The Transcendental Argument for God’s Existence
Michael R. Butler
III. Transcendental Arguments in Recent Philosophical Literature
Though transcendental arguments (TAs here-after) have been used by
various philosophers since Aristotle,[41] it is with the publication of
P. F. Strawson’s Individuals,[42] that TAs have become a
prominent fixture in contemporary philosophy. The discussion of the
structure and nature of TAs has generated a good deal of
controversy. In what follows, I will overview the contemporary
literature on TAs with the aim of setting the most common criticisms of
TAG in sharper focus.
A. The Nature of
Transcendental Arguments
Before plunging into the current debate over TAs it will helpful to
first sketch the form TAs gene-rally take as well review a few
definitions proffered in the literature. The aim here is not so much to
analyze the nature of TAs—this would require a paper of its own—but to
get something of a feel for what kind of arguments they are.[43]
A TA takes on (roughly) the following form: For x to be the case, y must
also be the case because y is the necessary precondition of x; since x
is the case, y must be the case. By itself there is nothing particularly
distinguished about this form of argu-ment. For with it I
could argue that having parents is the precondition of having
grandparents, and since I have grandparents, I must have parents. Though
this shares a structure similar to that of a TA, it is not a TA because
it appeals a posteriori knowledge—in this case, knowledge of
basic biolo-gical facts. TAs are distinguished from this type of
argument by the fact that they appeal only to a priori
knowledge—what we can know without any appeal to experience. From this
it follows that form alone is not the distinguishing feature that sets
TAs apart from other arguments.[44] Most recent commentators are in
agreement with this conclusion. Grayling is representative:
[T]o argue, or reason, or proceed transcendentally, or to employ
stan-dard philosophical techniques tran-scendentally, is just to argue or
pro-ceed, etc., with a certain aim in mind and a certain subject-matter
to hand ...there is nothing distinctive about the form of TAs, and that
what is distinctive about them is their aim and subject matter.[45]
What, then, is the aim and subject matter of TAs? Before answering
this, it is helpful to consider what is not the aim or subject of
TAs. TAs should not be confused with paradigm-case and/or polar concept
arguments popularized by Austin, Ryle and others of the
so-called Oxford school.[46] For while these types of arguments share a
similar form with TAs, they differ greatly in the type of conclusion
that is inferred. Specifically, TAs have highly generalized conclusions
while polar concept arguments are much narrower. A brief comparison
should bring out this distinction. Austin argues that the skeptic’s
appeal to illusion does not work because the term ‘illusion’ makes sense
only in a context of having some real things to compare with it and thus
everything could not be an illusion (or better put, it makes no sense to
say everything is an illusion). Assuming this argument works, the
conclusion in somewhat parochial: it defeats only one particular
skeptical challenge. The skeptic, though, can simply propose to toss
away both words and offer a fresh challenge. A TA aims at something
more cosmopolitan. Unlike polar con-cept arguments, TAs attempt to
demonstrate that x (whatever x may be) is a precondition of experi-ence.
In a word, then, the difference between a TA and a polar concept
argument is one of scope; the latter asks what are the necessary
preconditions for the intelligible use of a small set of terms, the
former is concerned with the use of a much larger set.
With this aim in mind, we are now in a position to survey a few
representative definitions found in the contemporary literature.
According to Anthony Bruekner a TA is:
an argument that elucidates the con-ditions for the possibility of some
fun-damental phenomenon whose exis-tence is unchallenged or
uncontrover-sial in the philosophical context in which the argument is
propound-ed. Such an argument proceeds de-ductively, from a premise
asserting the existence of some basic pheno-menon (such as meaningful
dis-course, conceptualization of objective states of affairs, or the
practice of making promises), to a conclusion as-serting the existence of
some interes-ting, substantive enabling conditions for that
phenomenon.[47]
Brueckner points to three salient ingredients that are involved in
TAs. First, they begin with some unchallenged or uncontroversial phenome-non
or experience (e.g., I speak a language or I have an idea of a single
spatio-temporal system of material things). Next, from this phenomenon
they proceed deductively to a conclusion. Finally, this
conclusion is a non-trivial condition for the possi-bility of the
phenomenon. Grayling further refines the nature of a TA’s conclusion:
... the aim of transcendental argu-ments is to establish the conditions
necessary for experience, or experi-ence of a certain kind, in general;
and, at their most controversial, to estab-lish conclusions about the
nature and existence of an external world, or other minds, derived from
paying attention to what has to be the case for there to be experience,
or for experience to be as it is.[48]
The conclusion of a TA either tells us something about the conditions
necessary for experience or something about the nature of reality. That
it, the conclusion of a TA may either be conceptual or on-tological.
Ross Harrison adds one more characterization of TAs:
Transcendental arguments seek to answer scepticism by showing that the
things doubted by the sceptic are in fact preconditions for the
skepti-cism to make sense. Hence the skep-ticism is either meaningless or
false. A transcendental argument works by finding the preconditions of
meaning-ful thought or judgment. For example, skepticism about other
minds sug-gests that only the thinkers them-selves might have sensations.
A tran-scendental argument which answered this scepticism would show that
a precondition for thinking oneself to have sensations is that others do
so as well. Expressing the skepticism in-volves thinking oneself to have
sen-sation; and the argument shows that if this thought is expressible,
then it is also false.[49]
According to Harrison, the refutation of the skeptic is the primary
objective of a TA. This view is supported by other commentators of
TAs. Barry Stroud, for example, maintains, “transcendental arguments
are supposed to demonstrate the im-possibility or illegitimacy of [the]
skeptical chal-lenge by proving that certain concepts are neces-sary for
thought or experience.”[50] Similarly, Strawson asserts that one who
“advances such an argument [transcendental] may begin with a pre-mise
which the skeptic does not challenge ... and then proceed to argue
[what the] necessary condi-tion of the possibility of such experience
is.”
