of response is determined by other variables—in particular,
by the contingencies of reinforcement. I have suggested that operant
reinforcement is simply a more effective formulation of purpose
(Skinner, 1963).2 To the
extent that an analysis of contingencies of reinforcement permits us to
predict and control when and how a man will act, we have nothing to gain
by speaking of a purposive act of will.
So-called
cognitive functions of consciousness are also displaced by an
adequate analysis of the Other-One. A hungry pigeon will repeatedly
peck a colored disk if reinforced with food when it does so, but it adds
nothing to say that it pecks because it knows that it will get food.
Similarly, if it has been reinforced for pecking a red disk, it will
also peck a yellow one, though not so rapidly, but it adds nothing to
say that it has seen some similarity in the two disks and has mentally
generalized from one to the other. Observable contingencies of
reinforcement also account for discrimination, abstraction, and concept
formation, as well as for other kinds of changes in behavior said to
show cognitive processes. To the extent that they do so adequately, no
explanatory role survives to be played by mental processes as such.
But the question is,
do we not see conative and cognitive activities? Before
answering it, we should ask what it means to see anything. Here the
mentalist has almost succeeded in sealing off a behavioristic analysis.
It has long been supposed that sensing or perceiving is something man
does to the environment; we are only beginning to discover what the
environment does to man. The modern concept of stimulus control
reverses the very direction of action and, for that and other reasons,
is not readily seen to be equivalent to “direct experience.” A
convenient account of stimulus control has been written by Herbert
Terrace (1965).3 Instead
of asking our subject to describe “what he sees,” using his everyday
vocabulary supplemented by a few technical terms, we can bring his
behavior under the control of explicit stimuli. The subject can be an
animal as well as a man. A nonverbal psychophysics, with either animals
or men, is proving to be much more feasible than early critics of
behaviorism foresaw. The mentalist will say that we are still getting
our subject to tell us what he sees—even when he is an animal. But
nothing comparable to experience enters into the formulation, although
the same contingencies of reinforcement account for the same behavior,
including behavior said to report the content of consciousness.
If the mentalist
insists that we have still left out “seeing” itself, we must ask him
what he means. What has been left out? What is seeing? What does a
perceiver do—either to, or about, or in response to the world he
perceives? “To experience” often seems to mean simply “to be in contact
with.” We know the world in the social sense of having been introduced
to it. Knowledge is a form of “acquaintance” (the word comes from the
same root as cognition). But the action is often more positive. The
perceiver ‘apprehends the world almost as one apprehends a criminal. He
makes it his own almost as if he were ingesting it, as one ingests the
body of a god in the rites of Mithra. He knows the world almost in the
biblical sense of possessing it sexually.
Contact and
possession are important elements in the concept of experience because
they are related to the physical privacy of the world within one’s
skin. They have led to the view that the world beyond one’s skin can be
known only from copies. When the copies are discovered to be bad, it is
concluded that the world can never be known as it really is. Richard
Held has described the search for copies of reality and for an
explanation of their shortcomings in his paper Object and Effigy
(1965).4 Physiologists
and neurologists have tried to support the notion of inner copies by
tracing the stimulus into the nervous system, where it can be more
intimately possessed, but their facts seem to show that the organism
begins at once to analyze stimuli and to respond to them in ways which
cannot be regarded as the construction of effigies. The behaviorist has
no interest in experience as contact or possession, and he quite
sensibly leaves the environment where it is. And even if private copies
of it existed in the external world, they would not answer the question
we are asking. Put the thing you see wherever you like—at the surface
of the organism, in the heart of the nervous system, or in the mind—what
does it mean to say that you see it?
The behaviorist must
give his own answer, and like everyone else he finds it difficult. The
study of operant behavior suggests that we look to the contingencies of
reinforcement. How are responses brought under stimulus control? What
responses are involved? A pigeon may learn to discriminate between
colors in pecking at disks for food, but surely there is nothing about
seeing color which involves pecking disks. Usually, however, an
enormous number of responses come under the same kind of stimulus
control, and it is possible that seeing color is something common to
them. Precurrent responses of observing or attending to stimuli may be
important. In verbal behavior certain generalized contingencies
maximize control by stimuli and minimize control by other variables,
producing the kind of response I have called a tact—and may be
especially relevant. Naming a color is no closer to seeing a color than
pecking a colored key, but the psychophysicist usually accepts it as an
equivalent activity. A similar analysis of contingencies may eventually
explain why a subject responds to one feature of a stimulus rather than
to another or sees one thing as if it were something else.
