From
Fortune, 29:6, June 1944, 165-167, 198, 201-202, 204, 206. A
black-and-white photographic portrait of Cassirer at work—a well-stocked
bookcase behind him, his eyes trained on the paper on which he is taking
notes, his left hand resting on an open tome of reference—fills page
164. (Fortune’s over-sized pages measured 10” x 13”.)
This
never-anthologized article is neither Cassirer’s book of the
same title (Yale University Press, 1946), nor his 1945 unpublished
lecture, “The Technique of Our Modern Political Myths,” anthologized in
Symbol, Myth, and Culture: Essays and Lectures of Ernst Cassirer,
1935-1945, ed. Donald Phillip Verene, Yale University Press, 1979,
with which it invites comparison. Charles W. Hendel, chairman of Yale’s
philosophy department when Cassirer taught there (1941-1944), narrates
its genesis:
. . . the
friends of Professor Cassirer looked to him as the man who could speak
with the wisest judgment [on the “crisis of world history”], since he
could interpret the situation of our time in the two greatest
perspectives of history and philosophy. Some of those who were close to
him ventured to ask: “Won’t you tell the meaning of what is happening
today, instead of writing about past history, science, and culture?
You have so much knowledge and wisdom—we who are working with you know
that so well—but you should give others, too, the benefit of it.” He
then set to work, in the winter of 1943-44, on a sketch of a book on the
theme “the myth of the state.” The magazine Fortune issued June,
1944, an abbreviated version of what he had so far written.
Foreword,
Ernst Cassirer, The Myth of the State, Yale University Press,
1946. The foreword is dated April 13, 1946, the anniversary of
Cassirer’s death.
As Hendel
recalled seven years later:
While
Cassirer was busy writing his new book, word of this enterprise was
quietly passed on to an editor of Fortune, Mr. Richardson Wood,
who saw the timely merit of it and proposed straightaway an essay on the
subject, which was very shortly published . . . . Before Cassirer could
finish the final revision of the book he was suddenly stricken fatally
in New York on April 13, 1945.
Preface,
Ernst Cassirer, The Philoso-phy of Symbolic Forms, Volume One:
Language, Yale University Press, 1953, xi.
I suspect
Fortune’s editor would have killed this article if he had grasped
what his invited author had made plain elsewhere: myth underpins
every regime, not just fascist ones. Copious evidence of American
mythology incongruously surrounds Cassirer’s analysis in the form of
wartime advertisements—virtually every one of them an imago sacra
for the edification of democracy’s faithful. Neither the word
“democracy” nor any of its cognates appears in the article. Only his
graciousness prevented him from applying his diagnosis to his host
country.
Anthony Flood
Posted September 9, 2008
The Myth of the
State
Ernst Cassirer
[The
article’s subtitle reads:] “Almost at the moment when political thinking
freed itself of illusions, it fell prey to myth. It can be rescued if
we have the courage to be wise.” [Two prefatory paragraphs, also
supplied by the editor, precede the article:]
For
generations men have labored to construct a science of politics, but the
twentieth century has seen politics stripped of its rationality and
clothed in the trappings of mindless myths. From these myths
totalitarianism springs. In the following article, Ernst Cassirer,
Research Professor of Philosophy at Yale University, illuminates the
great social issue of our century by tracing its backgrounds in men’s
ideas.
Dr.
Cassirer is particularly qualified to make such an analysis. He is not
only one of the greatest living philosophers, especially noted for his
work on symbolic forms, but one of the great philosophic historians, the
author of an extensive work on the history of the problem of knowledge
and of books on the Renaissance and enlightenment. Dr. Cassirer taught philosophy in Germany until the fateful year of 1933, when, the German
state falling a final prey to myth, he left the University of Hamburg
for England’s Oxford, Sweden’s University of Göteborg, and finally for
America’s Yale. In addition to his university duties, he has written an
Essay on Man, shortly to be published by the Yale University
Press, and is now working on The Myth of the State, the source of
the present article. The photograph opposite shows Dr. Cassirer in his
study.
