From
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
950:191-205 (2001). Abstract: “Addressing the title’s question from the
perspective of Whitehead’s process theology, fourteen basic
notions of which are explained, I argue that the universe is
not designed in six common senses of that notion: It was not
created out of nothing, all at once, through punctuated
creationism, from a blueprint, solely for humans, or even with
humans specifically in mind. But it is designed in two looser
senses of the term: It reflects a divine aim at richness of
experience, and it involved a divine establishment of this
cosmic epoch’s fundamental contingent principles—an idea that
is consistent with process theism’s view of divine power as
purely persuasive.”
Is the Universe Designed?
Yes and No
David Ray Griffin
I have been asked to
address the question “Is the universe designed?” from the
perspective of process theology, which is based on the
philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947). The name
“process theology” is derived from the title of Whitehead’s
major work, Process and Reality,1
which he wrote in the late 1920s after coming to Harvard to
teach philosophy. Whitehead had been educated at Cambridge
University in England, where he wrote a dissertation in 1884 on
Maxwell’s Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism and then
taught mathematics, including mathematical physics, until
1910. In some circles, Whitehead is best known for the major
work of this period, Principia Mathematica, which he
co-authored with his former pupil, Bertrand Russell. In the
next period of his life, spent in London, Whitehead increasingly
devoted himself to the philosophy of nature. After coming to
Harvard in 1924, he turned to metaphysics, which, as he understood
the term, differed from the philosophy of nature by including
the human subject within the scope of that which is to be explained.
The most important task of metaphysical cosmology, he came to
believe, is to reconcile our scientific intuitions with our
religious, ethical, and aesthetic intuitions, which can only
be done by developing a world view that is equally satisfactory
for the scientific and the religious communities.2
Whitehead had been
an atheist, or at least an agnostic, during most of his adult
life. But shortly after beginning to develop his metaphysical
cosmology, he came to the view that, if we are to give a fully
rational account of the universe—meaning one that is both
coherent and adequate to all the relevant facts, including the
various dimensions of human experience—it is necessary to posit
a non-local actuality. Although Whitehead used the term “God”
for this actuality, the divine reality to which he referred,
unlike the deity of traditional theism in the West, did not
possess omnipotence as traditionally understood. Whitehead’s
turn to a form of theism did nothing to lessen his antipathy to
the idea of a divine being who, while having the power to
prevent evil, refuses to do so.
If faced with our
question “Is the universe designed?,” Whitehead’s answer, like
the answer to most Yes or No questions about complex issues,
would have been Yes and No. This ambivalent answer reflects
the fact that the notion of a designed universe has many
connotations, not all of which imply all the others. I will
deal with eight possible meanings of this notion, suggesting
that, from the perspective of Whiteheadian process theology,
the answer to six of them is No, but that there are two senses
in which we can speak of the universe as designed.
Some Basic Whiteheadian
Notions
To explain the
Whiteheadian position on these issues, I will need to
presuppose many of the fundamental ideas in the system.
Unfortunately, to explain these ideas would take several hours,
if not days. All I can do here is briefly sketch them, hoping
that this sketch will be sufficient to make the ensuing discussion
at least somewhat intelligible. Another problem for my assignment
arises from the fact that Whitehead’s position involves a rejection
of many of the ideas of modern philosophy, some of which have
been widespread in scientific circles, so that Whitehead’s
alternative notions may strike many of you as implausible, if
not outrageous. Unfortunately, to defend these notions would
take days, if not weeks. So, although I have argued elsewhere
that all of these ideas can be defended as more plausible than
their alternatives,3
I can here only ask you suspend incredulity, granting these
basic Whiteheadian notions as premises for the sake of discussion.
I will briefly discuss fourteen of these notions.
1. The
most fundamental units of which the universe is composed are
momentary spatiotemporal events, rather than enduring things.
This notion, which Whitehead shares with Buddhism, fits with
the discovery that some of the so-called elementary particles
exist on the order of a billionth of a second, so that they
would more appropriately be called events.
2.
Each momentary event is an embodiment of creativity,
from which the physicist’s energy is an
abstraction. By enlarging the notion of energy to
include all that Whitehead meant by “creativity,” we could
say that the universe is made up of energetic events.
This is true even of so-called empty space, which means that
Whitehead’s ideas here are consonant with recent thinking
about the (“virtual” or “false”) vacuum.
3.