All these issues,
together with their uncertainties, arise when we are said to see our
acts of will, our thoughts, our sensations, our images. Things of this
sort should be seen with special clarity. They are inside our bodies;
we are in contact with them; we possess them; there is no need for
copies. But the fact is, they are not seen clearly at all. Two people
rarely agree about them, and for good reason. A private event may be
close to the perceiver, but it is remote from the environment which
teaches him to perceive. We learn to tell the difference between colors
when people reinforce our behavior appropriately while manipulating
colored objects. We cannot learn the difference between a resolution
and a wish, or between guessing and believing, in the same way. Certain
techniques permit the verbal environment to circumvent the fact of
privacy, but only to a limited extent (Skinner, 1945; 1957).5
In particular, we describe our past and present behavior, even when it
is not visible to others, and we appear to describe our future behavior
when we announce an intention. We often do so simply because we are in
a favorable position to observe the variables of which our behavior is a
function, and many of these are public, but whether public or private,
all the events described are physical.
Professor Blanshard
must deny this. “The experience of pain. . . ,” he says, “is
self-evidently not the same thing as a physical movement of any kind.”
His example is as nearly self-evident as possible, but I am afraid it
does not quite make the grade. Painful stimuli, being inside the body,
are both particularly strong and hard to observe in other ways, and they
do not need to be copied. The experience of an external object would
serve Professor Blanshard less well as an example. The expression
“physical movement,” taken from a contemporary analysis of matter, also
contributes to the plausibility, for a motion is not likely to be dull
or excruciating. But things are. Indeed, these two adjectives are
applied to pain just because they apply to the things which cause pain.
A dull pain is the kind of pain caused by a dull object, as a sharp pain
is caused by a sharp object. The term “excruciating” is taken from the
practice of crucifixion.
Ideas, motives, and
feelings are more important to Professor Blanshard’s argument than pain,
and they are by no means so self-evidently perceived. The processes or
states which such terms describe acquire control very slowly. Only a
long and complicated history of reinforcement leads one to speak of
sensations, images, and thoughts. Such a history is characteristic only
of certain cultures. Our own culture shows wide variations—it produces
the thoroughgoing extravert on the one hand and the introspective
psychologist and philosopher on the other. Some sort of history of
reinforcement is essential. Descartes could not begin, as he thought he
could, by saying “Cogito ergo sum.” He had to begin as a baby—a baby
whose subsequent verbal environment eventually generated in him (though
not, I am sure, in millions of his contemporaries) certain subtle
responses, one of which was “cogito.” It is a loose term, not because
the events it is said to describe are necessarily vague, but because
they are almost inaccessible to the verbal community which builds all
descriptive verbal repertoires.
Professor Blanshard
seizes upon my admission that the problem of images is difficult. It is
difficult for the mentalist too. What do you see when what you see is
not really there—as in a memory, a fantasy, or a dream? But first, what
do you see when what you see is there? Someone shows you a
picture of a group of scientists, among them Einstein. He asks, “Is
Einstein there?” and you say, “Yes,” as you have been taught to do in
thousands of comparable cases. But suppose he asks, “Do you see
Einstein?” and you say, “Yes.” What have you reported? Did you, in
response to his question, simply look at Einstein a second time? If so,
how do you distinguish between “seeing Einstein” and “seeing that you
are seeing Einstein”?
A possibility which
needs to be considered is that in reporting that you see Einstein, you
are reporting a response rather than a stimulus. No
matter how obscure its dimensions, the behavior called seeing must be
involved, and you must be reporting it, rather than the presence
of the thing seen, when you report that you see something. You may
be reporting the same thing when you report that you see something which
“isn’t really there”—when you are merely “imagining how Einstein
looked.” Seeing something in memory is not necessarily seeing a
copy. The whole concept of “stored data structures” —supported without
warrant by the analogy of the computer—may be quite wrong. What is
stored may be responses—in this case the responses involved in seeing.