In the intellectual history of the last
hundred years there is perhaps no more difficult and no more
disconcerting phenomenon than the rapid and sharp ascent and the sudden
decline and fall of political thought. During the nineteenth century
political thought entered on entirely new paths. New sources of
knowledge had been made accessible. Econo-mists, sociologists, and
philosophers vied with each other to utilize and exploit them. They
were con-vinced that the theory of politics, when compared with former
ages, was elevated to a higher level. Henceforth it was no longer
groping in the dark; once and for all the “royal road of science” had
been found.
The different economic, sociological, and
philoso-phical schools by no means agreed in their general views. They
followed different ways of investigation and they strove for widely
divergent political ideals. Nevertheless there was one point on which
all seemed unanimous. They had the same conception of the meaning and
task of a political theory. Such a theory, they told us, cannot indulge
in mere specula-tions or vain desires. It must be based on empirical
facts and general principles derived from them. By this method alone
can we make the decisive step that leads “from utopia to science.”
In the philosophy of the nineteenth
century this new tendency found its clearest expression in the system of
Auguste Comte. His ambition was to find a uniform method of scientific
thought that would over-come all the artificial barriers between the
different branches of knowledge. Comte’s Positive Philosophy
leads us, in an uninterrupted progress, from astro-nomy to physics,
from physics to chemistry, from chemistry to biology, from biology to
politics and sociology.
One of the principal arguments by which
Comte tried to prove the profound unity of human culture was his
discovery of a fundamental law prescribed by the very nature of the
human mind that, according to him, holds good for all the forms of man’s
cultural life: the human mind cannot reach its full scope without
passing through three different stages in its approach to each branch of
knowledge. It begins with a mythological stage, it develops into a
metaphysical stage, and it ends in a scientific or “positive” stage.
But, as Comte pointed out, it requires a much greater intellectual
effort to make the final step in the field of political thought than in
the field of mathematics, or physics, or natural history. In order to
comprehend and organize his own world—the world of his social
experience—man has first to study and to master the physical world. He
has to discover the laws of nature before he can even raise the question
of the existence and validity of fundamental sociological laws.
“Theological and metaphysical methods,
explod-ed in other departments,” wrote Comte, “are as yet exclusively
applied, both in the way of inquiry and discussion, in all treatments of
social subjects.” So, after innumerable vain attempts, this last spell
is about to be broken. Even in the world of poltics we need no longer
live in a world of illusions.
A Light That Failed
This philosophical ideal of the
nineteenth cen-tury—an ideal shared by all the pioneers of modern
political, economic, and sociological thought—seems suddenly to break to
pieces. Nothing is perhaps more characteristic of the present crisis in
our culture than the fact that what a few decades ago was regarded as
one of the great hopes and one of the highest triumphs of human science
has been abruptly abandoned.
It is not only the fulfillment of the
task set by Comte that is negated, it is the conception of the task
itself. Since the first decades of the twentieth century political
thought has slowly begun to change not only its content but its
fundamental form. And this change implies the complete reversal of all
the former intellectual or moral standards. Mythological thought openly
takes precedence over rational thought. In his political and social
life man is ex-pected to forget all he ever learned in the deve-lopment of
his intellectual life; he is admonished to go back to the first stages
of human culture.
When viewed from a mere theoretical
angle, this seems to be a complete breakdown of thought. But the
phenomenon is not to be accounted for in such a simple way. In order to
understand it we must take into consideration its practical motives and
its practical consequences. The twentieth century union of the
disparate elements of myth and politics appears at first sight to be
paradoxical. But the purport of this paradox is clear. By the alliance
both powers gain a new and unprecedented strength. Politics becomes a
mysterious thing, highly elevated over all our common standards. Its
authority is no longer open to any skeptical doubts or critical
objections. And myth gains not only by invading a special province but
by conquering the whole of human civilization.
It is not by chance that all the new
myths main-tain and defend a “totalitarian” conception of the state. By
this conception every appeal to any other tribunal is from the very
beginning declared null and void. There is nothing in the world to
restrict the power of the myth of the state. To mythicize man’s
political life means at the same time to mythicize all other human
activities. There exists no longer a separate sphere that has value of
its own. Philoso-phy, art, religion, science are under the control of the
new ideal. The hybrid of myth and politics becomes omnipotent and
irresistible.