While it is true that most (though certainly not all) contemporary TAs
are used as skepticism-refuting arguments, this aim is not a necessary
feature of them. Indeed, the view that TAs are essentially
anti-skeptical in nature rests upon a historical mistake. This mistake
is revolves around a faulty interpretation of Kant’s understanding of
a TA. In the next section I offer an analysis of the nature of Kantian
TAs.
B. Kant and
Transcendental Arguments
Before analyzing and evaluating contemporary TAs, it is obligatory to
say a few words about Kant. Contemporary proponents of TAs, such
as Strawson, often cite Kant as their inspiration. The TAs they offer,
however, differ in at least one fundamental way from Kantian
TAs. Whereas Kant’s understanding of a priori knowledge, and
hence transcendental reasoning, was closely tied to his view that the
forms of sensibility and concepts of the understanding in some way
consti-tute experience,[51] contemporary TAs tend to avoid anything
resembling Kant's transcendental idealism.
Because of this, a number of philosophers have accused contemporary
advocates of TAs, such as Strawson, of denuding Kant’s TAs of their
distinc-tiveness. Indeed, some go so far as to claim that the
contemporary reformulations do not deserve the title of “transcendental
argument” at all. Before one is tempted to cast aside this whole debate
as a petty etymological squabble,[52] it should be realized that more
than nomenclature or lexical proprietorship is at stake. Kant is, among
other things, the father of TAs.[53] Thus it would be a rather odd
conclusion to state that his arguments were not TAs. Indeed, one is
tempted to say that whatever Kant is doing in the first Critique,
he is arguing transcendentally. This is perhaps what Jaako Hintikka is
getting at when he states that “the first order of business in any
discussion of such arguments is to try to see what Kant under-stood by
the term.”[54] Ross Harrison is even more explicit, “Since Kant
invented the label, any-thing properly called a ‘transcendental’ argument
must have some analogy to the arguments which Kant used.”[55] These
considerations have weight, and so, taking Hintikka's advice,
understanding Kant's use of transcendental arguments shall be my first
order of business.
In his preface to the second edition, Kant men-tions in a note that the
only addition to the Critique was the Refutation of Idealism (Bxl),
the purpose of which was to once and for all do away with the scandal of
philosophy: that the existence of things outside us must be accepted
merely on faith. A cluster of controversial issues revolve
around the interpretation of the Refutation that are of import for the
contemporary debate about TAs. Should, for example, the Refutation be
viewed as Kant’s main TA? Much of the recent literature on TAs in-sists
that is the case. But this raises an immediate question. If the
Refutation is indeed Kant’s main TA, how are we to explain its absence
in the first edition? A related issue concerns the Refutation’s place
in understanding Kant’s transcendental pro-ject. Even if it is not Kant’s
main TA, it appears at least to be the clearest. Should we therefore use
it at a heuristic in understanding the more difficult arguments
contained in the Deduction? A final issue has to is whether the
Refutation is an exam-ple of a transcendental argument at all. Since the
answer of this last question is needed before we tackle the other
questions, it is to this I shall turn.
To help answer this question, a preliminary question needs to be
addressed. What did Kant mean by the term, ‘transcendental’? Perhaps
the clearest expression is found in the Introduction of the Critique:
I entitle transcendental all knowledge which is occupied not so much
with objects as with the mode of our know-ledge of objects insofar as
this mode of knowledge is to be possible a priori (A11/B25).[56]
Elsewhere Kant says that the only way we can know something about
objects a priori is knowing what we put into them (Bxviii). He also
flatly de-nies that the word ‘transcendental’ has any refer-ence to
knowledge of things; it refers only to cogni-tive faculties.[57] Hence,
transcendental know-ledge is knowledge of what our cognitive faculties
“impose” upon the world. From this Hintikka con-cludes:
Thus a transcendental argument is for Kant one which shows the
possibility of a certain type of synthetic know-ledge a priori by
showing how it is due to those activities of ours by means of which the
knowledge in question is obtained[58] (Hintikka, p. 275).
Hintika rightly takes Kant’s main TAs to be those in the Transcendental
Aesthetic and Tran-scendental Deduction. Though he admits that they are
not as lucid as they could be (a mild under-statement), Kant indicates
his intention to show that a priori knowledge always involves the
active processes of the mind. In a programmatic pas-sage, Kant writes:
“But only the productive synthe-sis of the imagination can take place
a priori” (A118).
What then of the Refutation? Hintikka (again rightly) maintains that
the Refutation should not be viewed as Kant’s paradigm TA. Indeed, he
thinks it is not even a TA at all. It is an ad hominem argu-ment
showing that the idealist contradicts his own position in the very
process of stating his position. In other words, this is a very different kind of argu-ment than those found in the Aesthetic and the
De-duction.[59]
A further consideration bolsters his claim. It is difficult to construe
the Refutation as the paradigm TA in the Critique since it was a
later addition to the second edition. And unless one wants to argue
that the first and second editions offer significantly different
philosophical outlooks (which nobody does) it is absurd to think of it
as his central TA. The retort to this is that while the Refutation is
not Kant’s central TA, it is his clearest example of one. Thus in
understanding it we can better under-stand his more difficult ones in the
Aesthetic and Deduction. I will return to this contention
present-ly. What is important to note now is that Kantian TAs always
involve appeals to constitutive or productive knowledge. Appeal to
transcendental psychology is thus the sine qua non of TAs.
If Hintikka is right, most of what passes as TAs today are, as we shall
see, un-Kantian. He further adds that if they are un-Kantian, they are
spurious. What this second charge amount to, though, is not clear. If
he uses “spurious TAs” as a synonym for “un-Kantian TAs,” there is no
problem. But if he that “spurious TAs” are not TAs at all, then we have
to ask why this is the case. The next question we must address, then, is
whether his take on Kant is correct.