When I recall how something looked, I may simply be recalling how I
once looked at something. There was no copy inside me when I first
looked at it, and there is none now. I am simply doing again what I
once did when I looked at something, and I can tell you that I am doing
so.
In another criticism
of behaviorism, Professor Blanshard6
has written, “The bats’ heads taken by the toper to be emerging from the
wallpaper are clearly not physical objects—what in the world would
physics do with them? They are not processes in the nervous system;
they are not muscular responses; and it is absurd to turn one’s back on
them and insist that they are nothing at all.” But why is it absurd?
We have no more reason to assume the existence of imaginary or
hallucinatory objects than of memories as sense data. The toper is
quite literally “seeing things.” His behavior would be most readily
evoked by actual bats’ heads emerging from wallpaper, but it can occur,
especially after toping, in the absence of any such stimuli.
Physiologists may someday find the precursors or mediators of that
behavior, but they will never find anything that looks like a bat, for
there is nothing of that sort inside the skin at any time—whether
external stimuli are present or not.
The same explanation
may hold for seeing something which does not closely correspond with an
external stimulus. Under certain conditions, analyzed in the study of
perception, the response of seeing a straight line may be evoked by a
curved line. We do not need to say that the straight line is in “the
world as it appears to be” and the curved line in “the world as it
really is.” There is no world as it “appears to be”; there are simply
various ways of seeing the world as it is—in this case, a way of seeing
a straight line in response to a curved line as a stimulus.
Professor Blanshard
feels that I am forced into another absurd position in having to assert
that “Hitler’s hatred of the Jews contributed nothing toward his orders
to have them exterminated” and that Newton’s ideas of gravitation never “affected in the slightest degree what he
said or put down on paper.” But again, why are these statements
absurd? If we are to speak of Hitler’s hatred, it is necessarily as an
inference from a long series of verbal and nonverbal actions. Hitler
himself undoubtedly had other information, for he must have observed
small-scale actions of the same sort not seen by anyone else, as well as
responses of his autonomic nervous system. But no one part of this
complex was the cause of any other part—unless, indeed, following
William James, we could say that the action caused the feelings. A much
more reasonable view is that the whole pattern was caused by
environmental events in Hitler’s personal history. It is too late to
discover enough of these to make a convincing case (only historians and
psychoanalysts explain individual behavior that way), but it is
important to emphasize that the real causes lay in the environment,
because if we want to do anything about genocide, it is to the
environment we must turn. We cannot make men stop killing each other by
changing their feelings. Whatever UNESCO may say to the contrary, wars
do not begin in the minds of men. The situation is much more hopeful.
To prevent war we must change the environment. In doing so we may well
reduce the so-called mental tensions which accompany, and are
erroneously said to foster; war-like acts.
And so with
Newton. We
infer his ideas from the things he said and wrote. Newton himself knew
about things he almost said and wrote, as well as things he said or
wrote, and revoked, but the ideas he did not quite express were not the
causes of the ideas he expressed (in behavioristic terms, his covert
responses were not the causes of his overt). The point is important if
we are to induce young people to have ideas. For more than two thousand
years teachers have been trying to stimulate minds, exercise rational
powers, and implant or tease out ideas, and they have very little to
show for it. A much more promising program is to construct an
educational environment, verbal and nonverbal, in which certain kinds of
verbal responses, some of them original, will be emitted. We are closer
to such an environment than most educators know.
Did Shakespeare
actually represent Othello as moved to action by feelings of jealousy?
We should quite justly complain that he had not motivated his character
if he had done so. He paints a detailed picture of jealous behavior
ending in the smothering of the innocent Desdemona. Most of that
behavior, as one should expect in a play, is verbal. Othello tells us
about his actions past, present, and future, and his emotional states.
Some of this is public and some private, but no one part is the cause of
any other part. If he had had time, he might have described the wound
he inflicts upon himself, but the felt pain was no more responsible for
his death than his feelings of jealousy were responsible for his jealous
acts. A common cause was involved in each case. We must turn to the
machinations of “honest Iago” to understand Othello’s behavior, and it
is a standard criticism of the play that Iago’s motives are not clear.
