From
Physics and the Ultimate Significance of Time: Bohm, Prigogine, and
Process Philosophy,
edited by David Ray Griffin, Albany: The State University of New York
Press, 1986, Chapter 9, 127-53.
This is a slightly revised version of what appeared in Zygon 20/2
(June, 1985), 165-191.
Bohm and Whitehead
on Wholeness, Freedom, Causality, and Time
David Ray Griffin
David Bohm’s passion
is to overcome fragmenta-tion. As a reflective person, he is acutely aware
of the problems, intellectual and social, that have resulted from the
modern vision, which sees all things as externally related to all other
things. This vision has led to the assumption that the truth about the
world could best be learned by assigning its various “parts” to separate
“disciplines,” and the relative success of this procedure has reinforced
the conviction that the intellectual divisions correspond to real
divisions within reality, e.g., between living and nonliving, between mind
and matter, between humanity and nature, between deity and the world.
This modern vision has reinforced the egotistical and tribal tendencies of
us humans to think that the welfare of the individual person or at least
group (social, cultural, religious, and/or economic) can be promoted by
ignoring (or even defeating!) the welfare of all the others.
As a physicist, Bohm
is aware that his own discipline was the major contributor to the rise to
dominance of the mechanistic tradition in the modern world, that is, the
Western world since the seventeenth century. Furthermore, he knows that
physics is still regarded as the paradigmatic “science,” implying that
overcoming the mechanistic vision could be achieved most effectively if
developments in physics itself showed its inadequacy. This is exactly
what he believes has happened in the twentieth century, and he has devoted
himself to trying to drive home this fact and to working out the new,
nonfragmenting vision he believes best makes sense of all the facts and
provides a vision of wholeness adequate to our intellectual, religious,
and ethical needs.
But these pragmatic
considerations do not provide Bohm’s only motivation. He is also deeply
committed to discovering the truth about reality, to the degree
that this is possible in our time. This leads him to reject the finality
of the present quantum physics, whose equations merely describe the
probability of what an observer with a certain instrument would observe,
since this means that “modern physics can’t even talk about the actual
world!” (RV 45; see list of abbreviations at the end of this chapter).
Not only does Bohm find this nonrealism unsatisfying, he sees that it
keeps the mechanistic vision, which became so deeply ingrained between the
seventeenth and the nineteenth centuries, from being effectively
challenged. So finally Bohm’s two passions coincide: he believes that a
realistic physics, which will once again intend to express the
truth about the world (however partial this truth may be), will point to a
vision of wholeness in which all things are seen as internally
related to all other things.
Because Bohm
radically rejects the twofold tendency to see reality as composed of
externally related things and to divorce “physics” from “psychology,”
“philosophy,” and “theology”—the twofold tendency that is the essence of
the modern vision—Bohm’s vision is radically post-modern. (Bohm is
post- rather than pre-modern because he wants to preserve the
truths and positive values—and he does not minimize these—that have been
attained by modern science.) In this paper I shall summarize
Bohm’s proposal for a post-modern vision of reality (section 9.1) and then
discuss some problems involved in his proposal as developed thus far,
problems relating to freedom, causality, and time (section 9.2). Finally,
I shall suggest how various distinctions within Whitehead’s formulation of
a vision of “prehensive wholeness” can avoid these problems while
retaining the central intuitions in Bohm’s vision (section 9.3).
9.1.
Underlying Wholeness: Internal Relatedness via the Whole
There seem to be two
basic ways of explaining how things are internally related to each
other—so that knowing the truth about one thing would ultimately involve
knowing the truth about all things and promoting the good of one thing
would involve promoting the good of all things—that would reject the
mechanistic view, which sees things as having merely external relations to
each other. One way would be prehensive wholeness, seeing each
individual as a microcosm, somehow grasping all other things into its own
reality. Another way would be underlying wholeness, seeing all
individuals as internally related to all others not directly, but by
virtue of the fact that they all arise out of a common ground, which is
thereby immanent in each of them, making each of them indirectly immanent
in each other. Much of Bohm’s language suggests that the second way, that
of underlying wholeness, is his. For example, he says that “everything,
including mind and matter, actively enfolds the whole (and through this
everything else)” (S 39; cf. S 20, 32, 34; RS 333, 337).
Bohm rejects the
notion of “interaction,” whether between “mind” and “body” or between two
“particles.” The term interaction suggests—and one must admit that
Bohm is correct here—that the two things are first what they are,
independently of each other, and then enter into relations with each
other. The relations would then be external to their respective essences;
the relation would not be constitutive or internal to either of them (W I
26f., 134, 137). Of course, Bohm knows that there are organismic views,
such as Whitehead’s, in which interaction is not thought of in this way,
but as involving mutual in-fluence (in-flowing), which is internal to each
party. But he also seems to reject the language of interaction because in
the vision of underlying wholeness one finite (explicate) thing does not
directly affect another one at all. Rather, all influence is
mediated via the implicate order, in the whole. Event A
arises out of the whole (“projection”) and thereby affects the whole
(however slightly). Then new events arise out of the whole that appear to
have been causally affected by event A. But they were not directly
affected. Event A directly affected only the whole, and’ the later
events each arose out of the whole, so they were only indirectly affected
by event A. Hence Bohm speaks of the appearance of
causation and of things behaving “as if” there were a force between them
(RV 36; W 184). There is really no “horizontal” causation from surface
event to surface event. All causation is “vertical,” from the bottom up
(projection) and then from the top down (reinjection).
This model can
provide the basis for a solution to the mind-body problem, as well as for
the wider problem of the “interaction” of mind and matter in general. We
do not have to conceive of mind as having a direct influence on matter, or
vice versa, but can see that the correlations are due to resonances in the
implicate order. Likewise, the nonlocal correlations implied by quantum
theory need not be explained in terms of literal “action at a distance” or
of supraluminal signals, but can be understood as involving events that
arise as explications of resonances in the implicate order (W 129, 186),
where the separative space of the explicate order does not exist, except
in implicate form: all places are enfolded in the whole. The phenomena of
parapsychology that seem to suggest action at a distance (e.g.,
telekinesis, telepathy) would presumably also be explained by Bohm in this
fashion. Even precognitive phenomena, which seem to imply the influence
of the future on the present, might be so explained, since Bohm sometimes
suggests that the implicate order is timeless, in the sense of enfolding
all times (W 155, 167; RV 36). So-called precognition would really
involve only the resonance of an event that is explicate now with
an event that is later—from the viewpoint of the explicate order,
which orders events sequentially—to become explicated.
The solution to the
mind-body problem mentioned in the previous paragraph would imply that
what we call “mind” or “experience” or “consciousness” is as fully an
example of the explicate order as what we call “matter.” Development of
this line of thought would make Bohm’s position somewhat similar to
Spinoza’s. Spinoza thought of there being one infinite substance that has
an infinity of attributes, with thought and extension being the only two
known to us. By denying that there are two kinds of substances, and in
fact that there is a multiplicity of distinct “substances,” Spinoza
avoided the Cartesian problem of how two totally different kinds of
substances, thinking substances and extended substances, interacted.
“Mind” and “matter” are simply two attributes of the whole, and
attributes are not the kinds of things that have to figure out how to
interact.