According to Grayling, Hintikka is wrong—or as he says, Hintikka gets
“the wrong end of the stick altogether.”[60] He tries to prove this by
pointing to Kant’s use of the metaphor of a legal deduction at the
beginning of the Transcendental Deduction (A84/B116). There Kant
asserts that, like a legal deduction which tries to justify a particular
claim or possession (i.e. prove that the claim or possession was
lawfully obtained), so a transcendental deduc-tion tries to justify the
employment of certain concepts. And it does this in a way that is
different from an empirical deduction. The latter type of de-duction
merely shows how a concept is acquired through experience and “therefore
concerns, not its legitimacy, but only its de facto mode of
origination” (A85/B117).[61] Grayling immediately concludes from this
that “the task [of transcen-dental deductions] is to provide a
vindication of title, not to show where the concepts come from.”
The problem with Grayling’s reading of Kant is that to Kant, these are
not separate questions. In order to vindicate the use of a concept one
must be able to demonstrate where the concepts come from. This is shown
by Kant’s later remarks on transcendental proofs in The Discipline of
Pure Reason. There he says that transcendental proofs are always direct
or ostensive and explains this by saying that this type of proof “is
that which combines with the conviction of its truth insight into the sources of
its truth” (A789/B817, my emphasis). In other words, transcendental
proofs or deductions are ostensive because they point to the source or
origin of truth.
As Hintikka has already noted, it is abundantly clear that the main
transcendental proofs in the Critique are found in the Aesthetic
and Deduction. It is also clear that understanding the TAs in them is
extremely difficult. This is why many take the comparatively easier
argument of the Refutation as a model to help understand them. And
since the basic form of the Refutation is a reductio [ad
absurdum], it follows that the Aesthetic and Deduction must also be
reductiones. This practice has been a common if not often stated
assumption among Kant scholars: they approach his more difficult
transcendental proofs by comparing them to easier and allegedly
analogous ones. That is, they pay attention to Kant’s alleged practice
rather than his theory.[62] This has resulted in much confusion as to
what the exact nature of Kant’s argument is.[63] It is precisely because
of the clarity of the passage at A789/B817 that it should be used as a
heuristic device to understand Kant’s main transcendental
proofs.[64] Thus the way to understand these difficult
arguments is via his me-tatheoretical comments in the Disciplines
of Pure Reason.
But what then are we to do with the above pas-sage from Kant (A85/B117)?
Based on Grayling’s reading, Kant must be contradicting himself. This
throws doubt on Grayling’s reading. Does Kant not contrast a
transcendental deduction with an empi-rical deduction that depends on the
“mere” origin of the concept? Does this not clearly state that whatever
transcendental deductions turn out to be, they are not concerned with
the source of the concept in question? A careful study of the text
leads us to a negative answer. Grayling mistakes the gist of what Kant
is getting at. Kant indeed is making a contrast between transcendental
and empirical deductions, but this contrast is not that the latter is
concerned with the mode of origination while the former is not. Rather
the latter is con-cerned with only its de facto or empirical mode
of origination (e.g. the actual perception of an object) while the
latter is concerned with the a priori mode of origination (in
this case, the transcendental ego). Grayling’s contention is based on a
profound mis-reading of the text. And so it is he, not Hintikka, who
gets the wrong end of the stick.
Before we acquiesce to Hintikka and claim that contemporary TAs are
un-Kantian because they do not make appeals to constructive knowledge,
it is important to point out the obvious. Kant did use an argument
analogous to contemporary TAs in the Refutation and the Second
Analogy. Even Hintikka admits this much. So in another sense it is not
cor-rect to call contemporary TAs un-Kantian. They are indeed Kantian
arguments, but they are not Kantian transcendental arguments. What then
of the charge that they are spurious? At this point the question has
become a mere linguistic matter. Nothing of philosophical important
hangs on the answer at all.
Since it has been the practice to call contempo-rary TAs ‘TAs’ and since,
as Walker has observed, Kant did not take out a copyright on the
term,[65]there seems to be no pressing need for a change in
nomenclature. It is little more than schoolmarmism (pace Hintikka
and Harrison) to insist that all TAs must comply with tight Kantian
strictures in order to warrant the honorific title “Transcendental
Argu-ment.” Thus it is legitimate to continue the practice of calling
contemporary TAs ‘TAs’, bearing in mind that not all TAs are Kantian in
nature.
C. Strawson
Over the last century there have been many examples of TAs in the
analytic philosophy tradi-tion. Frege, Wittgenstein, Davidson, Putnam
and Searle all have offered TAs for conclusions as various as the
necessity of senses (meanings), the impossibility of a private language,
the claim that beliefs are generally true, the claim that radical
skepticism is false and the truth of external realism.[66] It is with
the publication of Strawson’s Individuals in 1959, however, that
transcendental arguments came to the forefront of philosophical inquiry.
Strawson has spent much of his career resuscitating what he thinks
are Kant's important insights while at the same time removing the
dross. His Individuals and later The Bounds of
Sense[67] make extensive use of TAs while at the same time eschewing
synthetic a prioris and transcendental psychology. Strawson thinks that once
the swamp of intuition and the rest of Kant’s transcendental psychology
are put aside, there re-mains a core insight into how our conceptual
scheme works. According to Strawson, Kant’s work is best seen as
analysis of our conceptual scheme rather than a transcendental deduction
of catego-ries. By taking away from Kant what he considers to be this
core insight, Strawson employs TAs to solve two traditional problems in
epistemology: skepticism about other minds and skepticism about the
external world. Since the use of TAs against the latter has a longer
pedigree, I will concentrate on it. Whatever is said about this TA,
however, applies, mutatis mutandis, to the other.