Certainly it will not do for Professor Blanshard to tell us that he was
moved to action by his “villainy.”
I am surprised
that Professor Blanshard cites the contrary judgment of the world.
Philosophers seldom enjoy the support of that judgment, and it seems
dangerous to value it too highly. When physicists began to assert that
fantastic amounts of energy could be extracted from a lump of mud, I
doubt that they were much disturbed by the fact that “every major
moralist, historian, and man of letters” would have called it nonsense.
Against the judgment of the world, the behaviorist may set the
opportunity to discover comparable sources of energy making it possible
at long last to deal effectively with human behavior. I continue to
argue the behavioristic position because I believe it has vast
implications.
Current education supplies a useful example. Powerful techniques of
teaching, derived from an experimental analysis of behavior, are being
widely opposed in the name of traditional philosophies of education
philosophies which are avowedly mentalistic and which receive
substantial support from mentalistic, particularly cognitive,
psychologists. Those who subscribe to them have no really effective new
techniques to offer, but their discussions of education are warmly
received because they frequently allude to the mysteries of mind.
Millions of school children are being sacrificed on the altar of
cognitive theory. Men have suffered long enough from that strange quirk
in their behavior which keeps them from applying the methods of natural
science to their own lives.
References
1
Skinner, B. F., “The Operational Analysis of Psychological
Terms,” Psychology Review, 1945.
2
Skinner, B. F., “Operant Behavior,” American Psychologist, 1963.
3
Terrace, Herbert, “Stimulus Control” to appear in W. K. Honig, ed.,
Behavior: Areas of Research and Application.
4
Held, Richard, “Object and Effigy” in Gyorgy Kepes, ed., Structure in
Art and in Science, Braziller, N. Y., 1965.
5
Skinner, B. F., Verbal Behavior, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1957.
6
Blanshard, Brand,
“Critical Reflections on Behaviorism,” Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society, 1965.
Concluding Remarks by
Professor Blanshard
In my opening paper,
I made three criticisms of Professor Skinner’s behaviorism. Has he
answered them?
The first point was
that a conscious event such as a toothache is not the same as a physical
event—that is, a motion of particles—because its properties are
self-evidently different. A motion has velocity, but not a pain; a pain
may be dull or excruciating, while it is meaningless to say this of a
motion. Professor Skinner replies that though a motion cannot be dull
or excruciating, a physical object can be, and “these two adjectives are
applied to pain just because they apply to the things which cause pain.
A dull pain is the kind of pain caused by a dull object, as a sharp pain
is caused by a sharp object.” On this there are three comments to be
made.
First, it seems to be
untrue. Dull toothaches or headaches are not normally caused by dull
objects, or sharp ones by sharp objects. Secondly, granting that a pain
may be caused by a physical thing, that does not show that the pain
itself is a physical thing; cause and effect are not necessarily alike.
Thirdly, even if the term “dull” is ascribable to a physical thing as
well as to a pain, it is ascribed in a wholly different sense. The
dullness or sharpness of a thing is a matter of its shape; that of a
pain is not, for a pain has no shape. This reply can be extended to
other cases. The fact that we describe mental events in terms of
metaphors drawn from the physical is no evidence that the mental is
physical and that we are not using metaphors at all.
In maintaining that
there are distinct conscious events, I pointed out, further, that
philosophers from Descartes to Russell have found their own
consciousness the most certain thing in the world. I am still not clear
how Professor Skinner would answer them. He seems to take several
lines. One is that they would not have had this certainty if their
psychology had been of the right kind and had based itself on the
behavior of the Other-One. This of course is true) for we never observe
the consciousness of other persons, but only their bodily behavior, and
hence if we were confined to this sort of psychology, all talk of
consciousness would be ruled out from the beginning. But the question
is whether this sort of psychology does not itself leave something out.
We all talk with confidence about our own desires and purposes, and the
burden of proof is clearly on anyone who would ignore them.
