From
Science, 21 August 1970, Vol. 169, 733-738. Reprinted in 1977 Studies in Social
Theory, No. 3 by the Institute for Humane Studies,
Menlo Park,
CA. See the sketch of Professor Carneiro at the end of
this post.
While I
favor coercive to voluntaristic theories of the rise of the state, I post
this monograph not because I “endorse” its thesis—I lack the requisite
expertise—but for the light Professor Carneiro sheds on the problem every
libertarian must ponder so that any future libertarian victory will not be
reversed by the state’s re-emergence. Born in aggressive war, the state
can no more incline men to compete peacefully over scarce resources than a
glass of whiskey can incline an alcoholic to forego it for a glass of
water. The fundamental choice to cooperate rather than aggress,
however,
seems to
presuppose a certain moral conversion.
Anthony
Flood
Posted
March 20, 2008
A Theory
of the Origin of the State
Robert L. Carneiro
For the first 2 million
years of his existence, man lived in bands or villages which, as far as we
can tell, were completely autonomous. Not until perhaps 5000 B.C. did
villages begin to aggregate into larger political units. But, once this
process of aggregation began, it continued at a progressively faster pace
and led, around 4000 B.C., to the formation of the first state in history.
(When I speak of a state I mean an autonomous political unit,
encompassing many communities within its territory and having a
centralized government with the power to collect taxes, draft men for work
or war, and decree and enforce laws.) Although it was by all odds the
most far-reaching political development in human history, the origin of
the state is still very imperfectly understood. Indeed, not one of the
current theories of the rise of the state is entirely satisfactory. At
one point or another, all of them fail. There is one theory, though,
which I believe does provide a convincing explanation of how states began.
It is a theory which I proposed once before1,
and which I present here more fully. Before doing so, however, it seems
desirable to discuss, if only briefly, a few of the traditional theories.
Explicit theories of
the origin of the state are relatively modern. Classical writers like
Aristotle, unfamiliar with other forms of political organization, tended
to think of the state as “natural,” and therefore as not requiring an
explanation. However, the age of exploration, by making Europeans aware
that many peoples throughout the world lived, not in states, but in
independent villages or tribes, made the state seem less natural, and thus
more in need of explanation.
Of the many modern
theories of state origins that have been proposed, we can consider only a
few. Those with a racial basis. for example, are now so thoroughly
discredited that they need not be dealt with here. We can also reject the
belief that the state is an expression of the “genius” of a people2,
or that it arose through a “historical accident.” Such notions make the
state appear to be something metaphysical or adventitious, and thus place
it beyond scientific understanding. In my opinion, the origin of the
state was neither mysterious nor fortuitous. It was not the product of
“genius” or the result of chance, but the outcome of a regular and
determinate cultural process. Moreover, it was not a unique event but a
recurring phenomenon: states arose independently in different places and
at different times. Where the appropriate conditions existed, the state
emerged.
Voluntaristic Theories
Serious theories of
state origins are of two general types: voluntaristic and
coercive. Voluntaristic theories hold that, at some point in their
history, certain peoples spontaneously, rationally, and voluntarily gave
up their individual sovereignties and united with other communities to
form a larger political unit deserving to be called a state. Of such
theories the best known is the old Social Contract theory, which was
associated especially with the name of Rousseau. We now know that no such
compact was ever subscribed to by human groups, and the Social Contract
theory is today nothing more than a historical curiosity.
The most widely
accepted of modern voluntaristic theories is the one I call the
“automatic” theory. According to this theory, the invention of
agriculture automatically brought into being a surplus of food, enabling
some individuals to divorce themselves from food production and to become
potters, weavers, smiths, masons, and so on, thus creating an extensive
division of labor. Out of this occupational specialization there developed
a political integration which united a number of previously independent
communities into a state. This argument was set forth most frequently by
the late British archeologist V. Gordon Childe.3
The principal
difficulty with this theory is that agriculture does not
automatically create a food surplus. We know this because many
agricultural peoples of the world produce no such surplus. Virtually all
Amazonian Indians, for example, were agricultural, but in aboriginal times
they did not produce a food surplus. That it was technically feasible
for them to produce such a surplus is shown by the fact that, under
the stimulus of European settlers’ desire for food, a number of tribes did
raise manioc in amounts well above their own needs, for the purpose of
trading.4 Thus the
technical means for generating a food surplus were there; it was the
social mechanisms needed to actualize it that were lacking.