Strawson’s argument against the external world skeptic is deceivingly
simple.
There is no doubt that we have the idea of a single spatio-temporal
sys-tem of material things; the idea of every material thing at any time
being spatially related, in various ways at various times, to every
other at every time. There is no doubt at all that this is our
conceptual scheme. Now I say that a condition of our ha-ving this
conceptual scheme is the unquestioning acceptance of particu-lar
identity in at least some cases of non-continuous observation.[68]
Except perhaps the last sentence, Strawson's claim seems to be perfectly
correct. It is just a fact that we think that every material
object is in some relation to every other physical object—spatially and
temporally. Of course, we do not usually speak of having a
spatiotemporal system of ma-terial things, nor are we generally cognizant
of this fact. But the way we use language demonstrates that we
presuppose this conceptual scheme. A few pedestrian examples prove this
rather easi-ly. Think of a father telling his son to move his bicycle
off of the driveway so he can park the fami-ly car or a dry cleaner who
tells the customer to pick his suit up on Tuesday morning. In both of
these scenarios, all individuals involved presup-pose that material
objects share a spatial relation to each other (either the car or the
bicycle can be parked in a particular spot but not both) and temporal
relations (the suit that is dropped off today will be the same one that
will be ready on Tuesday morning). If they did not presuppose these
relationships communication would quickly break down.
But now the skeptic comes along and chal-lenges these presuppositions
perhaps the car dis-appears when no one is looking and a different
(though similar) one appears when it is observed again. What the skeptic
is challenging us to do is justify our belief that our conceptual scheme
is true. To the skeptic Strawson replies:
He pretends to accept a conceptual scheme, but at the same time quietly
rejects one of the conditions of its employment. Thus his doubts are
un-real, not simply because they are lo-gically irresoluble doubts, but
be-cause they amount to the rejection of the whole conceptual scheme
within which alone such doubts make sense. So, naturally enough, the
alternative to doubt which he offers us is the suggestion that we do not
really, or should not really, have the conceptual scheme that we do
have; that we do not really or should not really, mean what we think we
mean, what we do mean. But this alterna-tive is absurd. For the whole
process of reasoning only starts because the scheme is as it is; and we
cannot change it even if we would.[69]
The claim is that in order to get his doubts off the ground, the skeptic
must presuppose the very conceptual scheme he calls into question. And
this illicit importation uncovers the very absurdity of his position.
It is important to realize that Strawson thought[70] that this once and
for all defeats the external world skeptic. Were this the case, it would
have been a true milestone in the history of philosophy. Like most bold
claims from well-recognized philo-sophers, though, it has become somewhat
of a cause célèbre attracting many defenders and critics.
D. Objections
1. Stroud
One of the most trenchant critics of Strawson is Stroud. In his elegant
article entitled simply “Tran-scendental Arguments,”[71] Stroud sets out
to show that TAs in general and Strawson’s in particu-lar fail to deliver
on their promise of silencing the skeptic.
Stroud takes Strawson’s argument to be:
1. We think of the world as containing objective particulars in a single
spatio-temporal system.
2. If we think of the world as con-taining objective particulars in a
sin-gle spatiotemporal system, then we are able to identify and
re-identify particulars.
3. If we can re-identify particulars, then we have satisfiable criteria
on the basis of which we can make re-identification.
6. Objects continue to exist unper-ceived.
Stroud thinks the argument stops here. And if this is the case, it is
plainly a non sequitur. Stroud has no qualms with the move from
(1) to (3). The problem is that they do not get Strawson to (6).
Additional premises are, therefore, needed, and Stroud is ready to
oblige with
4. If we know that the best criteria we have for the re-identification
of parti-culars have been satisfied, then we know that objects continue
to exist unperceived.
and
5. We sometimes know that the best criteria we have for the
re-identifica-tion of particulars have been satis-fied.
Without these or similar premises, the argu-ment is not valid. But since
(5) is a statement of fact, the skeptic would not let Strawson (or
any-body) get away with it. So from this Stroud con-cludes that Strawson
is wrong to take the skeptic as denying (6). Instead he should be taken
as de-nying whether we can know the truth of (5); whe-ther we are
justified in ever asserting it—and this is far different from the exotic
Berkeleyan claim that objects cease to exist when not observed. So (5)
is superfluous. All that is really needed is (1)—(4), which say that if
we think of the world as contain-ing objective particulars in a single
spatiotemporal system, then we can know whether objects conti-nue to
exist unperceived. Or better put, if it is meaningful to speak of
objective particulars, then we must have a way of knowing whether they
con-tinue to exist unperceived. But this is a verification principle, a
principle that maintains that for propo-sitions to be meaningful, there
must be a way, at least in principle, of knowing or testing whether they
are true or false.
The problem with this is if TAs rely upon an im-plicit verification
principle, then TAs turn out to be superfluous for the skeptic is
directly refuted by such a principle. If we sometimes know that the
best criteria we have for the re-identification of particulars have been
satisfied, then we know that skepticism is false.
Later in the article Stroud goes on to generalize this point by
maintaining that is hard to imagine that there could be any TA that does
not in some way rely on a verification principle to bridge the gap
between belief and reality. The reason being is that any TA will
maintain that denying the truth of a given discourse presupposes that
discourse. But this will not do since the skeptic can simply bite the
bullet and say that the whole discourse is mud-dled. And because the
skeptic has this route al-ways open, the transcendental arguer will have
to make a universal claim and hold that all discourse is meaningless
unless a certain set of propositions (Stroud calls it “the privileged
class”) are neces-sarily true given the general discourse. There are
several problems with this, but the main one is that this does not set
the skeptical problem to rest. All this proves is that the privileged
class must be believed; it does not prove that the privileged-class
propositions are in fact true. To ensure this, a verification principle
is necessary. But, again, why spend so much time discussing the
intricacies of a TA when the verification principle is all that is
ne-cessary to vanquish the skeptic directly?