However, there is
another tendency in Bohm’s thought, the tendency to say that “mind” or
“consciousness” is more illustrative of the implicate order than is
“matter” (W 197; S 31, 32). This is a tendency to which I shall return.
For now I need to explore the monistic question suggested by the
Spinozistic parallel. Regardless of how Spinoza should be interpreted, is
Bohm monistic in the radical sense of attributing all agency to the whole,
with the result that the apparent multiplicity of individuals have no
agency of their own vis-à-vis the whole so that a complete
determinism (albeit a non mechanistic one) is the ultimate truth? Some of
his language does suggest this, as when he portrays the universe, in
Hegelian language, as observing and describing itself through human beings
(RS 339), when he says that each event in the explicate order is “simply a
projection” of the whole (RV 43), and when he speaks of an “overall
necessity” (W 181; cf. W 195, 204f., 209, 213) and suggests that if we
could “actually determine all the sub-quantum variables” we would be able
“to predict the future in full detail” (W 106). However, he has clearly
rejected this interpretation of his meaning. He sees the indeterminism of
quantum physics as pointing to indeterminism as a property of matter (W
85, 105). And he affirms that the universe is “a self-acting whole” that
is “in some sense distinct from (i.e., autonomous and independent of) the
activity of the entities of the explicate order” (RS 336, 333). This
implies that the entities of the explicate order have some autonomy of
their own, making them distinct from the activity of the whole. Bohm
affirms this explicitly, saying that “each of the sub-wholes has its
appropriate kind and degree of freedom” and that, because of the law of
freedom, the harmony of each event with the whole and hence with all
others cannot be perfect (RS 337). However, he does want to insist that
the holomovement, the activity of the whole, is primary and that
the individual events have a “vanishingly small degree of substance or
independent actuality” in relation to the totality (S 93; RS 334, 339).
One further point to
mention in this brief overview of Bohm’s view of wholeness is that he
means it to provide a way to explain how novel forms can appear in the
explicate world. If events simply arose from the past explicate world,
the rise of genuinely new forms would be unthinkable. Also, allowing for
novel forms to be inserted now and then by an agency beyond the multitude
of finite beings would seem to involve an ad hoc exceptional type
of influence. But Bohm’s view is that events are constantly being created
by the whole and then dissolving back into it. This allows a natural
way for a creative content to enter the world at any point (RV 47).
Apparently enduring things, such as electrons and minds, are really “world
tubes” composed of series of events, each event replicating its
predecessor more or less exactly (more exactly in the electron, less so in
a human mind). The other presupposition necessary for explaining the
emergence of novelty is that the whole has a purpose to bring about
new subwholes. This “deep intent” of nature (RV 39, 40) can explain why
the evolutionary process has brought forth a richness of forms far beyond
anything survival as the only goal would dictate (RV 40).
9.2.
Problems in the Vision of Underlying Wholeness
In this section I
shall discuss several problems that arise if Bohm’s position is to be
understood as that of underlying wholeness alone, without the direct
horizontal causation involved in prehensive wholeness. These implications
would be “problems” because they would be inconsistent with some of Bohm’s
deepest concerns and/or with some of our deepest convictions; at least
they could be reconciled with them only by ad hoc measures.
(1) One problem
posed by Bohm’s idea of underlying wholeness is that human freedom
or the power of self-determination, is minimized. In the first place,
Bohm has not given primary attention to the issue of freedom. When he
characterizes the mechanistic vision, the focus is always on the
externality of relations rather than, as for many people, the determinism
implied by mechanism. He even says that the fact that the laws of quantum
physics are statistical instead of deterministic has little or no
relevance to the issue of mechanism (S 10£, c£ W 173, 178). And, as
indicated above, when describing his own position he has not always been
careful to avoid statements that could be interpreted to mean that all
events, human and nonhuman, are totally determined. Second, after
clarifying that he sees all events as having some degree of agency for
self-determination vis-à-vis the whole, Bohm stresses that the
agency of the whole is primary, whereas that of the subwholes is
“vanishingly small.” Third, focusing on the dialectic between the
implicate and the explicate, combined with (sometimes) seeing “mind” and
“matter” as equally “explicate,” has a leveling effect; it suggests that
the human mind has the same “vanishingly small” degree of power for
self-determination as an electron: there is no suggestion of a hierarchy
in nature, with increasing degrees of self-determining power.
This minimization of
our agency undermines the conviction running throughout Bohm’s writing
that the mechanistic, fragmenting vision has been a tragic distortion of
the truth, one which we need to and can overcome. If we have only a
vanishingly small degree of power vis-à-vis the whole, how can we
believe that we have deviated seriously from its “deep intent”?
Here we have a version of the problem of evil: if the creatures have only
very little power in relation to the creator, so that they are virtually
mere creatures (not self-creating ones to any significant extent),
how can they significantly “sin,” i.e., miss the mark? Also, if our power
for self-determination is so minimal, how can we believe that our efforts
to develop better insight, and to share this insight with others, can have
any effect (even aside from the issue of whether we can affect others
directly, or only via the whole)? To stress that our power is
vanishingly small is implicitly to say: whether or not a new vision comes
to dominate is primarily up to the whole, hardly at all up to us. This
belies the passion involved in Bohm’s own efforts to help change the
dominant vision. (It may be true that true insight comes not from effort
in the usual sense, but through being receptive to inspiration. But, even
to the degree that this is true, it takes considerable effort to get
ourselves into a truly receptive attitude!)
(2) A second set of
problems arises from Bohm’s apparent denial that events exert any
direct causation upon other such events. One problem here is simply
that this denial would run counter to one of our deepest convictions,
which is that we do directly interact with other things from which we are
partly distinct—that other things do affect us directly, and that we
directly affect other things. My body affects me, and I my body; through
my body I am affected by the surrounding world, and I affect it. Bohm’s
formulation—according to which each enduring thing is a series of events,
each of which arises from the whole and then dissolves back into it,
thereby modifying it slightly—seems to deny this conviction. Each
event affects other events only by affecting the whole, out of
which the later events arise. It is similar therefore to Malebranche’s
view: I cannot kick you directly, but only (as it were) by kicking God
who in turn kicks you!
The denial of direct
effects would also make the stability of the world mysterious,
reconcilable with the theory only by an ad hoc solution. Why do
certain forms of order, e.g., electrons and molecules, keep repeating
themselves for eons? Bohm admits that his view entails that “in
principle, every new moment could be entirely unrelated to the previous
one—it could be totally creative” (RV 36, cf. W 205). But experience
shows us, as he points out, that “there is usually a great deal of
recurrence and stability leading to the possibility of relatively
independent sub-totalities” (W 205). This idea of “relatively independent
sub-totalities” is stressed repeatedly by Bohm; it connects his views with
the world as experienced by us. And he does seek to explain how this
occurs in a way that is consistent with his basic principles, by
suggesting that a series of repetitions of a form will create a
“disposition” of the implicate order to produce that form (RV 36). A form
is projected into the explicate order, then introjected back into the
implicate order, then back into the explicate, and so on. Each
introjection influences the whole, creating a tendency for it to explicate
itself in terms of that form (RV 36). This is how Bohm explains “the
appearance of the ‘causation’ of the present by the past” (RV 36) and the
“interesting point” that “each moment resembles its predecessors” (RV 42).