In order to understand the strange fusion
of political and mythical thought that takes place in our modern
theories, we must, first and foremost, possess a clear insight into the
nature of the two elements that center in the combination. I shall
therefore describe some of the most important and most important and
most interesting combats that have taken place between the rational and
the mythical theories of the state. I can give only a very brief and
rough sketch; but perhaps even such a sketch may lead to better
understanding of our present situation.
The Beginnings of Reason
A rational theory of the state did not
come forward before the times of Greek philosophy. In this field, as in
others, the Greeks were the first pioneers of rational thought.
Thucydides was the was the first to attack the mythical conception of
story and to introduce a new method of historical inquiry and
psychological analysis. In the philosophy of the sophists man becomes
‘‘‘the measure of all things,” and all possible knowledge is directed to
a political end. Plato added that to understand the nature of man we
must begin by studying the structure of the state. Politics is the clue
to psychology.
Plato was the first thinker who introduced
a “theory” of the state, not a knowledge of many, multifarious,
haphazard facts, but a coherent system of thought. What was new in this
theory was a postulate that has put its stamp upon the whole subsequent
development of political thought. Plato began his study of the
political and social order with an analysis and a definition of the
concept of “justice.” The true state has no other and no higher aim
than to be the administrator of justice.
In Plato’s language the term “justice”
does not mean the same as in common speech. It has a much deeper and
more comprehensive meaning. Justice is not on the same level with other
virtues of man. It is not, like courage or temperance, a special
quality or property. It means a general principle of order, of
regularity, of unity, and of lawfulness. Within the individual life
this lawfulness appears in the harmony of all the different powers of
the human soul; within the state it appears in the “geometrical
proportion” between the different classes, according to which each part
of the social body receives its due and cooperates in maintaining the
general order. By this conception Plato became the founder and the first
defender the idea of the “legal state.”
In order to attain this end Platonic
theory had to overcome a dangerous and powerful adversary. From the
Greek point of view philosophical thought is opposed to mythical
thought. If we allow mythical thought to influence our political ideals
and to intrude into the order of the state, all our hopes for a rational
organization of society are lost.
Here we find the approach to one of the
most con-troversial elements of Plato’s theory. For all the
commentators, Plato’s attack on Greek poetry has always been a stumbling
block. We cannot think of Plato as being personally an enemy of poetry.
He is the greatest poet who has appeared in the history of philosophy.
But in Greek culture the bond between poetry and myth was indissoluble,
and this is the point at which Plato’s attack aims. To admit poetry
means to admit myth. But myth cannot be admitted without frustrating
all our philosophical efforts and without undermining the very
foundations of our phi-losophical state. It was for this reason that
Plato had to banish the poets from his republic.
What Plato attacks most violently are the
mythical stories about the deeds of gods and heroes. Plato no longer
believes in the gods of Greek popular religion. They have been
dethroned by a stronger power: by the highest idea, “the idea of the
Good.” The Divine and the Good have become synonymous. The tales of gods
who quarrel with each other, who lie and commit the worst crimes, can no
longer be tolerated.
For Plato there was a far-yawning gulf
between such myths and philosophical thought. In his theory of the
state he could no longer make allowance for mythical imagination. His
was a moral theory, a theory of justice that had to exclude all
imaginative, all fictitious or irrational elements.
Man’s State and God’s
The idea of the legal state, discovered by
the Greek thinkers, became an everlasting possession of human culture.
But with the beginning of the Middle Ages political problems were no
longer in the center of philosophical thought. The new emphasis is best
felt if we pass from Plato to St. Augustine.
St. Augustine stands on the borderline of
two ages. His education is rooted in the Latin and Greek classics. But
all he finds there can no longer satisfy his mind. He is longing for
another world—far beyond the world of learning and intellectual culture.
That makes the real difference between Plato’s Republic and St.
Augustine’s City of God. Both works are closely related to each
other. The very title of St. Augustine’s work is borrowed from Plato.*
*In heaven, said Plato,
there is laid up a pattern of that city (i.e., state) which exists in
idea only, which he who desires may behold, and beholding, may set his
own house in order.