One respect in which this more inclusive energy, this
creativity, goes beyond energy as usually conceived
in physics is that it includes an element of internal
determination, or self-determination, so that no
energetic event is wholly determined by the forces
acting upon it from without. The epistemic indeterminacy of
the world at the quantum level reflects an element of
ontological self-determinacy.
4. The
energetic events are, of course, not simply embodiments
of raw, unformed energy, but of in-formed energy, with
the different types of things being different
because they contain different forms, different
in-formation.
5. Each
event prehends aspects of prior events, and thereby aspects
of their informed energy, into itself. The term
“prehend” is simply “apprehend” without the prefix, meant
to indicate that this response to other things need not
be a conscious process. The crucial point here is
that each event is internally related to prior
events. That is, rather than being a solid piece of
stuff, or a Leibnizian monad devoid of windows, each event is
internally constituted by its relations to prior events.
Here Whitehead’s view seems virtually identical with
some Buddhist understandings of the “dependent origination”
of all things.
6. Enduring
things, such as electrons, protons, and photons, exist
because a particular form of energy is repeated by a long
series of energetic events, perhaps dozens, hundreds,
thousands, millions, or even billions of times per
second. That is, although each event is influenced
by all prior events to at least some slight degree,
an event in an enduring individual is primarily constituted
by its prehension and thereby internalization of the form
of energy that was embodied by its predecessors in
the enduring individual to which it belongs. The proton
endures, in other words, because each of its
protonic events essentially repeats the form of its
predecessors, with this repetition going on, not
quite endlessly, but for many billions of years. (I
illustrated this point with protons, because they seem to have
an especially high degree of tolerance for monotony.)
7. Low-grade
enduring individuals can, in certain combinations, give
rise to higher-level enduring individuals, as quarks and
gluons give rise to protons and neutrons, and these
latter individuals combine with electrons to give
rise to atoms and molecules, with still higher forms
of enduring individuals perhaps being macromolecules,
prokaryotic cells, organelles (which may be captured
prokaryotic cells), eukaryotic cells, and the psyches
of animals, from gnats to human beings. These
higher-level enduring individuals are, by
hypothesis, not simply complex arrangements of lower-level
individuals. Rather, they involve higher-level energetic
events, with their own unity of response to their
environments. This emergence of higher-level units is possible
because of internal relations. That is, because each
event is internally constituted out of the things in
its environment, a more complex environment can
provide the basis for more complex events and thereby more
complex enduring individuals.4
8.
The most complex enduring individuals on our planet,
evidently, are the psyches of human beings. Although
there is no ontological difference between the psyches of
humans and those of other animals, as some dualists
hold, or between animal psyches and lower-level
enduring individuals, as other dualists hold, or
even between living and non-living individuals, as vitalists
hold, there are enormous differences of degree in terms
of capacities for prehension and self-determination.
Because our own existence is not entirely different from
that of lower-grade enduring individuals, there are
some features of our existence that can be
generalized all the way down, to the simplest types of enduring
individuals.
9. The
most general of these features is experience, this feature
being presupposed by the two features already mentioned,
namely, prehension and self-determination. I call
this position, accordingly, panexperientialism.
This notion is one of the features of this position that is
often thought to make it self-evidently subject to
one-word refutations, such as “implausible,”5
because we all know that sticks and stones have no
experience and exercise no self-determination. The
“pan” in panexperientialism, however, does not mean all
things whatsoever but only all true individuals—the
things I have been referring to as energetic events and
enduring individuals. Even then, the power of the
modern worldview, which was adopted in the
seventeenth century in opposition to views suggesting
that matter involves sentience and spontaneity,6
is such that most philosophers, scientists, and
theologians refuse to entertain this idea
seriously. One result of this refusal is that dualism
and materialism, the two positions allowed by the modern
worldview, have made little advance on the mind-body
problem beyond the stand-off between Descartes and Hobbes three
and a half centuries ago. I have recently shown that
Whiteheadian panexperientialism can, at long last,
resolve this problem, incorporating the strengths of
dualism and materialism while avoiding their weaknesses.7
10. Another
of these generalizable features, both presupposed and
implied by experience, is time, or temporal process. Because
each event prehends into itself aspects of prior events,
irreversible time obtains even for the most elementary
individuals. Time as we know it—that is, as an asymmetrical,
irreversible pro-cess—did not have to wait for the emergence of
human experience, as some think, or for life, as others think,
or even for aggregations of atoms subject to entropy, as still
others think. Rather, time is already real for individual atoms,
even for their constituent electrons, protons, and quarks.8
11. Indeed,
time is real even prior to the existence of enduring
individuals. For Whitehead, the ancient idea that the origin
of our universe involved the emergence of a particular form of
order out of chaos—an idea that was suggested by Plato, the
book of Genesis,9
and many other ancient cosmologies—is essentially correct. For
Whitehead, the chaos would have been a situation in which
extremely trivial energetic events happen at random, meaning
that none of them would have been organized into enduring
individuals, not even individuals as simple as quarks. Since
by a “thing” we usually mean an enduring thing, which retains
its identity through time, the chaos prior to the creation of
our world was a state of no-thing-ness. In this sense, we can
say that our world was created out of nothingness. But, as
Russian Orthodox philosophical theologian Nicholas Berdyaev put
it, this was a state of relative nothingness, not absolute
nothingness. In any case, in this chaotic situation, there would
still have been time, or temporal process, because each random
event would have prehended prior events and been prehended by
succeeding events. (It should not be surprising, of course,
that a position known as “process theology” would consider temporal
process to be ultimately real.)