Another current
voluntaristic theory of state origins is Karl Wittfogel’s “hydraulic
hypothesis.” As I understand him, Wittfogel sees the state arising in the
following way. In certain arid and semi-arid areas of the world, where
village farmers had to struggle to support themselves by means of
small-scale irrigation, a time arrived when they saw that it would be to
the advantage of all concerned to set aside their individual autonomies
and merge their villages into a single large political unit capable of
carrying out irrigation on a broad scale. The body of officials they
created to devise and administer such extensive irrigation works brought
the state into being.5
This theory has
recently run into difficulties. Archeological evidence now makes it
appear that in at least three of the areas that Wittfogel cites as
exemplifying his “hydraulic hypothesis”—Mesopotamia, China, and
Mexico—full-fledged states developed well before large-scale irrigation.6
Thus, irrigation did not play the causal role in the rise of the state
that Wittfogel appears to attribute to it.7
This and all other
voluntaristic theories of the rise of the state founder on the same rock:
the demonstrated inability of autonomous political units to relinquish
their sovereignty in the absence of overriding external constraints. We
see this inability manifested again and again by political units ranging
from tiny villages to great empires. Indeed, one can scan the pages of
history without finding a single genuine exception to this rule. Thus, in
order to account for the origin of the state we must set aside
voluntaristic theories and look elsewhere.
Coercive
Theories
A close examination of
history indicates that only a coercive theory can account for the rise of
the state. Force, and not enlightened self-interest, is the mechanism by
which political evolution has led, step by step, from autonomous villages
to the state.
The view that war lies
at the root of the state is by no means new. Twenty-five hundred years
ago Heraclitus wrote that “war is the father of all things.” The first
careful study of the role of warfare in the rise of the state, however,
was made less than a hundred years ago, by Herbert Spencer in his
Principles of Sociology.8
Perhaps better known than Spencer’s writings on war and the state are the
conquest theories of continental writers such as Ludwig Gumplowicz9,
Gustav Ratzenhofer10, and
Franz Oppenheimer.11
Oppenheimer, for
example, argued that the state emerged when the productive capacity of
settled agriculturists was combined with the energy of pastoral nomads
through the conquest of the former by the latter11
(pp. 51-55). This theory, however, has two serious defects. First, it
fails to account for the rise of states in aboriginal
America, where pastoral nomadism was unknown. Second, it is now well
established that pastoral nomadism did not arise in the
Old World
until after the earliest states had emerged.
Regardless of
deficiencies in particular coercive theories, however, there is little
question that, in one way or another, war played a decisive role in the
rise of the state. Historical or archeological evidence of war is found
in the early stages of state formation in Mesopotamia, Egypt, India,
China, Japan, Greece, Rome, northern Europe, central Africa, Polynesia,
Middle America, Peru, and Colombia, to name only the most prominent
examples.
Thus, with the Germanic
kingdoms of northern Europe especially in mind, Edward Jenks observed
that, “historically speaking, there is not the slightest difficulty in
proving that all political communities of the modern type [that is,
states] owe their existence to successful warfare.”12
And in reading Jan Vansina’s Kingdoms of the Savanna13,
a book with no theoretical ax to grind, one finds that state after state
in central Africa rose in the same manner.
But is it really true
that there is no exception to this rule? Might there not be, somewhere in
the world, an example of a state which arose without the agency of war?
Until a few years ago,
anthropologists generally believed that the Classic Maya provided such an
instance. The archeological evidence then available gave no hint of
warfare among the early Maya and led scholars to regard them as a
peace-loving theocratic state which had arisen entirely without war.14
However, this view is no longer tenable. Recent archeological
discoveries have placed the Classic Maya in a very different light. First
came the discovery of the
Bonampak
murals, showing the early Maya at war and reveling in the torture of war
captives. Then, excavations around Tikal revealed large earthworks partly
surrounding that Classic Maya city, pointing clearly to a military rivalry
with the neighboring city of Uaxactun.15
Summarizing present thinking on the subject, Michael D. Coe
has observed that “the ancient Maya were just as warlike as the. . .
bloodthirsty states of the Post-Classic.”16
Yet, though warfare is
surely a prime mover in the origin of the state, it cannot be the only
factor. After all, wars have been fought in many parts of the world where
the state never emerged. Thus, while warfare may be a necessary condition
for the rise of the state, it is not a sufficient one. Or, to put it
another way, while we can identify war as the mechanism of state
formation, we need also to specify the conditions under which it gave rise
to the state.
