From The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
Paul Edwards, Editor in Chief.
New
York: Macmillan, 1967, Vol. 8, 322-24.
Wisdom
Brand Blanshard
Wisdom in
its broadest and commonest sense denotes sound and serene judgment
regarding the conduct of life. It may be accompanied by a broad range
of knowledge, by intellectual acuteness, and by speculative depth, but
it is not to be identified with any of these and may appear in their
absence. It involves intellectual grasp or insight, but it is concerned
not so much with the ascertainment of fact or the elaboration of
theories as with the means and ends of practical life.
Wisdom
literature.
Concern with the art of living long preceded formal science or
philosophy in human history. All ancient civilizations seem to have
accumulated wisdom literatures, consisting largely of proverbs handed
down from father to son as the crystallized results of experience.
Perhaps the most ancient known collection of these sayings is the
Egyptian “Wisdom of Ptah-hotep,” which comes down from 2500 B.C. The
writings Confucius (sixth century B.C.) and Mencius (fourth century
B.C.), though more sophisticated, are still concerned with the Tao, the
good or normal human life. The early writes of India held views at once
more speculative and more disillusioned than those of China; both
Buddhists and Hindus found the greatest happiness of man in deliverance
from the grinding round of suffering and death and in absorption into
Atman or nirvana, where personality and struggle alike disappear. But
large parts of the Bhagavad-Gita and the Dhammapada, two classics among
the scriptures of
India, are devoted to maxims and counsels for the conduct of life.
Of far
greater influence in the West has been the Wisdom literature of the
Hebrew people, which consists of the more philosophical parts of the Old
Testament and the Apocrypha. Perhaps the most important of these are
the books of Job, Proverbs, and Psalms and the apocryphal book called
The Wisdom of Solomon. There is no certain knowledge of who wrote any
of them; they are probably the work of many men, extending over
centuries. They differ strikingly from the writings of Greek and
Chinese moralists in the closeness with which morality is identified
with religion. The Hebrew sages were all monotheists who held that God
fashioned the world but remained outside it; he had made his will known
in the law delivered to Moses. This law set the standard and pattern of
goodness for all time; the good man will make it his study and seek to
conform his life to it. At the same time these sages reduced the
miraculous element in Jewish history; they made no claim to being
inspired themselves, and inclining, indeed, to assume that the sole
motive of conduct was self-advantage, they offered their prudential
maxims as not only conforming to the divine law but also as the product
of good sense and sound reason. There is very little evidence that they
were affected by Greek thought, though Greek influence must have flowed
around them after the conquests of Alexander. It is possible that in
their cool and reasonable note, contrasting so sharply with the
visionary fervor of the prophets, there is an echo of the reflective
thought of
Greece.
The
Greeks had a wisdom literature of their own which long preceded the
appearance of their great philosophers. Hesiod (eighth century B.C.) and
Theognis (sixth century B.C.) summed up in poetic form the maxims of
traditional morality. Pythagoras (sixth century B.C.), a curious
combination of mathematician and religious seer, seems to have found in
philosophy the guide of practical life. This view was further developed
by the Sophists, who, at a time when libraries and universities were
unknown, undertook to instruct young men in the arts, theoretical and
practical, that were most likely to lead to success. In their emphasis
on success, however, there was something skeptical and cynical; the art
of life tended in their teaching to become the sort of craft that enable
one by clever strategy to achieve place and power.
The
Greek conception.
The first full statement and embodiment of the classic Greek conception
of wisdom came with Socrates (c. 470-399 B.C.), who insisted that virtue
and knowledge were one, that if men failed to live well, it was through
ignorance of what virtue really was. He had no doubt that if men know
what virtue was, they would embody it in their conduct. Thus, he set
himself to define the major virtues with precision. His method was to
consider particular instances of them and bring to light the features
they had in common; this would give the essence and true pattern of the
virtue in question. He did not profess to be satisfied with the results
of his inquiries, but his acuteness and thoroughness made him the first
of the great theoretical moralists, and the courage with which he
carried his principles into both life and death gave him a unique place
in Western history.