But if we have the latter, the former is super-fluous and, thus, there is
nothing special about transcendental arguments. To put it crassly, to di-vorce
meaning from truth is to render TAs impo-tent, but to conjoin meaning and
truth is to render them (TAs) extraneous.
2. Körner
One of the most prevalent criticisms of tran-scendental arguments was
first raised in the con-temporary literature by Stephan Körner.[72]
Körner
argues that while Kant's arguments provide sufficient conditions for
human experience (in this case the categories of understanding), they
are not necessary conditions.
The person propounding a transcen-dental argument assumes that every and
any thinker employs the same categorical framework as he does himself,
and tries to show that, and why, the employment of this particu-lar
framework is ‘necessary.’ The de-fect of all transcendental arguments
is their failure to provide a uniqueness proof, i.e., the demonstration
that the categorial framework is unique.[73]
The objection is that while it may be possible to prove that some
conceptual scheme is sufficient for experience, it is not possible to
prove that it is necessary. The reason that no uniqueness proof is
possible is laid out nicely by
Körner.
Körner
con-tends that there are only three possible ways of establishing a
schema's uniquness.
First, to demonstrate the schema’s uniqueness by comparing it with
ex-perience undifferentiated by any me-thod of prior differentiation . . .
. Se-cond, to demonstrate the schema’s uniqueness by comparing it with
its possible competitors . . . . Thirdly, one might propose to examine
the schema and its application entirely from within the schema itself,
i.e., by means of statements belonging to it.[74]
These three possibilities are subject to powerful criticisms,
however. The first possibility cannot es-tablish a schema’s uniqueness
by comparing it with undifferentiated experience, since in order for a
comparison to be made, statements about the un-differentiated experience
would have to be ex-pressed by making recourse to some prior
differ-entiation of experience. That is, there is no way to formulate a
statement about experience without differentiating experience. But even
if such a comparison could be made, all that could be de-monstrated is
that the schema under consideration does represent or reflect the
undifferentiated ex-perience. But this does not establish the
unique-ness of the schema since it may be that other schemas also
represent or reflect the undifferen-tiated experience as well.
Körner offers two criticisms of the second possi-bility. First, in order
to establish the uniqueness of one schema, all other possible schemes
would have to be exhibited and refuted. But as Rorty has pointed out,
we could never know whether all possible schemas have been
exhibited. “Nothing in heaven or earth could set limits to what we can
in principle conceive.”[75] No matter how many al-ternative schemas one
can conceive and refute, there is always the possibility that there is
another schema (or several!) that has not yet been
con-ceived. Griffiths sums up this criticism nicely:
[T]o establish [the uniqueness of a schema] would involve an exami-nation
of all possible conditions. But by what criterion could we determine
that all possible conditions had been enumerated? Further, this means an
examination of all possible conditions in detail: a humanly impossible
task.[76]
Second, Körner maintains that the very act of demonstrating a schema’s
uniqueness by compar-ing it with another schema is contradictory. Such a
demonstration would presuppose that another schema, a schema distinct
from the one whose uniqueness is trying to be proved, can possibly
re-present or reflect undifferentiated experience. But if this is
presupposed, the demonstration is self-contradictory. “[This] requires
anyone who uses it to admit before the argument begins that what he is
trying to prove is false, otherwise he could not even try to prove
it.”[77]
The third possibility (attempting to establish the uniqueness of a
schema from within the schema itself) is quickly dispatched
by Körner. All that can be shown by such a proof is how the schema
differentiates a region of experience. It cannot show that it is the
only possibly schema able to differentiate that region.
E. In Defense of
Transcendental Arguments
1. Stroud
Stroud’s argument against TAs is that they ei-ther rely on dubious
factual premises or that they require a verification principle. Either
way, the TA will not do the requisite work against the skeptic since he
will either reject the factual premise out of hand or reject the
verification principle upon which the TA depends. Thus Stroud places
defenders of TAs on the horns of a dilemma: either the verifi-cation
principle must be dropped and with it the claim that the TA gets us to
what the world must be like, or the verification principle can be
maintained, but only at the price of rendering the TA unneces-sary—the
verification principle answers the skeptic directly. Almost all recent
defenders of TAs have tried to meet this dilemma by tackling the first
horn.[78] Three basic strategies have been employed in this endeavor.
First, Stroud himself puts forth the possibility of denying the
skeptic’s claim that it is sufficient that we must merely think the
world is a certain way (have a certain conceptual scheme) and not that
the world must be a certain way.[79] The skeptic is just wrong in
asserting that mere belief is enough. The only way to account for the
fact that our con-ceptual scheme must be believed (or, conversely, to say
that it makes no sense to question our con-ceptual scheme) is that it
must be true. Our con-ceptual scheme is impossible to deny because it
“corresponds” to the way in which the world actually is.
Stroud points out that it is extremely difficult to conceive of a
defense for the strong modal claim of this position (i.e., the world
must be this way in order to make experience possible).
. . . [H]ow can truths about the world which appear to say or imply
nothing about human thought or experience be shown to be genuinely
necessary conditions of such psychological facts as that we think and
experience things in a certain way, from which the proofs begin?[80]
Not only has no argument
been advanced toward this end, but what such an argument would look like
is difficult to imagine.
Second, a defender of TAs may accept Stroud’s contention that such
arguments merely give us the conclusion that we must believe the world
to be a certain way and not that it really is that way. In order to
bridge the gap from belief to the world, the defender need not make
recourse to a verification principle, but can contend that the way in
which we conceive of the world constitutes the way the world actually
is. That is, there is in reality no gap between our thoughts and the
world since the world does not exist independently of our conception of
it. This, of course, is a version of idealism. Given idealism, the move
from our conceptual scheme to reality is immediate and the TAs that make
this idealist assumption do indeed tell us something about the
world.[81]
Accepting idealism is a high price to pay to get TAs to work, however.