And St. Augustine always speaks of Plato
with the greatest admiration and with a sort of religious awe.
Nevertheless St. Augustine was no
“Platonist.” Plato’s principal aim was to found a purely rational theory
of political life. For, this purpose he had to eliminate all mythical
elements. Of course, St. Augustine followed him in this so far as
Plato’s criticism was concerned with the gods of Greek popular religion.
But there remained one essential element that could not be accounted
for in a rational way and that nevertheless, from the Christian point of
view, was the basic problem of both religion and politics: original sin
and the fall of man.
Plato’s theory of the state is
philosophically true, St. Augustine conceded, but the fall of man is no
philosophical fact. Knowledge of it is based upon a special divine
revelation that was denied to Plato. And since Plato’s state is derived
from man’s mind, it is the outcome of the original sin of man and shows
all its marks. It is not reason, therefore, seeking its models in the
tainted mind of man, it is only the grace of God that can extinguish
these marks.
The medieval conception of the state has
never completely abandoned this view of St. Augustine. As late as in
the eleventh century, seven hundred years after St. Augustine, Gregory
VII still declared that the state was a work of sin and the devil. But
generally speaking, this uncompromising view could not be upheld in the
political literature of the middle ages. Even St. Augustine could not
forbear making a very important concession: if we cannot ascribe to the
political and social order any absolute value, we must admit that,
within its limits, it fulfills a positive and indispensable role. The
evil of the state, lodged as it is in the original sin of man, is deep
and incurable; but it is only a relative evil. When compared with the
highest absolute religious truth, the state proves to be at a very low
level; but it is still good in compari-son to our common human standards,
which, without the state, would lead us to chaos.
In the further development of medieval
thought this tendency to admit and to emphasize the positive value of
the state and the social order wins con-stantly in strength, owing
largely to the influence of Aristotle. According to Aristotle’s famous
phrase, man is by nature a social animal. Whenever we find man, we find
him in a social order. The superiority of man over the other animals
consists in the fact that he has developed the natural social instinct
into a new rational form. The human state is at the same time a natural
and a rational product. It has grown by a natural process through the
gradual enlarge-ment of the aboriginal community, the family.
This theory of the origin of the state was
accepted and elucidated by Thomas Aquinas. As the creator of all things
God is also the creator of the state. But here he works only as a
remote cause. Under the direction of God man builds up, by his own
forces and natural impulses, the political and social order. Yet in
this natural theory of the state the dogma of original sin is still a
necessary and preponderant element.
To fill the abyss between man’s primitive
condi-tion and his condition after the Fall was impossible for earlier
medieval thought, but in Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine the gap is bridged.
According to him there is no insuperable gulf between the temporal and
the divine order. Grace, he declares, does not destroy nature; it
perfects nature. The secular and the reli-gious order are different links
of one and the same chain. Despite the Fall, man has not lost the
faculty of using his forces in the right way and of thus pre-paring his
own salvation. Although, because of the Fall, salvation is not possible
without a special act of divine grace, man plays no mere passive role in
this great religious drama. His active contribution is re-quired, and
is, indeed, indispen-sable. By this con-ception not only man’s political
life but the whole of his cultural life has won a new dignity. The
“earthly state” and the “City of God” are no longer opposite poles; they
are related to each other and comple-ment each other.
The “New Science” of
Politics
A famous chapter in Jakob Burckhardt’s
book on the civilization of the Italian Renaissance is entitled: “The
State as a Work of Art.” Here Burckhardt gives a very clear description
of the new forms of political life. More than ever before state
appeared to be the work of individual men or of combined and continued
efforts of the members of a special family. It was planned by these men
and it was managed like a work of art. The predominance of the Medici
in Florence, the rise of the Visconti in Milan, the rule of the Gonzagas
in Mantova are famous examples of this phenomenon.
Machiavelli, the first man to have a clear
concep-tion of the dynamics of political life, was deeply im-pressed by
phenomenon. But as a theoretician he wished not only to describe it but
to understand it; to detect its origin and its reason. The reason for
the state and the mere fact of the state are his principal and
fundamental problems. If these reasons are to be sought in great
individuals we are in need not only of a historical or sociological but
also of a psychologi-cal interpretation of political life. We must study
the psychological motives and the procedures of the great artists of the
state.