Environmental Circumscription
How are we to determine
these conditions? One promising approach is to look for those factors
common to areas of the world in which states arose indigenously—areas such
as the Nile,
Tigris-Euphrates, and
Indus
valleys in the
Old World
and the Valley of
Mexico and
the mountain and coastal valleys of
Peru in the
New. These areas differ from one another in many ways—in altitude,
temperature, rainfall, soil type, drainage pattern, and many other
features. They do, however, have one thing in common: they are all areas
of circumscribed agricultural land. Each of them is set off by mountains,
seas, or deserts, and these environmental features sharply delimit the
area that simple farming peoples could occupy and cultivate. In this
respect these areas are very different from, say, the Amazon basin or the
eastern woodlands of
North America,
where extensive and unbroken forests provided almost unlimited
agricultural land.
But what is the
significance of circumscribed agricultural land for the origin of the
state? Its significance can best be understood by comparing political
development in two regions of the world having contrasting ecologies—one a
region with circumscribed agricultural land and the other a region where
there was extensive and unlimited land. The two areas I have chosen to
use in making this comparison are the coastal valleys of
Peru and
the Amazon basin.
Our examination begins
at the stage where agricultural communities were already present but where
each was still completely autonomous. Looking first at the Amazon basin,
we see that agricultural villages there were numerous, but widely
dispersed. Even in areas with relatively dense clustering, like the Upper
Xingu basin, villages were at least 10 or 15 miles apart. Thus, the typical
Amazonian community, even though it practiced a simple form of shifting
cultivation which required extensive amounts of land, still had around it
all the forest land needed for its gardens.17
For Amazonia as a whole, then, population density was low and
subsistence pressure on the land was slight.
Warfare was certainly
frequent in Amazonia, but it was waged for reasons of revenge, the taking of women, the
gaining of personal prestige, and motives of a similar sort. There being
no shortage of land, there was, by and large, no warfare over land.
The consequences of the
type of warfare that did occur in
Amazonia
were as follows. A defeated group was not, as a rule, driven from its
land. Nor did the victor make any real effort to subject the vanquished,
or to exact tribute from him. This would have been difficult to
accomplish in any case, since there was no effective way to prevent the
losers from fleeing to a distant part of the forest. Indeed, defeated
villages often chose to do just this, not so much to avoid subjugation as
to avoid further attack. With settlement so sparse in
Amazonia, a
new area of forest could be found and occupied with relative ease, and
without trespassing on the territory of another village. Moreover, since
virtually any area of forest is suitable for cultivation, subsistence
agriculture could be carried on in the new habitat just about as well as
in the old.
It was apparently by
this process of fight and flight that horticultural tribes gradually
spread out until they came to cover, thinly but extensively, almost the
entire Amazon basin. Thus, under the conditions of unlimited agricultural
land and low population density that prevailed in
Amazonia,
the effect of warfare was to disperse villages over a wide area, and to
keep them autonomous. With only a very few exceptions, noted below, there
was no tendency in Amazonia for villages to be held in place and to combine into larger political
units.
In marked contrast to
the situation in Amazonia were the events that transpired in the narrow valleys of the Peruvian
coast. The reconstruction of these events that I present is admittedly
inferential, but I think it is consistent with the archeological evidence.
Here too our account
begins at the stage of small, dispersed, and autonomous farming
communities. However, instead of being scattered over a vast expanse of
rain forest as they were in Amazonia, villages here were confined to some
78 short and narrow valleys.18
Each of these valleys, moreover, was backed by the mountains, fronted by
the sea, and flanked on either side by desert as dry as any in the world.
Nowhere else, perhaps, can one find agricultural valleys more sharply
circumscribed than these.
As with neolithic
communities generally, villages of the Peruvian coastal valleys tended to
grow in size. Since autonomous villages are likely to fission as they
grow, as long as land is available for the settlement of splinter
communities, these villages undoubtedly split from time to time.19
Thus, villages tended to increase in number faster than they grew in
size. This increase in the number of villages occupying a valley probably
continued, without giving rise to significant changes in subsistence
practices, until all the readily arable land in the valley was being
farmed.
At this point two
changes in agricultural techniques began to occur: the tilling of land
already under cultivation was intensified, and new, previously unusable
land was brought under cultivation by means of terracing and irrigation .20
Yet the rate at which
new arable land was created failed to keep pace with the increasing demand
for it. Even before the land shortage became so acute that irrigation
began to be practiced systematically, villages were undoubtedly already
fighting one another over land. Prior to this time, when agricultural
villages were still few in number and well supplied with land, the warfare
waged in the coastal valleys of Peru had probably been of much the same
type as that described above for Amazonia. With increasing pressure of
human population on the land, however, the major incentive for war changed
from a desire for revenge to a need to acquire land. And, as the causes
of war became predominantly economic, the frequency, intensity, and
importance of war increased.