However, one thing
this theory does not explain is why the same (or similar) forms are
almost always repeated in roughly the same place, vis-à-vis the
other forms that are being repeated. The forms embodied in the “aggregate
of events” I call the typewriter before me tend to be repeated second
after second, minute after minute, hour after hour, in the “same place,”
i.e., with the same spatial relations to the other forms that are being
constantly repeated, viz., those I call the house, the desk, the
lamp, and my body. Bohm’s account seems at most to account for the
disposition of the whole to repeat the same forms; it does not account
for the disposition to repeat them in the same or at least a contiguous
place. Bohm’s theory has the virtue of explaining how the phenomena
normally called “teleportation” or “materialization and dematerialization”
can occur. But on the basis of his theory we should expect these
phenomena to be much more common than experience teaches us they are. If
events do not directly affect their successors in a world tube, but only
by first influencing the whole, in which all times, places, and forms are
merged, we have no reason to expect the introjected form to be reprojected
next to approximately the same forms it was near in the previous moment.
Another problem is
closely related to this one: if one thing does not really affect another
one directly, but only indirectly via the whole, why is causation
between contiguous events so overwhelmingly important in our
world? Bohm’s theory explains how nonlocal correlations in physics (and
parapsychology) can occur. But Bohm himself says that the evidence to
date in quantum physics suggests that nonlocal effects arise only under
very special conditions. Furthermore, even if physics does come to show
that all “particles” manifest nonlocal correlations with others,
and if parapsychology convinces us that there are influences (or at least
correlations) between noncontiguous events far beyond the relatively few
instances of consciously detected extrasensory perception and
obvious psychokinesis, this will not change the fact that causal relations
between contiguous events are overwhelmingly important. Bohm’s theory, by
saying that every event is connected with every other event in the
implicate order, explains how nonlocal correlations in the explicate order
are possible. But if it denies that events have direct influences upon
other events, it does not explain why local correlations are so important.
Finally, there is an
element of arbitrariness in the affirmation that events exert
direct causal influence upon the whole (RV 36) but not directly upon other
subwholes. Insofar as Bohm distinguishes between the whole and the
multitude of subwholes, allowing each some autonomy vis-à-vis the
other, it would seem more consistent to allow that each event would have a
direct influence upon subsequent subwholes, as well as an indirect
influence upon them via its influence upon the whole. This vision would
combine underlying and prehensive wholeness.
(3) Another set of
problems could be created by Bohm’s suggestion that all times (as
well as places) interpenetrate in the implicate order (RV 36; W 155, 167),
which implies that the implicate order would be beyond time (RV 37, 43) in
the sense that the distinction between past, present, and future would
not be real in that order.
In the first place,
there is the problem of the compatibility of the belief in genuine freedom
and creativity, which Bohm wants to affirm, with the belief that in the
“really real” order the totality of what we regard as future is already
settled. If those events which are still future for us are, in some more
real realm, as fully settled as those which we regard as past, that is,
if the present implies the details of the future as fully as it implies
the details of the past, then each present event really has no power of
self-determination. Accordingly, insofar as people are logical,
belief that there is an implicate order in which all times interpenetrate
will undermine Bohm’s call to exercise our creativity to change the way we
and others think.
In the second place,
Bohm thinks of the implicate order as having awareness and purpose (RV 37,
39). To think of the implicate order as “the totality beyond time” (RV
43) raises all the problems that have been endlessly debated as to
whether it is even meaningful to speak of a “nontemporal awareness” and a
“nontemporal purposiveness.” I say that these have been endlessly
debated; but there does seem to be a growing consensus, shared by atheists
(e.g., Sartre) and theists (e.g., Hartshorne) alike, that these notions
are not meaningful because they are self-contradictory. Bohm is aware of
the problems. He says: “Whatever knowledge this implicate order would
have would be beyond time. Therefore, I don’t know if you would even
think of it as knowledge” (RV 37). And after saying that the universe
seems to be experimenting with forms, he says: “it shows itself to us
as if it were experimenting. That is, when looked at from the limited
aspect of time, the structure looks like an experiment” (RV 37;
emphasis added). If those few events which seem to imply that the future
is already as settled as the past, so-called precognitive events, could be
explained without denying the ultimate validity of the distinction between
past, present, and future (and I argue elsewhere that they can), would it
not be better to limit the nontemporality of the whole to an abstract
element within it and to retain the experienced asymmetry between
past and future as an ingredient in our theories about the ultimate nature
of things, since we can thereby more clearly retain freedom and
meaningfulness?
9.3.
Whitehead’s Vision of Prehensive Wholeness in Relation to Bohm’s Concerns
Some of the problems
in Bohm’s formulation of his vision thus far are matters of
self-consistency; others are tensions between his formulation and our
deepest convictions. All these are related, I suggest, to a more general
problem, a tendency to use the implicate-explicate distinction too
indiscriminately. Many of the analogies Bohm has lifted up between
apparently dissimilar features of the world and human experience are
indeed illuminating. But in some cases the general formula, “the
explicate unfolds from the implicate and is then enfolded back into it,”
leads to tensions with our deepest intuitions or with other applications
of this formula. These tensions arise because some fundamentally
different types of relations are subsumed under the general
implicate-explicate formula.
In this section I
suggest that some distinctions developed by Alfred North Whitehead can
preserve the affirmations about which Bohm is most concerned while
avoiding the problems in his formulation of these affirmations as
developed thus far.
Whitehead in many
respects traveled a path similar to Bohm’s. He also was a mathematical
physicist (though primarily a mathematician) passionately interested in
the relation between the world as described by physics, on the one hand,
and the phenomena of life, on the other, and the relation of both of these
to the world as known through moral, aesthetic, and religious experience.
He was also deeply disturbed by the deleterious effects the vision of
reality formulated in relation to the natural sciences has had upon the
modern world (see his Science and the Modern World). He likewise
began with a vision of wholeness reminiscent of Spinoza’s but then went
beyond it. It is primarily the distinctions he developed in moving beyond
the Spinozistic monistic and deterministic vision that are helpful in
resolving the tensions within Bohm’s developing position.
9.3.1. God and Creativity
Much philosophical
and religious thought, both Eastern and Western, has understood
undifferenti-ated being as the ultimate reality. It has variously been
named Being, Being-itself, Prime Matter, Urgrund, the Godhead,
Brahman, and Emptiness. Whitehead calls it Creativity. It is formless;
it is being without attributes (Nirguna Brahman). Whitehead says “it is
without a character of its own” (PR 31).
There have been two
major ways in which this metaphysical ultimate has been thought to be
related to a determinate, perhaps personal, deity (Saguna Brahman). On
the one hand, a determinate deity has been regarded as the first
emanation from the indeterminate ultimate reality. How that
which is totally devoid of all form, all determinateness, could give rise
to something with form has always been a problem, but the
affirmation has been widely made.
On the other hand,
some traditions have simply identified God and Being-itself. This creates
inevitable tensions. Sometimes, as in Tillich, the affirmations made about
the personal God of religious devotion have to be interpreted so as not to
contradict the philosophical vision of an ultimate reality said to
transcend all determinate characteristics and hence to be beyond
attributions of, e.g., love, knowledge, purpose, and agency. The pious
are allowed to continue applying such terms to Being qua God, but
the philosophical theologian knows that the attributions cannot be applied
literally, or even analogically, but only symbolically, metaphorically.