Indeed, Strawson’s reinter-pretation of Kant was motivated by the attempt
to purge out his problematic transcendental idealism and preserve his
ingenious insights into the analysis of concepts. Idealism is, thus,
the very thing that Strawson (and other proponents of TAs) attempts to
get away from. Moreover, a mover to-ward idealism will not in actuality
strengthen a TA since idealism is itself subject to serious criticisms
(e.g. those of Reid, Moore and Russell). And even if a good case can be
made for idealism, the assump-tion of idealism renders the anti-skeptical
TAs un-necessary since idealism refutes skepticism directly.
Third, one may concede that Stroud is correct in arguing that TAs must
rely on a verification principle to get from our conceptual scheme to
the world, but rather than give up on TAs altogether, propose a more
modest view of what TAs are supposed to prove.[82] Grayling, for
example, makes a distinction between two types of TAs—option-A and
option-B. These two options differen-tiate between TAs that have
metaphysical conclu-sions (“The world must be thus and so”) and those
that have conceptual ones (“We must not deny thus and so because of our
conceptual scheme”). For obvious reasons, Grayling is pessimistic about
the prospect for option-A TAs. As for option-B TAs, they have troubles
of their own. Such arguments attempt to establish that given our
conceptual scheme, certain concepts must be pre-supposed. That is, it
makes no sense to question our conceptual scheme since, in so doing, we
must presuppose it. But the skeptic’s reply to this line can be
anticipated: Even if certain concepts are es-sential for this conceptual
scheme, it may not be for another. Our current scheme might indeed
pre-suppose causation, but that does not mean that other possible
conceptual schemes must do so as well. This difficulty is addressed in
the following section.
2. Körner
Körner’s criticisms of the first and third possible ways in establishing
a conceptual scheme’s uni-queness are sound. There is no way to prove
the uniqueness of a conceptual scheme by comparing that scheme to
undifferentiated experience or by testing its application from within
the conceptual scheme itself. His criticisms of the second possibi-lity
are, however, subject to serious criticism.
Körner, recall, argued that the second type of proof, the proof that
attempts to demonstrate the uniqueness of a given conceptual scheme by
comparing it with its possible competitors, is impossible for two
reasons. The first is that it is “self-contradictory in attempting a
‘demonstration’ of the schema’s uniqueness, by conceding that the schema
was not unique.” What Körner means by this is that in attempting to
establish the unique-ness of a particular conceptual scheme by com-paring
it with possible competitors, this com-parison denies the very uniqueness
of the scheme it is trying to establish.
This argument, however, rests upon a confu-sion. It is true that if such
a uniqueness proof as-sumes that there are other legitimate conceptual
schemes that are in competition with the one that it is being
established, such a proof would be self-defeating. To say, for example,
that such and such a conceptual scheme is the only possible one and then
go on to compare it with another genuine conceptual scheme is an absurd
affair. However, the other possible conceptual schemes that are
compared to the one that is trying to be estab-lished by a uniqueness
proof need not be con-sidered as genuine competitors. These other
con-ceptual schemes appear to be in competition with ours, but on closer
examination, it is show that they are not. Such an argument would look
like something as follows: “One would think that this supposed
conceptual scheme poses a challenge to our conceptual scheme, but on
closer examination, this supposed conceptual scheme is, in actuality,
not a genuine conceptual scheme.”
The distinction between a genuinely competing conceptual scheme and a
merely apparent com-peting conceptual scheme shows that we can make sense
of a uniqueness proof that compares one conceptual scheme with its
possible com-petitors. But here we face a further diffi-culty. Granted
that conception of such a proof is not self-defeating, how could such a
proof actually proceed? There are at least to possible ways. First,
one can argue that the competing conceptual schemes violate some
necessary pre-condition of experience. That is, the competing conceptual
schemes are not genuine because that are unable to account for the
experience we have. Second, one can argue that all other pos-sible
conceptual schemes are dependent upon (and thus reducible to) the one he
is trying to establish as unique.
Schaper contends that the first option (demon-strating that a
supposed competitor scheme vio-lates some necessary precondition of
experience) is out of the question.[83] This is because, on the one hand, if the
necessary precondition of experi-ence belongs to the supposedly unique
conceptual scheme, the argument is question-begging. All that is being
demonstrated is that because the competing scheme does not adhere to the
sup-posedly unique scheme’s necessary preconditions of experience, it is
not a genuine competitor. This is hardly a persuasive argument. But
if, on the other hand, the necessary preconditions of experi-ence do not
belong the supposedly unique concep-tual scheme, that scheme is thereby
shown to be not unique. Either way, the first option of demon-strating
uniqueness is impossible.
The second option is to argue for the unique-ness of a particular
conceptual scheme by proving that it is the only possible conceptual
scheme. Such an argument is advanced by Donald David-son.[84] Davidson
contends that the notion of a completely foreign conceptual scheme that
philo-sophers such as Quine and Kuhn advance is inco-herent. Although
his arguments are subtle and tied in with his extensional semantics, the
gist of his contention is not difficult to understand. In order to
recognize something as an alternative concep-tual scheme, we must be able
to map it onto our own conceptual scheme. If a conceptual scheme is so
different from ours that we are not able to ac-complish such mappings, we
would not even re-cognize it as a competing conceptual scheme. This is
because the only way for us to recognize some-thing as a competing
conceptual scheme is that we compare it to our own. When no such
comparison is possible (where two “paradigms” are “incommensurable,” to
borrow from Kuhn), there would be no way for us to recognize it as a
con-ceptual scheme at all. In other words, the notion of an
inconceivable (i.e., unrecognizable) concep-tual scheme is thus
incoherent.