Once this stage was
reached, a Peruvian village that lost a war faced consequences very
different from those faced by a defeated village in
Amazonia.
There, as we have seen, the vanquished could flee to a new locale,
subsisting there about as well as they had subsisted before, and retaining
their independence. In
Peru,
however, this alternative was no longer open to the inhabitants of
defeated villages. The mountains, the desert, and the sea—to say nothing
of neighboring villages—blocked escape in every direction. A village
defeated in war thus faced only grim prospects. If it was allowed to
remain on its own land, instead of being exterminated or expelled, this
concession came only at a price. And the price was political
subordination to the victor. This subordination generally entailed at
least the payment of a tribute or tax in kind, which the defeated village
could provide only by producing more food than it had produced before.
But subordination sometimes involved a further loss of autonomy on the
part of the defeated village namely, incorporation into the political unit
dominated by the victor.
Through the recurrence
of warfare of this type, we see arising in coastal
Peru
integrated territorial units transcending the village in size and in
degree of organization. Political evolution was attaining the level of
the chiefdom.
As land shortages
continued and became even more acute, so did warfare. Now, however, the
competing units were no longer small villages but, often, large chiefdoms.
From this point on, through the conquest of chiefdom by chiefdom, the
size of political units increased at a progressively faster rate.
Naturally, as autonomous political units increased in size, they
decreased in number, with the result that an entire valley was eventually
unified under the banner of its strongest chiefdom. The political unit
thus formed was undoubtedly sufficiently centralized and complex to
warrant being called a state.
The political evolution
I have described for one valley of Peru was also taking place in other
valleys, in the highlands as well as on the coast.21
Once valley-wide kingdoms emerged, the next step was the formation of
multi-valley kingdoms through the conquest of weaker valleys by stronger
ones. The culmination of this process was the conquest22
of all of Peru by its
most powerful state, and the formation of a single great empire. Although
this step may have occurred once or twice before in Andean history, it was
achieved most notably, and for the last time, by the Incas.23
Political
Evolution
While the aggregation
of villages into chiefdoms, and of chiefdoms into kingdoms, was occurring
by external acquisition, the structure of these increasingly larger
political units was being elaborated by internal evolution. These inner
changes were, of course, closely related to outer events. The expansion
of successful states brought within their borders conquered peoples and
territory which had to be administered. And it was the individuals who
had distinguished themselves in war who were generally appointed to
political office and assigned the task of carrying out this
administration. Besides maintaining law and order and collecting taxes,
the functions of this burgeoning class of administrators included
mobilizing labor for building irrigation works, roads, fortresses,
palaces, and temples. Thus, their functions helped to weld an assorted
collection of petty states into a single integrated and centralized
political unit.
These same individuals,
who owed their improved social position to their exploits in war, became,
along with the ruler and his kinsmen, the nucleus of an upper class. A
lower class in turn emerged from the prisoners taken in war and employed
as servants and slaves by their captors. In this manner did war
contribute to the rise of social classes.
I noted earlier that
peoples attempt to acquire their neighbors’ land before they have made the
fullest possible use of their own. This implies that every autonomous
village has an untapped margin of food productivity, and that this margin
is squeezed out only when the village is subjugated and compelled to pay
taxes in kind. The surplus food extracted from conquered villages through
taxation, which in the aggregate attained very significant proportions,
went largely to support the ruler, his warriors and retainers, officials,
priests, and other members of the rising upper class, who thus became
completely divorced from food production.
Finally, those made
landless by war but not enslaved tended to gravitate to settlements which,
because of their specialized administrative, commercial, or religious
functions, were growing into towns and cities. Here they were able to make
a living as workers and artisans, exchanging their labor or their wares
for part of the economic surplus exacted from village farmers by the
ruling class and spent by members of that class to raise their standard of
living.
The process of
political evolution which I have outlined for the coastal valleys of
Peru was,
in its essential features, by no means unique to this region. Areas of
circumscribed agricultural land elsewhere in the world, such as the
Valley of
Mexico,
Mesopotamia,
the Nile
Valley, and
the Indus
Valley, saw
the process occur in much the same way and for essentially the same
reasons. In these areas, too, autonomous neolithic villages were
succeeded by chiefdoms, chiefdoms by kingdoms, and kingdoms by empires.
The last stage of this development was, of course, the most impressive.
The scale and magnificence attained by the early empires overshadowed
everything that had gone before. But, in a sense, empires were merely the
logical culmination of the process. The really fundamental step, the one
that had triggered the entire train of events that led to empires, was the
change from village autonomy to supravillage integration. This step was a
change in kind; everything that followed was, in a way, only a change in
degree.
