Brand Blanshard
Bradley’s thought is
so alien to present fashions of philosophising that a full-scale attempt
to appraise him by one who is at home among those fashions is bound to
be interesting. Mr. Wollheim disagrees with Bradley at every major
point; he finds his logic confused, his metaphysics obscure, his account
of knowledge and truth untenable, his ethical theory, though a little
more plausible, still quite unsatisfactory. But the book is far from
being merely an attack. It is a determined attempt by one whose
philosophical education has predisposed him against the whole Bradleian
outlook to see precisely what Bradley was saying and whether or not it
was true. And on the whole, both the analysis and the criticism are
exceedingly well done.
In Mr. Wollheim’s
view, Bradley’s philosophy is more negative than has been commonly
supposed; “we have the sense in studying it that it is built on a series
of denials, of negatives, of rejections.” This holds even of the
Logic, which Mr. Wollheim regards as a sustained attack on
empiricism. The empiricists had held that thought is essentially a
matter of images whose relations are governed by past associations;
Bradley insisted that thought dealt with universals which were, or might
be, connected necessarily. The ideas of the empiricists belonged to
their own minds; Bradley’s universals were part and parcel of the
independent world. His assault was not wholly unsuccessful. Though
there has been a return to empiricism of “a far more radical kind than
anything he knew or envisaged,” Bradley is classed with Frege as a
pioneer of the logic that has freed itself from its old dependence on
psychology.
The largest single
section of Mr. Wollheim’s book is devoted to Bradley’s “case against
pluralism.” The plain man and the pluralist are alike inclined to say
that the world can be broken up into a vast number of more or less
independent facts. Bradley denied both the existence and the
independence of these facts. Their existence he denied by means of a
new analysis of demonstrative judgments. When we say “that house is
white,” we seem to be pointing to a unique thing whose being white is a
unique fact. Bradley holds that we never reach such facts. “House” and
“white” both name universals; even “this” is a short-hand name for
universals; it means “the house in the square opposite the fountain in
the shape of a dolphin” and so on. Our effort to reach the particular
resolves itself into an effort to complete an inexhaustible series of
universals. Mr Wollheim thinks that the trouble here is that Bradley is
considering words as used in logic-books rather than in living speech.
It is true that, taken out of context, all these words refer to
universals, but when a man says “that house,” his actual reference is
particular, whether his words fully convey it or not. I do not think
Bradley would be much troubled by this criticism. He would be quite
content to enter the man’s thought and to show that any specification of
his meaning he cared to make, no matter how extended, still left him
among universals. I venture to think also that if Bradley had lived
into “the age of analysis,” and read, for example, Wittgenstein’s
account of “this is white” as the ascription of an attribute to a
faceless indescribable “it,” he would have driven a coach-and-four
through the analysis with surprising ease and all his old eloquent
scorn.
But of course Bradley
did not deny that judgment in some sense stated fact. Though the
grammatical subject and predicate named universals only, the judgment
declared the fact that subject and predicate in union qualified a
reality beyond the act. What was that reality? Not a thing-in-itself
nor a characterless it, but a system continuous with present experience,
of which the subject-predicate before us was a fragment. To apprehend
this fragment rightly, we must grasp it in its context. Every judgment,
therefore, is a hypothetical judgment, in which we state that something
is true on conditions—conditions that are inexhaustible and for the most
part unknown to us. Here is the second contention that Mr. Wollheim
singles out in Bradley’s attack on pluralism. Every fact is dependent
on other facts, and these on still others, and so on without end. The
judged fact is a link in a chain which seems to be fastened nowhere.
“And when the end is unsupported, all the rest is unsupported. Hence
our conditioned truth is only conditional.” We never
arrive anywhere at fact which, as it comes to us, can be taken as
settled and final.
Mr. Wollheim thinks
Bradley is arguing here from a muddled analogy. A chain not fastened at
the end would be insecure, but its links would still exist. Bradley is
arguing that because the chain of facts has no fastening at the end, the
links themselves are illusory; and this is absurd, because the existence
of such links or facts is presupposed in the argument; it is what
enables the argument to get under way. Again, I do not think Bradley
would be much worried. It is true that one who holds his position has,
in a sense, no right to talk at all, since whatever he says will be
subject to infinite unnamed conditions and therefore presumably false.
Bradley would of course admit this. He would insist that no fact as we
know it is real or stable fact. But neither is it simply unreal; it is
a fragment whose nature we can more fully master, if we try, by
mastering more of its conditions; and nothing ventured, nothing won. He
is not simply denying the existence of the links; he is denying the
finality of these links as they first present themselves to us, and
holding that as we see their wider linkage, their character will be
modified for us. In this I see no inconsistency.
In dealing with
Bradley’s teaching on internal relations, Mr. Wollheim offers acute
criticism of his doctrine of negation, his view of the contradictory as
the sum of the contraries, his baffling theory of identity, his struggle
over inference, and his coherence theory of truth. There is a chapter
on appearance and reality in which a good deal of cold water is thrown
on the display of dialectical fireworks by which Bradley reduces the
whole phenomenal world, with its things and selves, and its orders of
time, space, and causation, to a soggy mass of incoherence. With much
of this criticism one can only agree. Mr. Wollheim rounds off his book
with an account of Bradley’s ethics which shows how mistaken it is to
accept the famous chapter on “My Station and Its Duties” as his final
word on morals, and with a few interesting pages about his attitudes
toward faith, religion, and death.
It is in these last
pages that hlr Wollheim’s estimate of Bradley comes out most clearly.
He conceives him a little as Macaulay conceived of Burke, as a man who
contrived most impressive reasons for conclusions adopted on other
grounds. He was a man who had seen a vision, and was trying to get
others to see it also—a vision of “a unified and ordered and seamless
whole,” in which all the forms of imperfection that dog the human lot
are overcome. Mr. Wollheim cannot resist the temptation to do a little
amateur “depth psychology” on his distinguished subject and to find in
his acceptance of an Absolute a means of dealing with a deep-seated
anxiety. It may be true. If so, we could do with more people who see
visions and feel insecure. Bradley’s warmest admirers must admit that
he was an uneven thinker, with curious blind spots (as for mathematics),
and with certain prejudices (against Mill and Sidgwick, for example)
that are hard to share. But he is a dangerous man for “minute
philosophers” to write about, for by so doing, they will send students
back to him, and that is always a perilous thing to do. For Bradley,
with all his defects, was a philosopher in the grand manner, and there
breathes through his writing the vitality—the fire, force, and gusto—of
a mind intensely alive. He confessed that for him philosophy was “a
principal way of experiencing the Deity,” and added that “no one,
probably, who has not felt this, however differently he might describe
it, has ever cared much for metaphysics.” Such statements are a source
of uncomprehending embarrassment to commentators for whom the business
of philosophy is to dissect the meanings of words, but no critic who
fails to understand them can penetrate to where Bradley lived. I do
not think Mr. Wollheim has quite got there. But he has written the best
general criticism of Bradley that we have.
Posted September 24, 2007
Back
to Blanshard page