This brief discussion of Davidson is a nice segue into Körner’s second
reason why this kind of uni-queness proof is impossible. Recall that in
order to establish the uniqueness of one conceptual scheme, all other
possible conceptual schemes must be refuted. But surely this is an
impossible task since we do not have the time, let alone the capacity,
to conceive of every possible conceptual scheme and then proceed to
refute them one by one. If this were indeed the task, there would be no
hope of ever accomplishing a uniqueness proof. But fortunately for TAs
and their defenders, this is not what they set out to
accomplish. Rather than refuting every possible alternative conceptual
scheme, TAs endeavor to simply refute one—the negation of conceptual
scheme being defen-ded. Førster comments are insightful.
A transcendental argument ... in order to establish a particular
condition of knowledge or experience, proceeds by considering an
alternative, that is, the negation of the condition, and subsequently
demonstrates its inter-nal incoherence. Clearly, this ex-hausts the
field of possible alterna-tives to this condition. For although one may perhaps
imagine different philosophical positions or conceptions based on the
negation of the original condition, this would not add to the number of
alternatives to it.[85]
Since there is nothing particularly daunting about disproving the
negation of a conceptual scheme, a uniqueness proof for a conceptual
scheme is certainly not impossible.
An objection may be raised at this point that, while this may be what a
TA sets out to do, in practice it only refutes a particular competitor
of the conceptual scheme that it is trying to estab-lish. So, for
example, Strawson’s argument—that in order to re-identify particulars we
must have an objectivity condition—proceeds by refuting the sense datum
hypothesis. But notice that the sense datum hypothesis is simply one
version of the negation of the objectivity condition (the
“non-objectivity condition”). In refuting a particular
version of this
“non-objectivity condition,” Straw-son intends to refute the
“non-objectivity condi-tion” in general. In other words, the refutation
of one version of the “non-objectivity condition” is meant to show that
all versions of such a condition are reducible to absurdity. Of course
one may argue that in refuting the sense datum hypothe-sis Strawson is
only showing a problem intrinsic to it and not the “non-objectivity
condition” in gener-al. But in order to make this objection work, an
argument must be provided by the skeptic to show that this is indeed the
case. If no such argument is provided (and it is difficult to image
what such an argument would look like), the refutation of one particular
version of the “non-objectivity condi-tion” should is nothing less than a
refutation of “non-objectivity condition” in general. And be-cause the
“non-objectivity condition” is the nega-tion of the objectivity
condition, a refutation of the former provides a proof for the
latter.[86]
Notes
[41] In Metaphysics
(v. 1061a 5-1062b) Aristotle demonstrates the transcendental necessity
of the law of contradiction.
[42] Individuals: An
Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Methuen & Co., Ltd.,
1959).
[43] It should be noted
at the outset that some philosophers argue that there is nothing at all
distinctive about TAs. Moltke Gram is, perhaps, the leading advocate of
this view. The following articles by Gram are representative:
“Transcendental Ar-guments,” Noûs, vol. 5, no. 1 (February 1971),
15-26, “Must We Revisit Transcendental Arguments?” Philosophical
Studies 31 (1977), 235-248. Gram’s arguments, however, have not
been persuasive to most commentators on TAs.
[44] See T. E.
Wilkerson, “Transcendental Argu-ments,” Philosophical Quarterly 20
(1970), 200-212 and Ralph C. S. Walker, Kant: The Arguments of the
Philosophers (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978) for insightful
discussions of the logic of TAs.
[45] The Refutation
of Skepticism (London: Duck-worth, 1985), 94.
[46]
Michael Dummett denies that there is (was) such a school. Assuming he
is correct, the name is still useful and in this context innocuous. See
his “Oxford Philosophy” in Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1978), pp. 431-436.
[47] “Transcendental
Argument” in Robert Audi, ed., The Cambridge Dictionary
of Philosophy, 2nd ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 925.
[48] “Transcendental
Arguments” in Jona-than Dancy and Ernest Sosa, eds., A Companion to
Epistemology (Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd., 1992), 507.
[49] “Transcendental
Arguments” in Edward Craig, ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
vol. 9 (New York: Routledge, 1998) 452.
[50] Barry Stroud,
“Transcendental Argu-ments,” Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968),
241-256.
[51] Even a cursory
reading of the Critique makes this clear. In the very beginning
remarks of the Introduction to the second edition Kant states: “But
though all our knowledge begins with experi-ence, it does not follow that
it all arises out of experience. For it may well be that even our
empirical knowledge is made up of what we receive through impressions
and of what our own faculty of knowledge (sensible impressions serving
merely as the occasion) supplies from itself” (B 1).
[52] Although some of
the debate is indeed trivial. For although Kant made the term a
technical one and, thus, must be conceded a certain propriety over it,
philosophers should be more concerned with the success and failures of
the arguments at hand rather than lexicographical
particularities—Johnson, after all, was modest enough to call himself a
harmless drudge.
[53] Although Kant never
actually used the term “transcendental argument”; his closest term is
“Transzendentalen Deduktion”.
[54] “Transcendental
Arguments: Genuine and Spurious,” Noûs, Vol. 6 (1972), p. 274.
[55]
“Atemporal Necessities of Thought; or, How Not to Bury Philosophy in
History,” Reading Kant: New Perspectives on Transcendental Arguments
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), p. 42.
[56] All references from
the Critique of Pure Reason are from Norman Kemp Smith, trans.
(New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1965).
[57] Prolegomena,
p. 294 (Academy edition). Cited in Jaakko Hintikka, “Transcendental
Arguments: Genuine and Spurious,” Noûs, Vol. 6 (1972), p. 275.