In addition to being
pivotal, the step to supracommunity aggregation was difficult, for it took
2 million years to achieve. But, once it was achieved, once village
autonomy was transcended, only two or three millennia were required for
the rise of great empires and the flourishing of complex civilizations.
Resource
Concentration
Theories are first
formulated on the basis of a limited number of facts. Eventually, though,
a theory must confront all of the facts. And often new facts are stubborn
and do not conform to the theory, or do not conform very well. What
distinguishes a successful theory from an unsuccessful one is that it can
be modified or elaborated to accommodate the entire range of facts. Let
us see how well the “circumscription theory” holds up when it is brought
face-to-face with certain facts that appear to be exceptions.
For the first test let
us return to Amazonia. Early voyagers down the Amazon left written testimony of a culture
along that river higher than the culture I have described for
Amazonia generally. In the 1500’s, the native population living on the banks
of the Amazon was relatively dense, villages were fairly large and close
together, and some degree of social stratification existed. Moreover,
here and there a paramount chief held sway over many communities.
The question
immediately arises: with unbroken stretches of arable land extending back
from the Amazon for hundreds of miles, why were there chiefdoms here?
To answer the question
we must look closely at the environmental conditions afforded by the
Amazon. Along the margins of the river itself, and on islands within it,
there is a type of land called várzea. The river floods this land
every year, covering it with a layer of fertile silt. Because of this
annual replenishment, várzea is agricultural land of first quality
which can be cultivated year after year without ever having to lie fallow.
Thus, among native farmers it was highly priced and greatly coveted. The
waters of the Amazon were also extraordinarily bountiful, providing fish,
manatees, turtles and turtle eggs, caimans, and other riverine foods in
inexhaustible amounts. By virtue of this concentration of resources, the
Amazon, as a habitat, was distinctly superior to its hinterlands.
Concentration of
resources along the Amazon amounted almost to a kind of circumscription.
While there was no sharp cleavage between productive and unproductive
land, as there was in
Peru, there
was at least a steep ecological gradient. So much more rewarding was the
Amazon River than adjacent areas, and so desirable did it become as a habitat, that
people were drawn to it from surrounding regions. Eventually crowding
occurred along many portions of the river, leading to warfare over
sections of river front. And the losers in war, in order to retain access
to the river, often had no choice but to submit to the victors. By this
subordination of villages to a paramount chief there arose along the
Amazon chiefdoms representing a higher step in political evolution than
had occurred elsewhere in the basin.24
The notion of resource
concentration also helps to explain the surprising degree of political
development apparently attained by peoples of the Peruvian coast while
they were still depending primarily on fishing for subsistence, and only
secondarily on agriculture.18
Of this seeming anomaly Lanning has written: “To the best of my
knowledge, this is the only case in which so many of the characteristics
of civilization have been found without a basically agricultural economic
foundation.”25
Armed with the concept
of resource concentration, however, we can show that this development was
not so anomalous after all. The explanation, it seems to me, runs as
follows. Along the coast of
Peru wild
food sources occurred in considerable number and variety. However, they
were restricted to a very narrow margin of land.26
Accordingly, while the abundance of food in this zone led to
a sharp rise in population, the restrictedness of this food soon resulted
in the almost complete occupation of exploitable areas. And when pressure
on the available resources reached a critical level, competition over land
ensued. The result of this competition was to set in motion the sequence
of events of political evolution that I have described.
Thus, it seems that we
can safely add resource concentration to environmental circumscription as
a factor leading to warfare over land, and thus to political integration
beyond the village level.
Social
Circumscription
But there is still
another factor to be considered in accounting for the rise of the state.
In dealing with the
theory of environmental circumscription while discussing the Yanomamö
Indians of Venezuela, Napoleon A. Chagnon27
has introduced the concept of “social circumscription.” By this he means
that a high density of population in an area can produce effects on
peoples living near the center of the area that are similar to effects
produced by environmental circumscription. This notion seems to me to be
an important addition to our theory. Let us see how, according to Chagnon,
social circumscription has operated among the Yanomamö.
The Yanomamö, who
number some 10,000, live in an extensive region of noncircumscribed rain
forest, away from any large river. One might expect that Yanomamö
villages would thus be more or less evenly spaced. However, Chagnon notes
that, at the center of Yanomamö territory, villages are closer together
than they are at the periphery. Because of this, they tend to impinge on
one another more, with the result that warfare is more frequent and
intense in the center than in peripheral areas. Moreover, it is more
difficult for villages in the nuclear area to escape attack by moving
away, since, unlike villages on the periphery, their ability to move is
somewhat restricted.