The stress on wisdom
was maintained by his disciple Plato. For Plato there are three
departments of human nature, which may be described as the appetites,
directed to such ends as food and drink; the distinctively human
emotions, such as courage and honor; and reason. Of these reason is the
most important, for only as impulse and feeling are governed by it will
conduct be saved from chaos and excess; indeed, in such government
practical wisdom consists. In one respect Aristotle carried the
exaltation of reason farther than Plato; in addition to this practical
wisdom, he recognized another and purely intellectual virtue, the wisdom
that pursues truth for its own sake and without reference to practice.
In this pursuit, which can be followed effectively only by the
philosopher, lay the highest and happiest life.
It was among the
Stoics, however, that guidance by reason was most seriously and widely
attempted. In the thought of the Roman emperor Marcus Aurelius (A.D.
121-180), both nature and human nature are determined by causal law, and
the wrongs and insults that other men inflict on us are therefore as
inevitable as the tides. The wise man will understand this
inevitability and not waste his substance in futile indignation or
fear. He will conform himself to nature’s laws, recognize that passion
is a symptom of ignorance, free himself from emotional attachments and
resentments, and live as far as he can the life of a “passionless
sage.” The account given by Marcus Aurelius in his famous journal of
his struggle to order his practice and temper by this ideal of austere
rationality has made his little book a classic of pagan wisdom.
Modern
philosophers.
The opinions of modern philosophers on the meaning of wisdom are too
various for review here. But it can be noted of these thinkers, as it
was of Marcus Aurelius, that their standing as purveyors or exemplars of
wisdom bears no fixed relation to their eminence as philosophers. If
their chief work lies, as Kant’s does, in the theory of knowledge, or as
McTaggart’s does, in technical metaphysics, it may have no obvious
bearing on practical life. Furthermore, by reason of an unhappy
temperament, some philosophers of name and influence, such as Rousseau,
have been far from notable exemplars of wisdom in either controversy or
conduct. On the other hand, there are thinkers who have shown in their
writing, and sometimes also in their lives, so large a humanity and good
sense that they have been held in especial esteem for their wisdom
whether or not they have been of high philosophical rank. Montaigne and
Emerson are examples on one level; John Locke, Bishop Butler, John
Stuart Mill, and Henry Sidgwick are examples from a more professional
level. Among technical thinkers of the first rank, a figure who has
left a deep impression for a wisdom serene and disinterested, though a
little above the battle, is the famous philosopher of
Amsterdam,
Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677).
Components of wisdom.
Are there any traits uniformly exhibited by the very diverse minds that
by general agreement are wise? Two traits appear to stand out—reflectiveness
and judgment.
Reflectiveness.
By reflectiveness is meant the habit of considering events and beliefs
in the light of their grounds and consequences. Conduct prompted merely
by impulse or desire is notoriously likely to be misguided, and this
holds true of both intellectual and practical conduct. Whether a belief
is warranted must be decided by the evidence it rests on and the
implications to which it leads, and one can become aware of these only
by reflection. Similarly, whether an action is right or wrong depends,
at least in part, on the results that it produces in the way of good and
evil, and these results can be taken into account only by one who looks
before he leaps. Common sense, with its rules and proverbs, no doubt
helps, but it is too rough and general a guide to be relied on safely;
and the reflective man will have at his command a broader view of
grounds and consequences, causes and effects. He will more readily
recognize the beliefs of superstition, charlatanism, and bigotry for
what they are because he will question the evidence for them and note
that when reflectively developed, they conflict with beliefs known to be
true. In the same way he will be able to recognize some proposals for
action as rash, partisan, or shortsighted because certain consequences
have been ascribed to them falsely and others have been ignored. In
some activities wisdom consists almost wholly of such foresight. A
general, for example is accounted wise if he can foresee in detail how
each of the courses open to him will affect the prospects of victory.
Judgment.