[58] Hintikka, 275.
[59] For slightly
different reasons, David Bell also considers it a mistake to view The
Refutation as a transcendental argument. See his “Transcendental
Arguments and Non-Naturalistic Anti-Realism,” in Robert Stern, ed., Transcendental
Arguments: Problems and Prospects (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999),
189-210.
[60] The Refutation
of Scepticism, 80.
[61] Grayling
misleadingly paraphrases this phrase as “mere ‘mode of origination.’”
Grayling, The Refutation of Scepticism, 80.
[62] Graham Bird is one
of the few who makes his commitment to this practice explicit. “Kant’s
Tran-scendental Arguments,” in Eva Schaper and Wil-helm Vossenhuhl, eds.,
Reading Kant (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989).
[63] Perhaps the most
famous example of this is found in Strawson’s misreading of the
Deduction in his The Bounds of Sense (London: Methuen, 1966).
[64] By ‘clarity’ I mean
that it is clear what Kant intended the goal of transcendental proofs to
be. I do not mean that it is at all clear how Kant actually goes about
doing it.
[65] “Transcendental
Arguments and Scepticism,” in Schaper and Vossenkuhl, eds., Reading
Kant, p. 56.
[66] Gottlob Frege,
“Thoughts,” in Logical Investi-gations, P. T. Geach, ed. and
trans. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977); Ludwig Wittgen-stein, Philosophical
Investigations, trans. by G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell,
1958); Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984); Hilary Putnam, Reason,
Truth, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981);
John R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London:
Penguin, 1995).
[67] The Bounds of
Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (London: Methuen,
1966).
[68] Individuals,
35.
[69] Individuals,
p. 35.
[70] Strawson has since
changed his mind. See his Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1985).
[71] Journal of
Philosophy 65 (1968), 241-56.
[72] In a fascinating
study of early Post-Kantian-ism, Paul Franks shows that Gottlob Schulze
offered a similar objection to Kant and his K. L. Reinhold in his Aenesidemus
(1792). “Transcen-dental Arguments, Reason, and Scepticism:
Con-temporary Debates and the Origins of Post-Kantianism,” in Stern,
ed., Transcendental Argu-ments, 111-45.
[73] Categorial Frameworks
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1974), 72. Quoted in Eckart Førster, “How Are Transcendental
Arguments Possible?” in Schaper and Vossekuhl, 15. Roderick Chisholm’s
strictures on TAs are similar to Körner’s. See his “What Is a
Transcendental Argument?” in The Foundations of Knowing
(Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 98. Originally
published in Neue Hefte für Philosophie 14:
19-22.
[74] “The Impossibility
of Transcendental Deduc-tions,” The Monist, 51 (1967), 320-21.
[75] Richard Rorty,
“Transcendental Arguments, Self-Reference, and Pragmatism,” in P. Bieri,
R.-P. Horstmann, and L. Kròger, eds. Transcendental Arguments and
Science (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Pub-lishing Co., 1979), 82.
[76] A. Phillips
Griffiths, “Transcendental Argu-ments,” Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, suppl. Vol. 43 (1969), 171.
[77] Eva Schaper,
“Arguing Transcendentally,” Kantstudien, 63 (1972), 107.
[78]
Richard Rorty actually tackles the second horn. He agrees with
Stroud that a verification principle is necessary, but not the
empiricist kind that Stroud actually tackles the second horn. He agrees with Stroud
that a verification principle is necessary, but not the empiricist kind
that Stroud maintains. Rorty argues that this empiricist form
of verificationism is not only dubious, but demon-strably false. TAs
that rely on such a principle are therefore directly refuted. However,
Rorty main-tains that a Peircean form of verification (to know the
meaning of a term is to know inferential rela-tions), is not obviously
false and can do the requi-site work of answering the
skeptic. But this answer to the skeptic takes us no further that
Stroud. It merely shows that the skeptic must assume the truth of our
conceptual scheme in order to call it into question. But this, of
course, does not estab-lish anything about the way the world is. Richard
Rorty,
“Verificationism and
Transcendental Argu-ment,” Noûs,
Vol. 5, n. 1, (February 1971), 3-14. See Anthony Brueckner,
“Transcendental Ar-guments I,” Noûs, 17 (November, 1983), 551-575
for a trenchant criticism of Rorty.
[79] “Kantian Argument,
Conceptual Capacities, and Invulnerability,” in Paulo Parrini, ed.,
Kant and Contemporary Epistemology (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994).
[80] Stroud, “Kantian
Argument,” 234 quoted in Stern, ed., Transcendental Arguments, 7.
[81] Bernard Williams
suggests that both Kant and contemporary philosophers who employ TAs
impli-citly assume some form of idealism. See his
Prob-lems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
[82] This move is the
most common in the TA lite-rature. See, for example, Peter Hacker, “Are
Tran-scendental Arguments a Version of Verification-ism?” American
Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 9, No. 1 (January 1972), 78-85;
Eckart Førster, “How are Transcendental Arguments Possible? in Reading
Kant, 3-20, Ralph C. S. Walker, “Induction and Transcendental
Argument,” in Stern, ed., Transcen-dental Arguments, 13-29, Robert
Stern, “On Kant’s Response to Hume: The Second Analogy as Tran-scendental
Argument,” also in Stern, 47-66.
[83] Schaper, “Arguing
Transcendentally,” 107-8. Interestingly, Schaper thinks that this type
of proof is the only one possible.
[84] “On the Very Idea
of a Conceptual Scheme,” in Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and
Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), 183-198.
[85] Førster, ”How Are
Transcendental Arguments Possible?,” 15.
[86] The example in this
paragraph is due to Førster.
Next
IV. TAG Again and V. Conclusion
Beginning of Article and Table of Contents