The net result is that
villages in the central area of Yanomamö territory are larger than
villages in the other areas, since large village size is an advantage for
both attack and defense. A further effect of more intense warfare in the
nuclear area is that village headmen are stronger in that area. Yanomamö
headmen are also the war leaders, and their influence increases in
proportion to their village’s participation in war. In addition,
offensive and defensive alliances between villages are more common in the
center of Yanomamö territory than in outlying areas. Thus, while still at
the autonomous village level of political organization, those Yanomamö
subject to social circumscription have clearly moved a step or two in the
direction of higher political development.
Although the Yanomamö
manifest social circumscription only to a modest degree, this amount of it
has been enough to make a difference in their level of political
organization. What the effects of social circumscription would be in
areas where it was more fully expressed should, therefore, be clear.
First would come a reduction in the size of the territory of each
village. Then, as population pressure became more severe, warfare over
land would ensue. But because adjacent land for miles around was already
the property of other villages, a defeated village would have nowhere to
flee. From this point on, the consequences of warfare for that village,
and for political evolution in general, would be essentially as I have
described them for the situation of environmental circumscription.
To return to
Amazonia, it
is clear that, if social circumscription is operative among the Yanomamö
today, it was certainly operative among the tribes of the Amazon River 400 years ago. And its effect would undoubtedly have been to give a
further spur to political evolution in that region.
We see then that, even
in the absence of sharp environmental circumscription, the factors of
resource concentration and social circumscription may, by intensifying war
and redirecting it toward the taking of land, give a strong impetus to
political development.
With these auxiliary
hypotheses incorporated into it, the circumscription theory is now better
able to confront the entire range of test cases that can be brought before
it. For example, it can now account for the rise of the state in the
Hwang Valley of northern China, and even in the Petén region of the Maya
lowlands, areas not characterized by strictly circumscribed agricultural
land. In the case of the
Hwang
Valley,
there is no question that resource concentration and social
circumscription were present and active forces. In the lowland Maya area,
resource concentration seems not to have been a major factor, but social
circumscription may well have been.
Some archeologists may
object that population density in the Petén during formative times was too
low to give rise to social circumscription. But, in assessing what
constitutes a population dense enough to produce this effect, we must
consider not so much the total land area occupied as the amount of land
needed to support the existing population. And the size of this
supporting area depends not only on the size of the population but also on
the mode of subsistence. The shifting cultivation presumably practiced by
the ancient Maya28 required
considerably more land, per capita, than did the permanent field
cultivation of, say, the valley of Mexico or the coast of Peru.29
Consequently, insofar as its effects are concerned, a relatively low
population density in the Petén may have been equivalent to a much higher
one in Mexico or Peru.
We have already learned
from the Yanomamö example that social circumscription may begin to operate
while population is still relatively sparse. And we can be sure that the
Petén was far more densely peopled in Formative times than Yanomamö
territory is today. Thus, population density among the lowland Maya,
while giving a superficial appearance of sparseness, may actually have
been high enough to provoke fighting over land, and thus provide the
initial impetus for the formation of a state.
Conclusion
In summary, then, the
circumscription theory in its elaborated form goes far toward accounting
for the origin of the state. It explains why states arose where they did,
and why they failed to arise elsewhere. It shows the state to be a
predictable response to certain specific cultural, demographic, and
ecological conditions. Thus, it helps to elucidate what was undoubtedly
the most important single step ever taken in the political evolution of
mankind.
NOTES
1 R. L. Carneiro, in The Evolution of Horticultural Systems in Native
South America: Causes and Consequences: A Symposium, J. Wilbert, Ed.,
Antropológica (Venezuela), Suppl. 2 (1961), pp. 47-67, see
especially pp. 59-64.
2 For example, the early American sociologist Lester F. Ward saw the
state as “the result of an extraordinary exercise of the rational. . .
faculty” which seemed to him so exceptional that “it must have been the
emanation of a single brain or a few concerting minds.” [Dynamic
Sociology (Appleton, New York, 1883), vol. 2, p. 224].
3 See, for example, V. G. Childe, Man Makes Himself (Watts,
London, 1936) pp. 82-83; Town Planning Rev. 21, 3 (1950), p. 6.
4 I have in my files recorded instances of surplus food production by
such Amazonian tribes as the Tupinamba, Jevero, Mundurucu, Tucano, Desana,
Cubeo, and Canela. An exhaustive search of the ethnographic literature
for this region would undoubtedly reveal many more examples.