This view also means that “God” can exert no influence: there is no
concrete “whole” in the sense of an all-inclusive embodiment of Being.
The only embodiments are the multiple finite instances of Being.
Being-itself is not a being that can influence or be influenced by
the various beings; it is simply the being of the many beings.
At other times, as
in Thomas, the indeterminate-ness of Being-itself is compromised by being
equated with the determinate God. This equation leads to total
determinism, since all being and hence power and activity belong to (are
identical with) God.
One of Whitehead’s
major innovations was to diverge from these two dominant ways of relating
God and Being. Whitehead distinguishes between God and Creativity
and yet makes them equally primordial. God is not simply
Creativity; God has determinate characteristics: God knows the world,
envisages primordial potentials with appetition and purpose, influences
the world, and is in turn influenced by the world. God loves the world
actively, seeking to influence it toward its good, and receptively,
responding sympathetically to its events. But God is not a derivative
emanation from Creativity; God is the primordial embodiment of
Creativity. (Creativity is that which is instantiated by all actualities;
it is not an actuality that could exist by itself, unembodied.) Whitehead
refers to God as the “eternal primordial character” of Creativity (PR 225,
cf. 344).
I suggest that Bohm
has thus far wavered between these three visions. Sometimes he speaks in
a Vedantist-Neoplatonic way, as if the ultimate reality, the ultimate
implicate order, were totally formless. For example, he says in an
interview: “We must have some form—we can’t live entirely in the implicate
order” (RV 36). In this mood, he speaks of all “measure” as created by
human insight, denying that “it exists prior to man and
independently of him” (W 23). Reality as such would be formless, Brahman
without attributes. All form and measure would be maya, illusion.
In line with this vision, Bohm can legitimately say that we have freedom,
for each of the explicate parts, each of the events of the world, would be
an embodiment of the whole, which is a holomovement, dynamic activity.
But if he were to carry out this vision consistently, he would not be able
to talk of the influence of the whole on the parts (except as the “whole”
in the sense of the totality of the parts, and this is the mechanistic
vision he wants to avoid), nor the influence of the parts back upon the
whole (i.e., of the enfoldment back into the implicate order as somehow
altering it). It is not for nothing that consistent visions of this sort
stressed that the ultimate reality was impassible.
More
characteristically, Bohm seems to equate God and Being somewhat in the
Thomistic fashion (at least as I am interpreting Thomas) and to see this
somewhat determinate reality as the ultimate implicate order.
Accordingly, Bohm speaks of the ultimate implicate order as having
intelligence and compassion. But this vision, if carried out
consistently, would lead to determinism, for if all energy, movement, or
activity as such is equated with a concrete being (and only a concrete,
determinate being can have attributes such as intelligence and
compassion), then the creatures have none of their own. In this vision,
all causation is vertical: there is a hierarchy of levels of
order. Each level (except the highest and the lowest) is implicate in
relation to the level above it and explicate in relation to the level
deeper than it. (In line with speaking of “underlying wholeness,” I am
referring to the more implicate orders as deeper, even though Bohm
often speaks in Neoplatonic fashion of descent from the highest
implicate order to the more explicate orders.) The “implicate-explicate”
language here suggests determinism: each level is a mere explication or
unfolding of what was already there, implicit or enfolded, in a deeper
level. Indeed, Bohm sometimes says that there is an infinite hierarchy of
implicate orders, suggesting that this somehow avoids the conclusion of
total determinism. But this is problematic. First, it is hard to see
what it might mean. Second, it is hardly consistent with speaking of the
ultimate implicate order as characterized by love and
intelligence. Third, if the level of conscious human experience is
totally a product of some deeper level, it does not mitigate the implied
determinism to say that the series of increasingly deeper levels of causal
orders never reaches bedrock. But the fact that Bohm thinks there is a
problem requiring a solution shows that he often does not think of each
level of reality as having its own activity, creativity, or freedom, by
which events can partially determine themselves vis-à-vis other
levels and the whole.
Bohm’s statement
that these events do have some such power, but that it is “vanishingly
small,” can be regarded as a compromise between the first two visions.
But his intuitions that these explicate events somehow affect the whole,
even if only slightly, can fit with neither vision. If the ultimate
implicate order is formless, we cannot affect its form; if it has
all the activity, in which case we are merely emanations from or
explications of it, then we have no agency by which we can effect a change
in it.
But Bohm’s
intuitions here can be conceptualized in terms of Whitehead’s new vision,
in which God and Being (i.e., Creativity) are distinguished. Creativity
is embodied by all events. Creativity is the threefold capacity of events
(1) to be influenced by previous events, (2) to create themselves
partially: and (3) to influence subsequent events. Creativity is embodied
by every local event (“actual occasion”) and by the all-inclusive series
of events (“God”). Accordingly, God has autonomous power to influence the
world and the capacity to be influenced by it (this latter capacity is
called God’s “consequent nature”). Likewise, each local event
constituting the world arises from the Whole at that moment, meaning God
and the totality of previous actual occasions. But each event then
influences God and all subsequent local events. Accordingly, the Whole
out of which the next moment of the world will arise will be slightly
different from what the Whole was a moment before.
In this vision, God
is not seen as owning Creativity (or Being-itself) any more than does the
world. God has always existed, instantiating Creativity. But so has the
world—not this world, with its contingent forms of order, but
some world or other, with a multiplicity of actual occasions embodying
Creativity. Creation of our particular world was not initiated by a
creation ex nihilo, in the sense of a total absence of finite forms
of actuality, but was a creation out of chaos, out of a less ordered realm
of finitude.
Accordingly, the
relation between God and finite events cannot be described in the language
of implicate-explicate, for at least two reasons: (1) God and local
events each have self-determining power in relation to each other, so
neither is merely the unfolding of what was contained implicitly in the
other; and (2) local events are directly influenced by previous local
events, not just by God: the Whole out of which they arise is
God-and-the-world.
Although there is
hierarchy in this Whiteheadian vision, there are distinct realities
that are not related hierarchically. Rather than a Neoplatonic-type
descent from Creativity, to Forms, to God, to Creatures, all of these
realities are equally metaphysical, equally primordial (with the
qualification that no particular creatures are necessary, only
Creaturehood as such; i.e., there must be some creatures). God is
as primordial as Creativity, each implying the other. God, as a
determinate being, can act: God’s primordial activity is the appetitive
envisagement of the Eternal Forms (“eternal objects”), the Primordial
Potentials, which imply God and Creativity as much as being implied by
them. And God, Creativity, and the Forms all imply, and are implied by, a
realm of Creatures who will in-form their Creativity with a selection from
the Eternal Forms.
This set of mutually
implied (rather than hierarch-ically arranged) realities protects our
intuitions about freedom, causation, and time.