There is a wisdom of ends as well as of means, which is here denoted by
“judgment.” The goal of the general—namely, victory—is laid down for
him, but the ordinary man needs the sort of wisdom that can appraise and
choose his own ends. The highest wisdom of all, Plato contended, is
that required by the statesman, who is called upon to fix both the goals
toward which society strives and the complex methods by which it may
most effectively move toward them. Unfortunately, at this crucial point
where the ends of life are at issue, the sages have differed
profoundly. Some, like Epicurus and Mill, have argued for happiness;
others, like the Christian saints, for self-sacrificing love; others,
like Nietzsche, for power. Many philosophers of the present [20th]
century have come to hold that this conflict is beyond settlement by
reason, on the ground that judgments of good and bad are not expressions
of knowledge at all but only of desire and emotion. For these thinkers
there is properly no such thing as wisdom regarding intrinsic goods;
knowledge is confined to means.
Whatever the future
of this view, common opinion is still at one with the main tradition of
philosophy; it regards the judgment of values as a field in which wisdom
may be pre-eminently displayed. It must admit, however, that this
judgment is of a peculiar kind; it seems to be intuitive in the sense
that it is not arrived at by argument nor easily defended by it. One may
be certain that pleasure is better than pain and yet be at a loss to
prove it; the insight seems to be immediate. And where immediate
insights differ, as they sometimes do, the difference appears to be
ultimate and beyond remedy. Must such wisdom end in dogmatic
contradiction and skepticism?
That it need not do
so will perhaps be evident from a few further considerations. First,
differences about intrinsic goods may be due to mere lack of knowledge
on one side or the other. The Puritans who condemned music and drama as
worthless could hardly have excluded them if they had known what they
were excluding; in these matters wider experience brings an amended
judgment. Second, what appears to be intuitive insight may express
nothing more than a confirmed habit or prejudice. Where deep-seated
feelings are involved, as in matters of sex, race, or religion, the
certainty that belongs to clear insight may be confused with the wholly
different certainty of mere confidence or emotional conviction.
Fortunately, Freud and others have shown that these irrational factors
can be tracked down and largely neutralized. Third, man’s major goods
are rooted in his major needs, and since the basic needs of human nature
are everywhere the same, the basic goods are also the same. No
philosophy of life that denied value to the satisfactions of food or
drink or sex or friendship or knowledge could hope to commend itself in
the long run.
It should be pointed
out, finally, that the judgment of the wise man may carry a weight out
of all proportion to that of anything explicit in his thought or
argument. The decisions of a wise judge may be implicitly freighted
with experience and reflection, even though neither may be consciously
employed in the case before him. Experience, even when forgotten beyond
recall, leaves its deposit, and where this is the deposit of long trial
and error, of much reflection, and of wide exposure in fact or
imagination to the human lot, the judgment based on it may be more
significant than any or all of the reasons that the judge could adduce
for it. This is why age is credited with wisdom; years supply a means
to it whether or not the means is consciously used. Again, the
individual may similarly profit from the increasing age of the race;
since knowledge is cumulative, he can stand on the shoulders of his
predecessors. Whether individual wisdom is on the average increasing is
debatable, but clearly the opportunity for it is. As Francis Bacon, a
philosopher whose wisdom was of the highest repute, remarked, “We are
the true ancients.”
Bibliography
For proverbial wisdom
see Archer Taylor, The Proverb (Cambridge, Mass., 1931), and—old
but suggestive—R. C. Trench, Proverbs and Their Lessons (London
and New York, 1858).
For the problems of
determining right and wrong, see any first-rate work on ethics, such as
Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Chicago, 1962).
For an analysis of
reflection, see, for example, John Dewey, How We Think (New York, 1910).
For the place of
reason in valuation, see L. T. Hobhouse, The Rational Good (New
York, 1921), or Brand Blanshard, Reason and Goodness (London and
New York, 1962).
For some useful
popular works see T. E. Jessop, Reasonable Living (London, 948); H. C. King, Rational Living (New York, 1912); and A. E.
Murphy, The Uses of Reason (New York, 1943).
Back
to Blanshard page