So Professor Skinner
offers a second line of reply; we do not need them in explaining
behavior. The purpose by which we explain a given action has, if it
exists at all, certain conditions of a physical kind. Why not, then,
bypass the purpose and connect our behavior directly with these prior
conditions? If a causes b, and b causes c,
then a causes c, and if we can link these two directly, we
shall not need to introduce anything inner or mental whatever. The
chief novelty of Professor Skinner’s behaviorism lies, I suppose, in
this attempt to bypass inner events, whether mental or physical, by
correlating their causes directly with their effects and ignoring these
events themselves. But surely you do not abolish the intermediate link
in the chain by ignoring it. Every chug of the engine in your car has
prior causes which are therefore the remoter causes of the car’s
running, but that does not mean that the engine can be eliminated. Even
if you did succeed in linking event 3 with event 1 in your explanation
without mentioning 2, that does not prove that there is no 2.
Furthermore, we have
the most impressive positive evidence that 2 does exist, the evidence of
direct awareness. I am aware that I am now thinking about behaviorism
with the purpose of criticizing it. Here we meet with Professor
Skinner’s third line of reply: he questions this awareness. He says
that we never see these inner processes. I agree, for I hold that they
are not, like physical processes, the sort of events that can be seen.
I can say this, but I am puzzled as to how Professor Skinner can say
it. On his theory these processes are as truly physical events in space
as the rolling of billiard balls, and such events can normally be seen.
It is one of the paradoxes about behaviorists that they first tell us
that pains and thoughts are just physical movements in space, and then
when we draw the conclusion that we should be able to see them like
other such movements, they draw back in dismay. Surely they should
either give up the theory that these processes are physical
movements—that is, give up behaviorism—or else go courageously forward
to the view that we may hope, with a new electronic microscope, to see
someone’s toothache or concept of liberty lurking or scurrying about in
his head. This the behaviorist feels, with the rest of us, to be
absurd. On his premises, I do not see why.
Still, consistently
or not, Professor Skinner does deny that pains and thoughts can be seen,
and, on that ground, apparently, questions whether there really are such
things. But surely seeing is not the only kind of awareness. We may be
vividly aware not only of shapes and sizes, but also of our activity of
thinking, of our being hot, of being in doubt what should be done about
Viet Nam, of the last time we saw Paris, of the funniness of a joke, or
of 2-and-2’s making 4. I should not for a moment deny that there are
difficulties in analyzing these kinds of awareness. I should only
maintain that no argument by which people have sought to analyze them
away is half so certain as their own disclosures to us. If any
behavioristic or Christian Scientist tells me that my consciousness of
an intense pain is an illusion, I can only say, No, thank you; if that
is science, I prefer to stay with common sense or (heaven help me)
philosophy.
The second thesis of
my paper was that behaviorism, for all its desire to be scientific, is
really in conflict with science. Only physical things and events exist,
says Professor Skinner. Images, hallucinations and sensations of blue,
if anything at all, must therefore be physical things or events. But no
physicist would accept this. No natural scientist would introduce the
bats’ heads seen by the toper, or our images of Einstein, or the hues we
see in the rainbow, into physical space. The behaviorist is here
ranging himself not against philosophy only, which he would do with
equanimity, but against physics also, which he respects. What is
Professor Skinner’s reply?
I have had some
difficulty in following it, but apparently it is this. The image of
Einstein is not an object seen or imagined at all, and hence the problem
of finding a place for it does not arise. At some time in the past we
have seen Einstein in person or in a picture, and when we now have an
image of him, we are repeating the response or activity of seeing. “No
matter how obscure its dimensions, the behavior called seeing must be
involved, and you may be reporting it rather than the presence of
the thing seen when you report that you see something.” That is, the
seeing occurs, but without an object. To have an image is to engage in
an activity of seeing into which the alleged object is telescoped or
dissolved. And this activity of seeing is of course bodily activity.