5 Wittfogel states: “These patterns [of organization and social
control—that is, the state] come into being when an experimenting
community of farmers or protofarmers finds large sources of moisture in a
dry but potentially fertile area. . . . a number of farmers eager to
conquer [agriculturally, not militarily] arid lowlands and plains are
forced to invoke the organizational devices which—on the basis of
premachine technology—offer the one chance of success: they must work in
cooperation with their fellows and subordinate themselves to a directing
authority.” [Oriental Despotism,
Yale Univ. Press, New
Haven, Conn., 1957), p. 18].
6 For Mesopotamia, Robert M. Adams has concluded: “In short, there is
nothing to suggest that the rise of dynastic authority in southern
Mesopotamia
was linked to the administrative requirements of a major canal system.”
[in City Invincible, C. H. Kraeling and R. M. Adams, Eds. (U niv.
of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1960), p. 281]. For China, the prototypical
area for Wittfogel’s hydraulic theories, the French Sinologist Jacques
Gernet has recently written: “although the establishment of a system of
regulation of water courses and irrigation, and the control of this
system, may have affected the political constitution of the military
states and imperial China, the fact remains that, historically, it was the
pre-existing state structures and the large, well-trained labour force
provided by the armies that made the great irrigation projects possible.”
[Ancient
China, from the
Beginnings to the Empire,
R. Rudorff, Transl. (Faber and Faber, London, 1968), p. 92]. For
Mexico, large-scale irrigation systems do not appear to antedate the Classic
period, whereas it is clear that the first states arose in the preceding
Formative or Pre-Classic period.
7 This is not to say, of course, that large-scale irrigation, where it
occurred, did not contribute significantly to increasing the power and
scope of the state. It unquestionably did. To the extent that Wittfogel
limits himself to this contention, I have no quarrel with him whatever.
However, the point at issue is not how the state increased its power but
how it arose in the first place. And to this issue the hydraulic
hypothesis does not appear to hold the key.
8 See The Evolution of Society: Selections from Herbert Spencer’s
Principles of Sociology, R. L. Carneiro, Ed. (Univ. of Chicago Press,
Chicago, 1967), pp. 32-47,63-96, 153-165.
9 L. Gumplowicz, Der Rassenkampf (Wagner, Innsbruck, 1883).
10 G. Ratzenhofer, Wesen und Zweck der Politik (Brockhaus, Leipsig,
1893).
11 F. Oppenheimer, The State, J. M. Gitterman, Transl. (Vanguard,
New York, 1926).
12 E. Jenks, A History of Politics (Macmillan, New York, 1900), p. 73.
13 J. Vansina, Kingdoms of the Savanna (Univ. of Wisconsin Press,
Madison, 1966).
14 For example, Julian H. Steward wrote: “It is possible, therefore, that
the Maya were able to develop a high civilization only because they
enjoyed an unusually long period of peace; for their settlement pattern
would seem to have been too vulnerable to warfare.” [Amer. Anthropol.
51, 1 (1949), see p. 17] .
15 D. E. Puleston and D. W. Callender, Expedition 9 No.3, 40
(1967), see pp. 45, 47.
16 M. D. Coe, The Maya (Praeger, New York, 1966), p. 147.
17 See R. L. Carneiro, in Men and Cultures. Selected Papers of the
Fifth International Congress of Anthropological and Ethnological Sciences,
A. F. C. Wallace, Ed. (Univ. of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, 1960),
pp. 229-234.
18 In early agricultural times (Preceramic Period VI, beginning about
2500 B.C.) human settlement seems to have been denser along the coast than
in the river valleys, and subsistence appears to have been based more on
fishing than on farming. Furthermore, some significant first steps in
political evolution beyond autonomous villages may have been taken at this
stage. However, once subsistence began to be based predominantly on
agriculture, the settlement pattern changed, and communities were
thenceforth concentrated more in the river valleys, where the only land of
any size suitable for cultivation was located. See E. P. Lanning,
Peru
Before the Incas (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1967), pp. 57-59.
19 In my files I find reported instances of village splitting among the
following Amazonian tribes: Kuikuru, Amarakaeri, Cubeo, Urubtl, Tupari,
Yanomamö, Tucano, Tenetehara, Canela, and
Northern Cayapo. Under the conditions of easy resettlement found in
Amazonia, splitting often takes place at a village population level of less
than 100, and village size seldom exceeds 200. In coastal Peru, however,
where land was severely restricted, villages could not fission so readily,
and thus grew to population levels which, according to Lanning [Peru
Before the Incas (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1967), p.
64], may have averaged over 300.
20 See R. L. Carneiro, Ethnograph.-archäol. Forschungen 4, 22
(1958).