The distinction between God and Creativity, which allows the creatures to
be equal stockholders in Creativity, protects the freedom of the
creatures. It also protects the concreteness and transcendence of God
and, hence, causal influence between God and world. The idea that God is
not derivative from Creativity protects the ultimacy of determinateness,
including the temporal distinction between past, present, and future. The
idea that the Creativity embodied in the creatures is not derivative from
God also protects the ultimacy of temporal distinctions. The idea that
God also embodies Creativity gives further support to the ultimacy of
temporal distinctions, since, besides God’s primordial, nontemporal
aspect, there is God’s concrete actuality, which is temporal, i.e., which
distinguishes between events that have occurred and possible events, which
have not. Also, this fact that God as concrete is temporal allows us to
speak of an all-inclusive awareness and purpose without contradiction and
without undermining the reality of time and freedom. Our future could
hardly be indeterminate, to be rendered determinate only by our exercise
of creativity, if from a higher point of view the events that seemed
future to us at a certain “now” were already (or eternally) determinate.
9.3.2. Events in Themselves and for Others
I have distinguished
between three phases of Creativity: an event’s (1) reception of influences
from its environment, its (2) self-determining activity, and its (3)
influence upon subsequent events. In this section I shall collapse the
first two moments into one and refer to this moment as the event as it is
in itself; the third moment will be identical with the event as it
is for others.
The event in itself
is a subject.
It does not enfold the influences from the environment the way a cabinet
receives canned goods, but the way a moment of experience receives
influences from its body and the greater world. It does it with
feeling. In fact, Whitehead refers to each local event, each, “actual
occasion,” as an “occasion of experience.” Every true individual (as
distinct from aggregates of individuals, such as sticks and stones) has
(or is) a unity of experience in which a vast myriad of influences are
synthesized. This reception of influences, and self-determining synthesis
of them into a unified experience, is what an event is in itself. This
internal, self-determining process is called “concrescence,” which means
“growing together.” This notion corresponds with Bohm’s attribution of an
inner formative activity to events in their phase of enfolding (W 12, 13,
79).
But as soon as this
unity is reached, the event becomes an object for others. The subject
becomes a “superject.” The event as a becoming subject “perishes”; the
event as a causal power upon others comes into being. The data it had
enfolded are now unfolded or “superjected” into the universe. The event
reveals publicly what it had been doing privately. What was a subject in
itself becomes something for others, and in this sense it is an
object. Whether it also becomes an object of sense perception, and/or an
object of consciousness, depends upon whether there are subjects around
capable of making it into an object in this more sophisticated sense. But
it, willy-nilly, becomes an object in the sense of a causal influence upon
subsequent subjects, which unify it (along with the rest of the
environment) into their internal reality and which then in turn perish as
subjects and become objects or superjects for subsequent subjects, and so
on.
This provides a way
of distinguishing between mind and matter without relying on an
ontological dualism making their mutual influence unintelligible. Rather
than being two different types of actualities, “mind” refers to what an
actual entity is in itself, whereas “matter” refers to what it is for
others. Our self-consciousness at a moment is our direct knowledge of
what an event is in itself: we know what a “thing in itself” is by
being one—and by being one that is sophisticated enough to be aware of
itself. (Lower-grade subjects would have awareness, but not
self-awareness.) We do not have the same kind of direct knowledge of the
subjectivity of other individuals. But since we know that we have
subjectivity, even though it does not appear to others, we can assume, by
analogy, that other individuals had their own subjectivity prior to their
becoming objects for us. Bohm suggests this nondualist position, saying
that what we call “matter” has something analogous to mentality,
creativity, and imagination (RV 39, 47).
I am using the word
individual deliberately. There are also aggregates of
individuals, such as sticks, stones, and tables. These answer to the
ordinary notion of matter even more than does the objective existence of
individuals such as electrons, atoms, molecules, and cells. These
aggregates show no signs of the spontaneity we associate with
subjectivity, since the uncoordinated spontaneities of the millions or
billions of members of the aggregate (e.g., the molecules in a rock)
cancel each other out with the result that no unified movement is
attained.
There are some
groupings of individuals that are not mere aggregates, however. These are
“compound individuals,” in which a higher-level series of
subject-then-object events arises and has a dominating influence over the
society as a whole. Animals, including ourselves, are the obvious
examples. But atoms, molecules, and living cells can also be thus
regarded. The world of finite things can then be classified into these
four basic types of things: (a) actual occasions; (b) enduring objects,
which are serially-ordered societies of occasions (Bohm’s “world tubes”);
(c) nonindividualized societies of enduring objects (inorganic things,
plants); and (d) compound individuals. A high-level compound individual
harbors, as its dominant member, a series of higher-level occasions of
experience, a “soul.”
It seems to me that
this position is already implicit in Bohm’s thought, insofar as he speaks
of each event as enfolding the whole and then unfolding itself back into
the whole and of a so-called particle as in reality being a world tube or
a trajectory of such events of enfolding and unfolding. His complaint
against orthodox physics would be that it has thus far assumed that the
events in their unfoldment, or explicate state, constituted the full
reality of the events, thus ignoring their prior, implicate state. His
suggestion that there are “hidden variables” to account for the behavior
of observed events would mean that the explanation may lie in what the
event is in itself, in its subjective moment, which has at least an iota
of self-determining power. Bohm comes close to this view when he suggests
that mind or consciousness is more illustrative of the implicate order
than is matter (above, section 9.1). I am urging him to say that
self-conscious experience is our one opening into what an event in its
state of enfolding is and then to generalize some degree of experience to
all events.
The Whiteheadian
position would have the following advantages to Bohm:
(1) It would show
how mind and body can be directly related, without having to route this
apparently direct relation through some underground reality. Bohm is
right to say that mind and matter are related through some more
fundamental reality, but this more fundamental reality need not be thought
to exist beyond the concrete events of the world. The concrete events are
themselves this more fundamental reality, each being first a subject which
enfolds previous subjects-become-objects into itself and then in turn
unfolds itself as matter for subsequent events. What we call our own
“mind” or “soul” is simply a very high-level series of subject-object
events dominating a body made of societies composed of lower-grade events
with this dual nature. Since there is no ontological dualism, mutual
influence is no problem.
(2) This position
would show the fundamental reality, and irreversibility, of time. Time
results from the causal relations between events. The irreversibility of
time is due to the relationship of enfolding and being enfolded. If event
B is later than A because B included A but A
does not include B, it would be nonsense to suppose that time could
then go backwards, so that event A would be later than B.
For this would mean that B would both include and not include A
which is a self-contradiction.
Time is not an
actuality which could exist apart from events. But since Creativity is
the ultimate reality, so that there always has been and always will be
ongoing relationships of including and then being included, time in the
sense of a distinction between past (determinate, included), present
(including, becoming determinate), and future (indeterminate, not included
[at least in the same sense as the past is included]) is a necessary
feature of reality.
(3) This doctrine
allows real causation (vs. positivism) but without a mechanistic view of
causation as total determination and mere external relation. The direct
causation of one event upon another can be affirmed, and yet Bohm’s view
that there is no causation between two explicate objects is supported.
The causation of one event (as object or superject) does not directly
influence a subsequent event’s superjectivity; rather, it passes through
the affected event’s subjectivity and hence through an implicate ordering
process, which involves some element of self-determination and which is
hidden to the outside observer. It is only when the affected explicate
event is our own behavior that we are privy to what goes on in between
the two explicate events.