What is most striking
about this theory, to my mind, is its appeal from experienced fact to a
materialist metaphysics; it could hardly have been suggested by the
facts themselves. I report that I have an image of Einstein, so clear
that I can see the fluffy hair and some of the wrinkles; I am told that
in fact I am seeing nothing at all. I report that in my own experience
seeing is always a seeing of something or other, that to see and yet see
nothing is impossible. I am told that the impossible is perfectly
possible, and this must be regarded as a case of it. I report that in
my own experience there is a sharp difference between the object of a
response and the response itself; I am told that here the object has
been absorbed in the response in a way to which nothing in the facts
seems to correspond. I report that in my own experience there is a
difference between contemplating and acting, that I can envisage a face
or a scene without doing anything about it. I am told that there is no
such distinction, that contemplating is behaving. I report that
seeing Einstein in imagination, even if it is in a sense behaving, seems
at the farthest possible remove from the making of a bodily adjustment.
I am assured that my having an image is a bodily adjustment and nothing
more.
Now I believe
in philosophy, but in a philosophy that starts from facts as given, not
as moulded to suit the interest of a materialist or any other
metaphysics. The behaviorist is committed to an antecedent
philosophical theory which requires him to regard images, like
everything else, as physical. But he meets with so stout a resistance
from the physicist that he feels compelled to change his tactics and to
say that the image is not a physical thing; it is really the physical
activity of seeing. But this does not remove the difficulty; it doubles
it; for now in addition to calling an image physical, he is trying to
dissolve an object into the process of responding to it. It cannot be
done. If my image of Einstein is not a physical thing, neither is it a
physical process.
My third thesis was
that in denying consciousness, behaviorism makes us robots or hollow
men, since consciousness is the seat of all values and all motives.
Regarding values, Professor Skinner says nothing, and I remain in the
dark as to how values of any kind can exist in a world of matter in
motion. Regarding motives, however, he is gratefully clear. He
accepts my reading of behaviorism as implying that Hitler’s hatred had
nothing causally to do with his acts of genocide, and adds that mental
tensions are “erroneously said to foster war-like acts.”
Newton’s
“ideas” made no difference to what he wrote, and Othello’s feelings of
jealousy were no more responsible for his jealous acts than his feelings
of pain were responsible for his death. To the comment that here he
would have against him “every major moralist, historian, and man of
letters” Professor Skinner replies that these men would also have
opposed modern science when it said you could extract vast energy from a
lump of mud.
Now I do not think
they would; humanists are more likely to be helplessly credulous when
scientists speak in their own field. But even if they did, the
testimony of humanists when in turn they speak in their own field can
hardly thus be brushed aside. They feel threatened by a rising wave of
computerized philistinism, which seems bent on liquidating the world
they live in. They are coming to learn with bewilderment that the new
science of mind rules out as an antiquated delusion the entire realm of
mind once occupied by the humanities. It says that in the traditional
humanistic sense the poetry of Keats, the thought of Kant, the music of
Mozart, the morality of Schweitzer, the religion of Tillich, ever the
scientific reflection of Newton and Darwin, literally never existed at
all, and that there was really nothing about these men except their
bodily complexity to distinguish them from an IBM computer. And the
theory not only destroys the humanities in principle; it makes education
in them or any other field pointless, for there is nothing about a
complex robot to make it more worth being than a simple robot. “We
cannot make men stop killing each other,” says Professor Skinner, “by
changing their feelings.” Why educate their feelings at all, one
wonders, if not even the hatred of a Hitler or the jealousy of an
Othello can make the slightest difference in what they do? It seems
equally pointless to educate men to reflect, for the foresight of the
consequences of their conduct can never affect that conduct. Indeed it
is hard to see why, in a behaviorist world, any consequences should be
better than any others. Why should I not impose suffering on others if
it is only a mentalistic unreality? Fortunately Professor Skinner is so
unreasonable a behaviorist as to be a very kindly and considerate man.
He has quoted a name
we both revere, and may I do so too in closing? William James, our
greatest psychologist, was a man who believed in science thoroughly, but
also believed in the existence, the importance, and the efficacy of
consciousness. He concluded his Lowell Lectures with this sentence:
“I, for one, as a scientist and practical man alike, deny utterly that
science compels me to believe that my conscience is an ignis fatuus or
outcast, and I trust that you too . . . will go away strengthened in
the natural faith that your delights and sorrows, your loves and hates,
your aspirations and efforts are real combatants in life’s arena, and
not impotent, paralytic spectators of the game.”
Posted March 5, 2007
Back
to Blanshard page