21 Naturally, this evolution took place in the various Peruvian valleys
at different rates and to different degrees. In fact it is possible that
at the same time that some valleys were already unified politically,
others still had not evolved beyond the stage of autonomous villages.
22 Not every step in empire building was necessarily taken through actual
physical conquest, however. The threat of force sometimes had the same
effect as its exercise. In this way many smaller chiefdoms and states
were probably coerced into giving up their sovereignty without having to
be defeated on the field of battle. Indeed, it was an explicit policy of
the Incas, in expanding their empire, to try persuasion before resorting
to force of arms. See Garcilaso de la Vega, Royal Commentaries of the
Incas and General History of Peru, Part 1, H. V. Livermore, Transl.
(Univ. of Texas Press, Austin, 1966), pp. 108,
Ill, 140,
143, 146,264.
23 The evolution of empire in
Peru was
thus by no means rectilinear or irreversible. Advance alternated with
decline. Integration was sometimes followed by disintegration, with
states fragmenting back to chiefdoms, and perhaps even to autonomous
villages. But the forces underlying political development were strong
and, in the end, prevailed. Thus, despite fluctuations and reversions,
the course of evolution in
Peru was
unmistakable: it began with many small, simple, scattered, and autonomous
communities and ended with a single, vast, complex, and centralized
empire.
24 Actually, a similar political development did take place in another
part of Amazonia—the basin of the
Mamoré
River in
the Mojos plain of Bolivia. Here, too, resource concentration appears to
have played a key role. See W. Denevan, “The Aboriginal Cultural
Geography of the Llanos de Mojos of
Bolivia,” Ibero-americana No. 48 (1966), pp. 43-50, 104-105, 108-110.
In native North America north of Mexico the highest cultural development
attained, Middle-Mississippi, also occurred along a major river (the
Mississippi) which, by providing especially fertile soil and riverine food
resources, comprised a zone of resource concentration. See J. B. Griffin,
Science 156, 175 (1967), p. 189.
25 E. P. Lanning,
Peru
Before the Incas
(Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1967), p. 59.
26 Resource concentration, then, was here combined with environmental
circumscription. And, indeed, the same thing can be said of the great
desert river valleys, such as the
Nile,
Tigris-Euphrates, and
Indus.
27 N. A. Chagnon, Proceedings, VIIIth International Congress of
Anthropological and Ethnological Sciences (Tokyo and Kyoto, 1968),
vol. 3 (Ethnology and Archaeology), p. 249 (especially p. 251). See
also N. Fock, Folk 6, 47 (1964), p. 52.
28 S. G. Morley and G. W. Brainerd, The Ancient Maya (Stanford
Univ. Press, Stanford, Calif., ed. 3, 1956), pp. 128-129.
29 One can assume, I think, that any substantial increase in population
density among the Maya was accompanied by a certain intensification of
agriculture. As the population increased fields were probably weeded more
thoroughly, and they may well have been cultivated a year or two longer
and fallowed a few years less. Yet, given the nature of soils in the
humid tropics, the absence of any evidence of fertilization, and the
moderate population densities, it seems likely that Maya farming remained
extensive rather than becoming intensive.
“Born in
New York City on
June 4, 1927,
Robert Leonard Carneiro earned his Bachelor of Arts degree in Anthropology
in 1949 from the University of
Michigan and his Master’s degree in 1952. He earned his Ph.D. in
Anthropology in 1957 from the
University of
Michigan. At the
University of
Wisconsin, Carneiro served as a Professor from 1956 to 1957. From
1957 to 1969 he was the Assistant to the Associate Curator for South
American Ethnology. He also served as Assistant Curator (1957-1963),
Associate Curator (1963-1969) and Full Curator (1969-present) for the
American
Museum of Natural History. During this time, Carneiro held
concurrent positions as Visiting Professor at
Hunter
College from 1963 to 1964, at the
University of
California,
Los
Angeles in 1968, at the
University of
Victoria, and at
Pennsylvania
State
University in 1973. Carneiro is currently an Adjunct Professor at
Columbia
University. Carneiro is currently a member of the American
Anthropological Association, the American Ethnological Society, and the
Society for American Archaeology. He has also been elected to the
National
Academy of Sciences. His research consisted of cultural
evolution, including the reconstruction of sequences and the history of
evolutionism. Carneiro often conducted research on the origin and
development of the state. He suggested that states might emerge because
of population growth in an area that is physically or socially limited.
Carneiro illustrates his theory by describing how states may have emerged
on the northern coast of
Peru. He also researched the cultural ecology of
Amazonia, especially the effects of subsistence. He also helped
edit several volumes of Leslie A. White's Ethnological Essays.”
From the
Minnesota State University website.