Machiavelli’s Prince, written in
1513, is an unpre-cedented step in this study. It analyzes political
movements in the same spirit that Galileo analyzed physical movements.
But the treatise does not pursue a theoretical end alone; it has a very
definite practical purpose. Political analysis has to prepare and to
pave the way for political action. Every artist and every craftsman
needs a certain technique in order to perform his work in the right way.
All the other arts are in possession of such technical rules. But in
politics all this is still missing. Our actions are the result of
instinct or feeling, not the outcome of methodical observation and
rational thought. It is this obvious lack that Machiavelli’s book
strives to fill. Like any other craftsman the politician must know both
his material and his tools. His material is man; his tools are the
various ways in which human nature and conduct are to be influenced.
How much this new attitude toward
political life affected all the traditional conceptions is evident.
Machiavelli never attempted to refute the earlier conceptions; he simply
ignored them. In his hands the secularization of politics became
complete. To Machiavelli nothing in political life is wrapped in
mystery. All its features have, so to speak, become permeable to human
reason. We can understand the hidden motives and we can calculate the
effects of political actions in the same way that we understand the
effects of any natural phenomenon.
If we look at the problem in this way, as
Machia-velli himself did, we can exculpate the theory of Machiavelli from
one of the principal charges that has been made against him: its
profound immorality. Machiavelli spoke as a psychologist and as a
technician of political life who did not allow himself to be influenced
by any moral concerns. His theory is not immoral, but it is entirely
amoral. He is concerned with the causes and effects, not with the moral
ends of political action. His state holds its ground against all
attacks. Its sovereign is absolute. It is freed from all moral or
religious obligation.
For all this the theory had to pay a heavy
price. With Machiavelli the state loses some of its most essential
social functions. The sharp knife of Machiavelli’s analytic thought not
only severs all the bonds that connect political life with moral or
religious life; it also cuts off all the threads which the state is
fastened to the organic whole of social life. In the pursuit of the
interests of the state the rulers are longer bound to any consideration
for the commonweal. The state has become omnipotent; but on the other
hand it is completely isolated; it has lost its connection with the rest
of man’s cultural life. It stands, so to speak, in an empty space. For
power as sheer power, power for power’s sake, is, after all, a
meaningless thing.
It was this problem that had to be faced
by all the political theorists of the following centuries. The work of
Machiavelli could not be undone. Even his strongest opponents could not
think of going back to the medieval conception of the state. On the
other hand, even his followers and admirers very seldom admitted his
radical consequences. The doctrine of the reason of the state as the
ultimate reason for any social action was accepted; but in most cases
there was made an express reservation for other and higher reasons; for
the inviolability of Divine or natural law. But by such a compromise
the problem could not be solved. It was not enough to deny the
inferences drawn by Machiavelli. It became imperative to attack and
refute the very premises of his theory.
The Rights of Man
The seventeenth century is the period of
the labor pains of the modern world, and the political thought of that
century is a battlefield between two opposite and irreconcilable
conceptions. On the one hand the theory of the “absolute” state is
represented in its full strength. In thinkers like Jean Bodin and
Thomas Hobbes this theory is developed into its most radical
consequences. On the other hand a new ideal begins to form itself, and
finally wins the ascendancy. The doctrine of popular sovereignty
eclipses the principle of absolute government. Nevertheless these
widely divergent elements of political thought are held together by a
common intellectual bond. The cham-pions of absolutism and the defenders
of the sove-reignty of the people accept a common basis of thought. The
doctrine of the “state-contract” be-comes in the seventeenth century a
self-evident axiom of political thought.
In the history of our problem this fact
marks a great step forward. For if we adopt this view, if we reduce the
legal and social order to free individual acts, to a voluntary
contractual submission of the governed, all mystery is gone. There is
nothing less mysterious than a contract. A contract must be made in
full awareness of its meaning and conse-quences; it presupposes the free
consent of all the parties concerned. If we can trace back the state to
such an origin, it becomes a perfectly clear and understandable fact.