Of course, we are
only partly privy to this process, since much of it transpires
below the threshold of consciousness. This is another way in which Bohm
uses the implicate-explicate distinction: conscious experience can be
considered an explication of unconscious experience (S 67). One moment of
conscious experience, as explicate experience, does not directly affect a
subsequent conscious experience, but only indirectly, by passing through
the unconscious depths of the next moment of experience. It should be
noted, however, that this is not an example of causation by one event upon
another, but of different phases within a teleological, self-determining
process. But even here the explicate (i.e., conscious) aspect is not
merely an explication of what is already determined in the implicate
depths: the conscious aspect of experience plays a role in the
self-determination of a moment of experience. Consciousness is not merely
an epiphenomenal by-product of unconscious forces. So, even though the
implicate-explicate formula works here better than for many distinctions,
it is not fully appropriate.
However, terminology
aside, Bohm’s point is important, and it is supported by Whitehead.
Consciousness, according to Whitehead, tends to light up only the later
phase of an occasion of experience, not the early phase, where the
enfolding of the environment occurs. Hence consciousness tends to lose
sight of the connectedness of experience with its world-the fact that it
arises from and even includes the whole past world (and God) in itself.
Accordingly, the soul, insofar as it identifies itself with its conscious
experience, comes to see itself as an independent substance, only
externally connected to the surrounding world. Solipsism can even be
seriously entertained. Bohm is right: our conscious experience can seem
to be even more disconnected from its environment than the matter we
perceive (and construct—see below) through our sensory experience (5
94f.). Insofar as Bohm is using the implicate-explicate distinction to
stress that this apparently disconnected consciousness is part of a far
vaster experiential process in which the whole world is enfolded, the
distinction is justified.
(4) Whitehead’s way
of speaking of an enduring object as a serially-ordered society of events
provides a basis for conceptualizing another of Bohm’s concerns, which is
to affirm that nature has a “deep intent” to realize new forms (above,
section 9.1) and that the world is somehow able to respond to this. Bohm
says, for example: “You might suppose, say, that somehow nature realizes
that it’s being presented with various things that now have to be brought
together. Nature realizes this greater whole at a deeper level, which is
analogous to imagination” (RY 47).
Whitehead’s
explanation is as follows. The primordial nature of God, which is the
Divine Eros of the universe, is God as envisaging the primordial potencies
with appetition that they be realized in the world (PR 32-34). Worldly
events, for which a given potentiality is relevant, come to feel this
potentiality for its future successors conformally, i.e., with appetition.
Many successive members of a given enduring society (world tube) could
continue to feel this possibility for the society’s existence, but as long
as it was only felt with appetition, or “mentally,” nothing would be
changed in the outer appearance of the enduring object. The successive
occasions of experience would in themselves be different, in that the new
possibility would be fermenting in them; but their outer demeanor would
remain unchanged. The new form would only be implicit in the society.
But at some point, as Bohm says, “it unfolds into the external
environment” (RY 47). In Whitehead’s terms, it unfolds when some member
of the society feels the possibility not only mentally, which is a
restricted way of feeling it, but physically, or unrestrictedly (PR 291).
This occurs when there is a “hybrid physical feeling”: an occasion feels
physically what was felt by a predecessor only mentally. To feel it
physically is to accept it as characterizing one’s one shape. At this
moment, the new form becomes observable and has effects upon the
environment. Accordingly, Whitehead supports Bohm’s intuition that novel
forms do not suddenly arise in the observable world from nothing, or even
directly from other observable events, but from an implicate, hidden
dimension of the world.
Incidentally, this
doctrine is germane to the problem of evil. God’s causal efficacy does
not directly produce the form of the observable world, but is twice
removed from it. First, God must wait for events in the world to feel the
divine appetitions for them conformally, i.e., to develop an appetition
for these new forms. Second, even after this appetite is whetted, the
novel possibilities will not become manifest in the world until some event
makes the leap from entertaining the possibility to actually living in
terms of it.
(5) The distinction
between hybrid physical prehensions and pure physical prehensions provides
a causal basis for accounting for nonlocal correlations (i.e.,
correlations between noncontiguous occasions) while accounting for the
special significance of causation between contiguous events. In a pure
physical prehension, the form prehended from a previous occasion is
one that is energized by the creativity in the physical pole of that
occasion. Forms that have been physically realized are unrestrictedly
realized, and hence are superjected with the full energy of the
occasion behind them, and hence with considerable compulsiveness. Forms
that are realized only conceptually (mentally, appetitively) are not
embodied in the event’s physical energy, but only in its mental energy,
which may be negligible. The prehension of such a form from an
antecedent occasion will mean, at least usually, the reception of data
without compulsive, but only persuasive, power.
This distinction
should correspond to Bohm’s suggestion of two forms of energies: the
denser explicate energies and the subtler implicate energies, which “would
not ordinarily even be counted as energies” (RV 39, 44). Here again,
Bohm’s “implicate” would correspond with Whitehead’s “conceptual” or
“appetitive.”
Whitehead suggests
that pure physical prehension is limited, at least for the most
part, to contiguous occasions. If so, i.e., if compulsive
influence occurs only between contiguous occasions, this explains why
contiguous causation is so important in our world, so much so that the
modern mind has thought it to be the only kind of causation. But since
Whitehead does not consider it the only kind, he has a basis for
explaining action at a distance. That is, he suggests that hybrid
physical prehensions can occur equally between contiguous and
noncontiguous occasions. This provides for another kind of influence,
different from the “physical energy” of current physics.
Hence, Whitehead
explains both local and nonlocal correlations in terms of prehension, and
hence in terms of direct causation of one event upon another. With a
Whiteheadian basis, one need not resort to noncausal synchronicity, rooted
in some timeless dimension in which all things are together, in order to
explain parapsychological events or nonlocal correlations in physics. By
allowing for direct prehensions of remote events, the speed of light does
not put an upper limit on the time in which one remote event can influence
another. Accordingly, one need not assume that some connection, other
than a direct one between the two events, is needed in order to explain
the nonlocal correlations in physics and parapsychology. One thereby
avoids the problem as to why, if events do not directly influence other
events, the apparent causal connections between contiguous events are
different in kind from those between noncontiguous events.
Incidentally, I
should add that Whitehead was not dogmatic about limiting pure physical
prehensions to contiguous events. “Provided that physical science
maintains its denial of ‘action at a distance,’ the safer guess is
that direct objectification is practically negligible except for
contiguous occasions; but that this practical negligibility is a
characteristic of the present cosmic epoch, without any
metaphysical generality” (PR 308; emphasis added to highlight the four
qualifications given). Accordingly, if physics or paraphysics seems to
require it, e.g., for instances of psychokinesis, there would be no
metaphysical reason to deny that the more compulsive type of causality
could be exerted at a distance.
In any case,
assuming for the most part that pure physical prehensions occur only
between contiguous events, we can see that each kind of causation has its
own advantage. The kind exerted only between contiguous events has much
more immediate strength, but the kind that can be exerted between
noncontiguous events can develop strength through repetition. Hence,
Whitehead’s position provides a basis for the kind of point made by Jung
and Sheldrake, that the repetition of a form countless times in the
past creates an “archetype” or “field” that exerts a formative influence
upon present events. If a particular form is repeated in events A-D,
event E will receive the same form directly from A, from
B (which includes A), from C (which includes both A
and B), and from D (which includes A, B,
and C) (see PR 56, 226, 284). Hence, even though noncontiguous
causation of event A upon event Z may be trivial compared
with its contiguous causation upon event B, the noncontiguous
causation received by Z may be as important as the contiguous
causation, due to the cumulative effects of countless repetitions of a
similar pattern.