12. In
addition to all the local events constituting the universe,
there is an enduring individual comprised of an
everlasting series of nonlocal, all-inclusive
events.10
Rather than existing outside the universe, in the
sense of existing independently of any realm of finite
entities, this nonlocal individual is essentially
the soul of the universe, providing the unity that
makes it a universe. This everlasting individual is the home
of all possibilities. By virtue of being prehended by
all local events, it is the primary source of both
order and novelty in the universe. Being good, in the two-fold
sense of having friendliness and compassion for all
sentient creatures, as well as being ubiquitous,
everlasting, and the source of the world’s order, it
can be considered divine.
13. The
influence of this divine individual, rather than ever involving
supernatural interruptions of the world’s normal causal processes,
is a natural part of these processes. The fact that process
theology regards the God-world relation as a fully natural relation
is due in part to its panexperientialism. One of the reasons
for the decline of theism since the seventeeenth century has
been puzzlement as to how a cosmic mind could influence nature,
understood in mechanistic or materialistic terms. The God-world
problem was to some extent simply the mind-body problem writ
large. Panexperientialism, by showing how our minds can influence
our bodies, simultaneously shows how a Cosmic Mind could influence
the physical world.
14. Although
this divine individual, being ubiquitous, exerts influence
on all finite events, it cannot fully determine either
the inner constitution or the external effects of
any of them. Although creative power, which is the
two-fold power to exercise self-determination and then to exert
efficient causation on others, is embodied by this divine
individual, this two-fold power is also embodied by
all finite events. The power of the divine individual in
the world, accordingly, is the power to evoke and to
persuade, never the power to coerce, in the sense of
the power unilaterally to determine.
As this brief
summary indicates, Whiteheadian process theology is not
simple. But, as Whitehead observed, all simple theologies “are
shipwrecked upon the rock of the problem of evil.”11
This point is central to our topic, because the decline in the
belief that our universe is in any sense designed has surely
resulted from the problem of evil as much as from any
scientific developments. In any case, given these fourteen
notions of process theology, I turn now to the question of
whether our universe is designed. I will begin with six senses
in which, from a Whiteheadian perspective, the universe is not
designed.
Six Senses in Which the
Universe Is Not Designed
1. Not created
out of absolute nothingness: Sometimes the idea the our
universe is designed means that it was brought into existence
ex nihilo, with the nihil in this phrase taken to
mean absolute nothingness, so that even the mere fact that there
are finite actualities and temporal processes is due to divine
design. Process theology rejects this view, holding instead
that our universe, with its contingent laws of nature, is a
particular instantiation of the universe, which exists eternally,
embodying necessary, metaphysical principles. So, with reference
to the papers by Jaroslav Pelikan and Anindita Balslev, we can
say that the idea that the universe had a beginning, associated
with Jerusalem, and the idea that the universe has always existed,
associated with Athens and India, are both correct.
2. Not created
all at once: Sometimes the idea that the universe is
designed means that it, with all its present species of life,
was created all at once, or at least virtually so.
Process theology rejects this idea, agreeing instead
with the consensus that the present form of our
universe has come about through a long evolutionary
process.
3. Not
progressively created out of nothing: Sometimes, as in the
thought of Alvin Plantinga and Phillip Johnson,12
the idea that the universe is designed means that,
although our present world came about over billions
of years, each new species along the way was created
ex nihilo. This view, known as “progressive
creationism”—or, more fashion-ably, “punctuated creationism”—is
rejected by process theology, which accepts the
evolutionary view that all new species have arisen through
descent with modification from prior species. With
regard to the common questions as to why God created
the world in such a simple state and then took so
long to bring it to the present state, process theology’s
answer is that this is the only way that God could create
a world.