This rational approach is by no means a
historical approach. Only a few thinkers are so naive as to assume
that the origin of the state, as explained in the theories of the social
contract, gives us a true insight into its historical origin. We cannot
assign a definite moment of history in which the state made its first
appearance. But this lack of knowledge does not concern the
theoreticians of the state-contract. What they are seeking is not the
beginning of the state, but its principle. The thinkers of the
seventeenth century are no historians; they are logicians. Thus origin,
according to Hobbes, is not an origin in time but in reason.
The idea of the social contract looks back
at the classical distinction between “natural” and “positive”
law-natural law; in contrast to positive law, is prior to the state and
not subject to its rules. And it looks back especially to the doctrine
of man’s natural “equality” to other men, as developed by the Stoics.
The ideal of equality is not to be found
in the politics of Plato or Aristotle. Plato’s ideal state is the state
of justice. But according to Plato justice does not mean the same as
equality of rights. The state of justice will give to everyone and to
all the social classes their allotted work in the life of the state; but
it will not give them an equal share. And according to Aristotle slaves
are slaves by nature; the abolition of slavery is no political ideal,
but a mere dream.
The Stoics were the first to remove all
these bar-riers. They started from a sharp distinction between what is
necessary and what is accidental in human nature. There are innumerable
differences in men that are regarded as being of the highest importance,
but that do not count in an ethical and philosophical estimation of
human life. Whatever depends on ex-ternal circumstances, on conditions
that are not in our own power, is to be left out if we wish to deter-mine
the true value of our personal life. Riches, rank, social distinction,
even health or intellectual gifts—all these belong to the class of
irrelevant and indifferent things. There remains only one essential
good: the personal value of the human soul—that value which the
individual gives to himself. All the conventional barriers—the
distinction between Greeks and barbari-ans, between social classes,
between masters and slaves—are declared by the Stoic philosophers to be
null and void. The history of Stoic thought confirms and elucidates
this maxim: of the great Stoic thinkers one, Marcus Aurelius, was the
ruler of the Roman Empire, whereas another, Epictetus, was a slave.
All the Stoic thinkers are determined
individual-ists. The autonomy and independence of the indivi-dual will is
the highest principle in Stoic ethics. But this Stoic freedom does not
mean the isolation of the individual will, its emancipation from all
social bonds. Man finds his true individuality in the fulfillments of
his social tasks and obligations. The state itself, when seen in its
true light and interpreted in its right sense, is the consummation and
the guaranty of hu-man freedom. In Stoic thought the strictest
individu-alism and the largest cosmopolitanism are fused to-gether into an
indissoluble unity.
These theoretical presuppositions, pushed
into the background by the medieval feudal system, were suddenly turned
into most powerful practical weapons at the beginning of the modern era.
In the seventeenth century they proved their full strength in the
combat against the doctrine of the absolute state. According to the
theory of the absolute state developed in the work of Hobbes, the social
contract makes an end to all individual liberty. This contract is a
contract of submission by which the individual wills are extinguished
and cease to exist. In the civil state all powers are transferred to
and concentrated in the ruler. As against the sovereign power of the
ruler the individuals have no rights whatever.
According to the opponents of Hobbes, the
very concept of an absolute sovereignty is a contradiction in terms. If
the power of the sovereign is to be not only a physical force but a
legal power, it is bound to certain fundamental and inviolable rules.
These rules, being universal, are not subject to the freaks and fancies
of individual wills; and they cannot, therefore, be transferred from one
individual will to another. In the seventeenth century the classical
expression of this principle was given in the famous saying of Grotius,
that even the will of an omnipotent being, the will of God, is not at
liberty to change or cancel rights guaranteed by natural laws.
This is neither an isolated dictum nor a
mere pa-radox. It is a general opinion upheld by many of the most
influential political writers of the seventeenth century. That might
and right coincide in God does not mean that God is exempt from all
obligations; it means on the contrary that to him these obligations are
no external demands imposed upon him but that they are derived from his
very essence and, there-fore, are necessary elements of his own being.