This point, although
often overlooked by Whitehead interpreters, is a key to his central
description of Creativity, which is that “the many become one, and are
increased by one” (PR 21). The “many” out of which any event is created
is finally the whole past, not just the immediate past: “the whole world
conspires to produce a new creation” (RM 109). This view provides a very
strong notion of wholeness, of each event as a microcosm: incorporating
in some sense the whole world, and of the world as an organism, in which
the whole enters into every part, not a machine, in which causation by
contact is king. And of course the whole that is prehended by each part
is not only the whole past world but also God, who has incorporated the
whole past world into an all-inclusive experience. And yet all this
wholeness is affirmed on the basis of the category of prehension alone,
which means that the distinction between past, present, and future is
never compromised. Wholeness does not require giving up the limitation of
efficient causation from past to present. The future and the contemporary
worlds are left as indeterminate and hence as exerting no causation upon
the present event. This allows our intuition of freedom, in the strong
sense of the capacity for self-determination in the moment, to remain
unthreatened by our intuition of wholeness.
9.3.3. The Worlds of Causal Efficacy and of Sensory Experience
One of Whitehead’s
chief concerns is to distinguish the actual world, in which real causal
efficacy is exerted among events, from the world as it appears to our
sensory perception, especially vision. This latter “world’ is not the
world as it actually is, but an appearance produced by our sensory and
conscious experience out of the actual world’s causal efficacy upon us.
This appearance is not a total falsification of the actual world, but it
involves gross simplification and distortion. In particular, it presents
us with a world in which things appear to be passive rather than active,
to be externally rather than internally related to other things, to have
no experience, no aim, no self-value. And of course natural science has
largely limited itself to this world of appearance—to the world as known
through our senses and instruments designed to amplify them. Accordingly,
if the world as it appears to scientific study is taken to be the actual
world, we get a picture of the world as made of externally related,
passive, aimless, valueless bits of stuff. And such a world can clearly
provide no intelligible explanations as to why it behaves as it does.
Explanation, as opposed to merely descriptive generalization (which is
positivism), requires resorting to something hidden beneath the
appearances. In the modern period, the dominant assumption among those
seeking explanations has been that the actual world is composed of
entities whose reality is exhausted by their appearances, their effects.
What they are in themselves is not thought to be essentially
different from what they are for others. This assumption has produced the
materialistic-mechanistic world view.
Whitehead, however,
decided that actual entities in themselves were subjects, aiming at and
realizing value and being internally related to other actualities in their
environments. He does not base this conclusion on pure speculation, but
upon experience, but it depends upon not taking sensory perception as the
basic type of perception. More basic is “perception in the mode of causal
efficacy,” which involves a direct perception and internalization of other
events. At this level of experience, we perceive the actuality of other
things, their activity, and some of the values they have achieved. At
this level perception is not of an object as external; rather, it is a “prehension,”
a grasping of aspects of the object into oneself as material for one’s own
experience. Hence, Whitehead speaks of a direct interaction among events,
but he does so without using the image of external, mechanistic relations
that the term interaction often conjures up.
From a Whiteheadian
point of view, Bohm is absolutely right that there is no causation between
“explicate” events, if this term is used to refer to events as
perceived by sensory experience, which is how Bohm often uses it (W
ix, 158, 186, 206; S 92). That world is entirely a product, not a
producer. (It has “effects” only insofar as we act upon the illusory
belief that it is the actual world.) And yet, by distinguishing between it
and the actual world, we can affirm our deep intuition that there is a
direct causal relationship between events, such as between one moment of
experience and the next or between mind and body.
9.3.4. Various Levels of Actuality in Compound Individuals
One of the points I
have been making is that, although there are several features of
Whitehead’s vision that correspond to distinctions Bohm makes between
implicate and explicate orders, these features do not form a hierarchy of
levels of existence, a great chain of being, ending in a deepest level in
which everything in the higher levels was already implicit. However,
there are some types of hierarchy in Whitehead’s thought. These
also correspond to notions suggested by some of Bohm’s statements.
First, there is
hierarchy involved in all compound individuals. The atom is already a
hierarchical society, since it is not merely an aggregate of subatomic
parts. Rather, inclusive of these parts there is a series of atomic
occasions of experience that make the atom into an integrated whole.
Molecules can likewise be thought to be unified by molecular occasions of
experience. The same can be thought to be true of macromolecules,
viruses, etc. The living cell is dominated by living occasions of
experience. Finally, the multicelled animal is not just a democracy of
cells, but has a dominating member, the series of experiences constituting
the soul.
Now, when we make a
conscious decision, the causation involves all these levels—besides the
previously mentioned fact that conscious experience arises to a great
extent from integrations made at a preconscious level. This preconscious
experience involved enormously complex integrations of data from various
parts of the brain. These parts of the brain are composed of brain
cells. The functioning of the cells is partly determined by that of their
organelles, etc., and those in turn by their molecules, and those in turn
by their atoms, and those in turn by their- subatomic constituents. Bohm
uses this example as an illustration of the fact that what is implicate in
relation to a higher level (e.g., the functioning of brain cells is
implicate in relation to the person’s conscious decision) is in turn
explicate in relation to a lower level (the functioning of the cells is
explicate in relation to that of their molecules). This surely points to
an important truth.
However, it does not
provide an example of a kind of “implicate order” that modern science has
overlooked. This attempt to explain the functioning of organisms in terms
of their elementary constituents has been at the heart of the
reductionistic drive of modern science. So this way of employing the
implicate-explicate distinction does not provide a parallel to the kind of
implicate order that is in principle hidden to the current methods of
modern science.
Furthermore, to use
the hierarchy in a compound individual as an example of levels of
implication suggests reductionistic determinism. To say that our
experience is (merely) an “explication” of what was already implicit in
the brain is to reduce the mind to the brain. And if the functioning of
the brain cells is likewise said to be an explication of that of their
constituent molecules, and so on down, the logical conclusion is that
human experience is in principle totally explainable in terms of the
functioning of subatomic particles. (And then whether they are thought
really to be materialistic particles or world tubes of momentary
enfoldings and unfoldings is irrelevant, at least to the issue of human
freedom.)
In Whitehead’s
portrayal of the compound individual, the terminology of implicate and
explicate orders would not be appropriate for the relation between any two
levels. The key point again is the universality of Creativity. Individuals
at every level have their own degree of Creativity, and hence power for
self-determination, vis-à-vis the influences upon them (from above,
below, or across). So individuals at no level are mere explications of
what was already implied at some other level. In fact, far from being
reductionistic, Whitehead’s view implies that individuals at the higher
levels have more creative power than individuals at lower levels. For
example, although it may be that brain and mind (or soul) have about the
same degree of influence upon each other, the soul is at each moment
one occasion of experience whereas the brain is composed of billions.
This suggests that the soul-experience has billions of times more creative
power (to determine itself and then others) than an individual
cell-experience. Accordingly, from this perspective, it would be very
misleading to suggest epiphenomenalism by seeing each higher level as an
explication of a lower one. (And it would also be erroneous to speak,
with Christian Science and other forms of hypophenomenalism, of the lower
levels as mere explications of the higher, as if cancer always resulted
from a screwed-up psyche and never from a polluted environment.)
