From Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 29, No. 1
(September 1968), 116-118. The original title was “Rejoinder to Mr.
Kearns”
Rejoinder to a
Criticism of My Theory of Universals
Brand Blanshard
I am grateful to Mr. Kearns for the searching attention he has given to
my theory of universals. In this brief rejoinder I can do no more than
touch on his main criticisms. His general thesis is that if I accept
the specific universal (e.g. this shade of red) as a genuine identity, I
should do the same with the qualitative universal (e.g. redness) and the
generic universal (e.g. animality), instead of falling back on
resemblance.
He offers several arguments against the resemblance theory. The first
is that it involves a vicious infinite regress. Suppose we start with
two pairs of specific universals; pink and crimson resemble each other,
and so do pink and black. But then these two resemblances themselves
resemble each other, and we can say that the first resemblance is closer
to complete identity than the second. This involves again a higher
order of resemblance, for the resemblance between these two resemblances
will itself more or less resemble other resemblances, and so on without
end. And we cannot pronounce the first resemblance to hold unless we
have completed this infinite series of resemblances, which of course we
cannot do.
I do not find this as convincing as perhaps I should. I concede that an
indefinite series of resemblances is entailed by the first resemblance,
but I do not think this must be completed before the initial resemblance
is seen. I can judge that pink resembles crimson, and that this
resemblance is closer to identity than that between pink and black,
without adverting to any hierarchy of resemblances entailed by those
earlier ones. After I have had my first perception I can by analysis of
it see that the later ones are involved, just as I can see that by
recognizing a figure as a triangle I have committed myself to the
presence of all that being a triangle entails. But neither in the one
case nor in the other do I see that these implications must be
recognized or exhausted before the first judgment can be validly made.
Secondly, Mr. Kearns thinks that my opposition to generic and
qualitative universals arises in part from confusion, a confusion
between two ways in which a genus may be included in its species.
Sometimes the species is formed by adding to the genus something from
outside, as when we add red to the genus rectangle to form the species
red rectangle. But sometimes the relation is far more intimate, as it
is between the genus rectangle and the species square. In the former of
these cases it may make sense to say that the genus is a little granule
of identity in the midst of alien associates. It makes no sense in the
latter. And it is because I have assimilated the second to the first
that I have been so tempted by resemblance. Confronted by cases of the
second kind, I have looked round for my granule of identity, failed to
find it, and fallen back on resemblance as a way out. I have failed to
recognize that in such cases the relation belongs to neither type; here
the species are neither mere composites nor mere similars, but
developments of the genus. They are its very “ways of being.”
No, to the charge of neglecting this last type of genus-species relation
I plead not guilty. The importance of it is a main point of the chapter
on “The False or Abstract Universal” in my book The Nature of Thought.
I cannot complain if Mr. Kearns has not read that book; it puts him in
a large and distinguished company. But I can assure him that if I have
resorted to resemblance as the unifying element in certain classes, it
is not because I have confounded the development type with the
association type of genus-species relation.
He is right, however, in saying that in the development type it is
especially hard to bring to light any core of identity among the
species; just what is the animality that is identical in Aristotle and
an amoeba? In my earlier book I found it not among the individuals, but
in the thought itself, conceived as a purpose that might be realized in
and through them; the genus exists in the mind, not in nature. This may
or may not be sound. But in either case it seems necessary to recognize
some sort of unity among the individuals in nature, and in my Reason
and Analysis I found it easier to unite them by similarity than by
the presence in each of an abstractable identity.
Here arises Mr. Kearns’ third difficulty. He thinks that if I have
failed to find such an identity, it is partly because I have set up a
mistaken requirement for an abstraction: it must be capable of existing
separately. I agree that such a requirement would be mistaken.
Certainly we can often distinguish in an object before us attributes
that cannot exist apart—convex and concave, for example. In reply I can
only plead that I have nowhere knowingly used that test. There is no
such thing as animality existing apart from all animals and wandering
about on its own. But that is not the reason I suspect it. I suspect
it because I have found myself unable to conceive it clearly, as
distinct from the characters of its species.
Fourthly, Mr.
Kearns
thinks that my difficulty in recognizing qualitative universals is
rooted in a misunderstanding of their admitted vague-ness. In the
concept of red, how far are we to go among the pinks at one end and the
crimsons at the other? People differ on the point, and differ even from
themselves. And since their concepts are thus unstable at the edges,
the abstraction of a stable common element may be impracticable. Mr.
Kearns argues, however, that this vagueness is both natural and curable.
It can be removed by an arbitrary decision as to what shades are to be
covered by a given genus and what not. Once agreement is reached on
that head, the vagueness disappears, and with it the difficulty of
accepting the qualitative universal.
I agree that the vagueness would disappear, but not the difficulty. For
the difficulty of accepting such universals is that of analyzing out
what is meant by a red that, without being any specific red, is
identical in all reds, whether their range is defined or not. It is my
failure to find such an identity, not the vagueness of its coverage,
that had made me skeptical about the qualitative universal.
Mr. Kearns has done well, I think, to raise these questions. I am
encouraged by his agreement that at least for many universals the
granular theory breaks down. Being a square is a way of being a
rectangle, not a mere conjunction of rectangularity and squareness. This
is an insight of importance for logic, and if Mr. Kearns can
successfully analyze it, we shall all be in his debt.
Posted April 20, 2008
Back
to Blanshard page