This means at the same time that the
individual will is not entirely absorbed by the universal will. It
maintains and preserves a sphere of its own. There are certain inborn
and indefeasible rights of the individual that the state has to respect.
If man is to be truly man he can never surrender his indepen-dence; he
cannot entirely submit to the rules and commands of an external power.
In forming the social contract the individual has not given up his
personality.
The question of how far this sphere of the
indivi-dual will extends was answered in different ways. Liberty and
equality were regarded as the original natural rights of man, whereas
the problem whether individual property is to be reckoned among these
inalienable rights found no unanimous solution. We meet here with all
the theoretical foundations of those practical ideals and demands which
in the eighteenth century found their expression in the De-claration
of the Rights of Man.
Toward the Myth of the
State
The German romanticism that began to
flourish at the time of the Napoleonic Wars marks a new and decisive
epoch. It paved—though it did not point—the way that led to the modern
fascist and nationalist myths of the state. In this development
romanticism played a negative, not a positive, role.
Romanticism removed one of the principal
bar-riers that hitherto seemed to be invincible and insu-perable. The
romantic movement completely changed the valuation of myth. To
all the thinkers of the eighteenth century, myth was a barbarous thing—a
strange and uncouth mass of confused ideas and gross superstitions.
Between myth and philosophy there could be no point of contact. Myth
ends where philosophy begins—darkness gives way to the rising sun. Even
to look back at it would be to renounce mankind’s intellectual progress.
This view undergoes a radical change as
soon as we pass from the period of enlightenment to early romanticism.
Myth becomes not only a subject of the highest intellectual interest,
but also a subject of awe and veneration. It is regarded as the
mainspring of human culture. Art, history, poetry originate in it. A
system of philosophy that overlooks or neglects it is declared to be
shallow and inadequate. One of the principal aims of Schelling’s
philosophy was to give myth its right and legitimate place in· human
civilization. In Schelling’s works we find, for the first time, a
philosophy of mythology—side by side with his philosophy of
nature, history, art. And the more Schelling proceeds, the more
important becomes this part of his system. Finally all his interest
seems concentrated on it. Myth has become the very focus of
philosophical thought.
Romantic poetry goes the same way.
Mythology was always a part of poetry; and mythical subjects have been
treated, time and again, in classical literature. But all this—it is
now declared—was only accidental and superficial. What is demanded in
poetry is the revival and rehabilitation of the mythical spirit.
Romantic poetry is no longer to speak in mere images, in the language
of clear sensuous or intuitive forms. It must learn to speak a new
language—a language of hieroglyphs, of secret and sacred symbols. That
is the new gospel that we find in Novalis’s poetical works. To Kant’s
critical idealism, which had played such a decisive role in the
formation of the aesthetic ideals of classic German literature, Novalis
opposes “magic idealism,” his keystone of philosophy and poetry. The
poets and philosophers of the romantic era had come full circle from
Plato. The poet was now to banish the politician.
To the Romanticists, politics was not the
first and principle concern. They lived much more in the world of
“spirit,” in the world of poetry, of art, of philosophy than in the
world of hard political facts. And in this world they discovered a new
province. Henceforth their whole attention was focused on this
discovery, which filled them with the greatest enthusiasm. In early
romanticism, the interest in history oversha-dows all other
interests. It is from this point of view that they denounce the
“nature-right” theories of the state. The social compact is not a
historical fact; it is a fiction. All theories of the state that start
from such presuppositions are built on sand. Law and the state have not
been “made” by men. They are no product of individual wills, and they
are, therefore, not under the jurisdiction of these wills; they are not
bound to and restricted by our pretended individual rights. According
to the principles of the historic-right school, man could not make law
any more than he could make language, myth, religion. Human culture is
not an offspring of free and conscious human activities; it originates
in a “higher necessity,” in the national spirit, which works and creates
unconsciously.
That is the real philosophical center of
all the political theories developed by romantic writers. The
Romanticists love the past for the past’s sake. Even here we find the
deep influence of that mythical spirit that sees in the past the only
justification of all forms of personal life. The Romanticists always
see the past in a halo of sanctity. To them everything becomes
understandable as soon as it is traced back to its origins.