9.3.5. Electromagnetic, Geometric, and Extensive Societies
The point of the
above discussion is that the hierarchy involved in a compound individual,
such as a human being, is a hierarchy of actualities, and as such
it cannot be simply a hierarchy of implication and explication, since all
actualities embody self-determining Creativity. However, there is another
kind of hierarchy of societies in Whitehead. Whitehead suggests that all
compound individuals (discussed above) are specialized societies
(developed to foster more intense experiences) within more general forms
of social order. These latter societies are related in a somewhat
Chinese-box style, with the less general orders being totally included in
more general ones.
The first level of
generality, he suggests, is the electromagnetic society, composed of
electromagnetic occasions. The order of this society has physical
relationships determining the importance of one family of straight lines,
one definition of congruence, and systematic law—which is statistical (PR
98). This society is our present “cosmic epoch.” It is set within a far
wider society, the geometric society, which has those relationships which
make possible definable and hence measurable straight lines. But there
can be competing definitions of straight lines and hence alternative
systems of metrical geometry, so this geometrical society could be patient
of cosmic epochs quite different from our own electromagnetic one. And
this geometric society is set in turn within a far vaster society of pure
extension, the properties of which express “the mere fact of ‘extensive
connection,’ of ‘whole and part,’ of various types of ‘geometrical
elements’ derivable by ‘extensive abstraction’; but excluding the
introduction of more special properties by which straight lines are
definable and measurability thereby introduced” (PR 96f.)
In distinction from
the hierarchy involved in a compound individual, this is a hierarchy of
abstractions, not of actualities. The point of this hierarchy is not that
there are actual occasions anywhere that are characterized only by
extensive connection without any more special characteristics. Some more
specialized characteristics, such as those specifying ours as a geometric
and then an electromagnetic epoch, are necessary. The point is that the
less general features are contingent. Whitehead suggests that the most
general level of characteristics, that of pure extensiveness, is probably
metaphysical and applies to all possible worlds. (Hence this feature of
our world would be parallel to God, Creativity, Eternal Forms, and
Creaturehood as such in being an eternally necessary feature of reality.)
But there could be creatures whose extensive connectedness was such as to
make a different type of geometry important, or even such as to make
geometry unimportant altogether. These features of our particular world
are contingent. They are obviously compatible with the most general
feature of extensive connection. In this sense one could say that the
higher, more specialized forms of order were implicit in the deeper
levels, but this language would again be misleading. For the more
specialized forms of order were not necessitated by the more general.
This is again due to the ubiquity of Creativity. Those actual occasions
which, billions upon billions of years ago, began exemplifying those forms
of order which now dominate our world were not following mere necessity.
Some degree of self-determination (probably on the part of both God and
the creatures) and hence contingency was involved. The world could have
been otherwise. To speak of explication of implicate orders here would
mute this contingency.
We can say
that the deeper orders are implicit in the higher. The more general is
implied by the less general. This shows the limitation of the Chinese-box
analogy, for the smaller boxes can be removed from the larger without
essential loss. But the characteristics of our cosmic epoch, with its
laws and dominant family of straight lines, simply would not exist apart
from the features making geometry in general important; and these
geometric relationships in turn imply extensive relatedness in general.
So the more particular implies the more general, i.e., the more general is
implicit in the more particular.
If we are going to
use the language of implicate and explicate in regard to this
hierarchy, we would have to say that the more general levels of order were
an explication of the more special ones (since they are implied by the
more special ones). But no one would want to say this. And since we
cannot appropriately say the opposite—that the more specialized are mere
explications of the more general—it turns out that the implicate-explicate
scheme does not apply at all to this hierarchy of abstraction, just as it
failed to apply to the hierarchy of actuality.
Again we see that
the key reason is the hypothesis that Creativity is the ultimate reality,
embodied in all actualities. If Bohm accepts this notion, the
implicate-explicate distinction will have to be disassociated from
hierarchical notions. There are hierarchical features of the world
and there are features of the world illumined by the implicate-explicate
distinction, but these are different features.
9.4.
Conclusion
The status of
freedom, causality, and time are in the same boat. The denial of one
implies, finally, the denial of the others. If time is unreal, in the
sense that from an ultimate perspective there is no distinction between
past, present, and future, then there can be no freedom, in the sense of
self-determination in the moment. For if what still seems undetermined
and hence future “right now” is in reality already as determinate as the
past, then my feeling that I am deciding something in my apparently
self-determining activity is an illusion. Likewise, if time is unreal,
then there is no real causation, as distinct from logical implication. If
the relations of the present with the past and the future are symmetrical,
then the present implies the future as fully as it implies the past.
Hence we can say that we cause the future only in the same sense as we
cause the past, and this empties the word of any meaning.
Likewise, if there
is no freedom, then time is ultimately unreal. (Again, I speak of the
ultimate reality of time, not to reify it as another actuality alongside
events, but as shorthand for the ultimate validity of the distinction
between past, present, and future.) For if what happens a minute from
now, a year from now, a million years from now, was already implicit in
the world at this moment, with no genuine alternatives, then time is an
illusion. The distinction between past, present, and future is merely an
illusion: every event eternally exists, fully determinate. Time is
invention or it is nothing, as Bergson said. So if there is no freedom,
time is nothing. Similar reflections would show the dependence of
causality upon time and likewise of time and freedom upon causation.
I have suggested
that Bohm could formulate his intuition of wholeness without contradicting
our deepest intuitions about time, freedom, and causation if he would
highlight certain themes already present in his writings and drop others.
In particular, the insight that the basic reality is a holomovement, or
what Whitehead calls Creativity, should be strengthened, to stress that
every event of enfolding and unfolding embodies this self-creative
dynamism. Second, God should not be equated with this dynamic activity
but regarded as the all-inclusive, intelligent, compassionate embodiment
of it. Third, the distinction between implicate and explicate should be
limited primarily to (1) the distinction between an event in itself (as
subject) and an event for others (as causal superject) and (2) the
distinction between the actual world with its enfolding and unfolding and
the world as perceived through sensory experience. It can also be
helpfully used for the distinction between unconscious and conscious
experience, if it is clarified that the conscious aspect of
experience is not merely an epiphenomenal explication of the unconscious
depths. Fourth, the hierarchical features of reality should be stressed,
but not in terms of the implicate-explicate distinction, since this
application would contradict the ultimacy of creativity or holomovement
and thereby threaten our deep convictions about time, freedom, and
causation.
Abbreviations of Bohm’s Works
RS “Response to
Schindler’s Critique of My Wholeness and the Implicate Order,”
Interna-tional Philosophical Quarterly 20, 4 (December 1982):329-39
RV “Conversations
between Rupert Sheldrake, Renee Weber, David Bohm,” ReVISION 5, 2
(Fall 1982)
S “A Series of
Talks Given at Syracuse University, September, 1982” (Unpublished
manuscript)
W Wholeness and
the Implicate Order (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980)
Abbreviations of Whitehead’s Works
PR Process and
Reality, Corrected edition, ed. David Ray Griffin and Donald W.
Sherburne (New York: Free Press, 1978)
RM
Religion in the
Making
(New York: Meridian
Books, 1960)
Posted May 8,
2007