The romantic emphasis on history came at
the time of the Napoleonic Wars and the subsequent rise of national
states, which continued throughout the nineteenth century until finally
national history became, in the hands of Hitler and Mussolini, the
material from which the mythical state was built. The early
Romanticists had had no such intention. Their historical interest was
universal. Before the Roman-ticists, Goethe had been the first to use
the term “world literature,” and the Romanticists adopted the concept
with enthusiasm. Ranke’s monumental work was a world history.
Friedrich Schleiermacher, the greatest of the romantic theologians,
developed the ideal of a universal religion comprising all sorts of
creeds. But the rising national forces of the epoch diverted this
historical and mythological interest to narrow and particular ends. A
whole school of German political historians of the nineteenth century
developed and glorified the idea of the “power state.” The most extreme
among them, Heinrich von Treitschke, boasted that to avoid becoming
confused in writing the history of Prussia he had avoided looking into
the archives of Austria. Only one voice, that of the Swiss, Jakob
Burckhardt, was raised to say that power is evil in itself. No one
listened. The devotees of the “power state” had turned them-selves from
philosophers and historians into political pamphleteers. They had
opened the way for the mythmakers of the twentieth century.
The Antidote to Myth
What we have learned in the hard school of
our modern political life is the fact that human culture is by no means
the firmly established thing that we once supposed it to be. Modern
civilization is very unstable and fragile. It is not built upon sand;
but it is built upon a volcanic soil. For its first origin and basis
was not rational, but mythical. Rational thought is only the upper layer
on a much older geological stratum that reaches down to a great depth.
We must always be prepared for violent concussions that may shake our
cultural world and our social order to its very foundations.
The deep and ardent desire to reconstruct
our cultural world from its debris is now generally felt. But this aim
cannot be reached at once. The modern political myths have intoxicated
our thoughts and poisoned our feelings. It will be a long time before
the social organism can overcome or eliminate this poison. I do not
doubt that philosophy will have its share and do its duty in this slow
process of reconstruction. And perhaps its greatest contribution can
come through a reassertion of the ethical analysis made by Spinoza at
the beginning of the seventeenth century.
No philosophical thinker was more
convinced of the power of rational thought than Spinoza. Never-theless
he was perfectly aware of the fact that a passion cannot be overcome by
argument. It must be destroyed by a stronger and contrary passion. But
where can we find this stronger passion?
According to Spinoza our emotional life is
irra-tional in its very principle. It is based on dim feelings and
confused ideas, on imagination rather than reason or intuitive
knowledge. Yet there are two passions that, in the system of Spinoza,
are declared to be exempt from this flaw. They have their origin in the
active, not in the passive, part of human nature. In Spinoza’s system
the distinction between “active” and “passive” emotions does not follow
the traditional lines of thought. According to the Spinozistic theory
not only hatred but also love, not only pride but also humility, not
only cruelty but even pity belong to the class of passive emotions.
There remain only two active emotions:
fortitude and generosity. They are the fundamental virtues
of man; for they are those affections by which alone he can reach the
supreme goal: philosophical and ethical freedom. This freedom means not
only freedom from violent desires and emotions. It means freedom from
false conceptions, from inadequate ideas, from all sorts of prejudices
and superstitions. To get rid of all these obstacles to true freedom
high courage is required. This courage is not the same as mere physical
courage. Its true sense may be described by the words: “Sapere aude!”—“Dare
to know!” Fortitude is the courage to be wise, to live an
independent, active, and rational life.
But it is not enough that we reach this
goal for ourselves. We must freely communicate the good that we have
acquired for ourselves to others. And to do this we need the active
passion of generosity. Fortitude and generosity are the only means to
attain and secure the freedom of the individual mind and of human
society. By the former we win the mastery over ourselves, by the latter
we build up a social, a truly human order.
It was perhaps never more imperative to
recall these maxims of Spinoza than at the present moment. A passion
can only be overcome by a stronger passion. Only if we learn to
develop, to cultivate, and to intensify our active emotions can we hope
to check the wild chase of our passive emotions and to remold our social
and cultural life.
Cassirer main page