4. Not
preprogrammed from the outset: Some theists, such as
Rudolf Otto early in the twentieth century, have
held that, although God has never intervened in the
world since its creation, every detail of the evolutionary
pro-cess is designed, because every evolutionary sequence
was preprogrammed.13
Even the thought of Charles Darwin, with its deism
and determinism, was not free from this implication, although
this implication of Darwin’s thinking existed in strong
tension with his belief in the contingency of
evolutionary developments.14
Process theology rejects this notion of deistic design,
holding more consistently than did Darwin to the
contingency of every development in every evolutionary
sequence, grounding this ubiqui-tous contingency in the
doctrine that all individual events involve an
element of self-determination. Evolutionary developments
thereby involve chance in an ontological, not merely an
epistemic, sense. Because the self-determination
that exists at the quantum level is magnified, rather than
being canceled out, in higher-level individuals, the
contingencies increase in the later stages of
evolution. The present world cannot be considered, even
approximately, as simply the inevitable outworking
of the Big Bang.15
5. Not
created solely for human beings: Sometimes the idea that
the universe is designed means the anthropocentric notion—held
by William Paley, the utilitarian theologian studied by Darwin—that
the universe was designed solely or at least primarily for the
sake of human beings. According to this notion of design, the
value of other species is their utility for human beings. Process
theology rejects this anthropocentrism, holding instead that
every individual of every species has both intrinsic value,
meaning value in and for itself, and ecological value, meaning
value for the ecosystem. These two forms of value would have
existed if human beings had never appeared and will continue
to exist after we have departed.
6. Human beings
not inevitable:
Sometimes the idea that the universe is designed means that
it was designed to bring forth our own species, just as
it is. Process theology’s rejection of this
connotation is implied by its insistence on contingency, rooted
in the self-determination that has pervaded the
evolutionary process. In the evolutionary sequence
that led to Homo sapiens, there were countless
contingent developments. If a different possibility
had been actualized in any of these cases, beings
exactly like us would not exist. If a different possibility
had been actualized in any of the more crucial cases, no
beings even remotely similar to us would exist.
Now, having
clarified several senses in which process theology does not
think the universe is designed, I turn to two senses in which
process theology thinks that it is.
Two Senses in Which the Universe Is Designed
The idea of divine
“design” is not one that process theologians naturally use,
because it suggests that the creation of our universe came
about in accordance with a detailed blueprint, prepared in
advance. But if we understand the term “design” in a looser
sense, to mean that the universe reflects some sort of purpose,
then process theologians can speak of the universe as designed
in two senses. First, the evolutionary process is viewed as
reflecting a divine aim at increasing richness of experience, a
directionality that is reflected in the rise of life and then
the more complex forms of life. Second, the fact that our
universe was able to bring forth life presupposed a basic
cosmological order that can, with less qualification, be
described as designed. I will discuss these two types of design
in order.
Design in the Sense of a Divine Aim Towards Richness of Experience
Physicists, we are
told, think of the universe as a physics experiment. Whitehead
came to regard it as an aesthetic experiment, with the physics
experi-ment being simply an aspect of this larger project. To
explain: Experience is the only thing that is intrinsically
valuable, meaning valuable in and for itself. Every individual,
by hypothesis, has at least some slight degree of experience
and thereby some slight degree of intrinsic value. But the
intrinsic value of the simplest individuals, judged in terms of
the aesthetic criteria of harmony, complexity, and intensity of
experience, must be extremely trivial, compared with the
intrinsic value of a human being, or even a bat. If, as Thomas
Nagel has emphasized, we cannot imagine what it is like to be a
bat,16
far less can we imagine what it is like to be at atom, or even
an amoeba. The divine aim, by hypothesis, has been to bring
about conditions that allow for the emergence of individuals
with more complex modes of experience and thereby the capacity
for greater intrinsic value. This aim is reflected in the
increasing complexity that, even allowing for all necessary
qualifications, clearly characterizes the evolutionary process.17
The slowness of this
process reflects the fact that the power behind this aim is not
omnipotent in the traditional sense, not essentially the only
center of power. Each event, having its own power of
self-determination, can either adopt or resist divinely
proffered novel possibilities through which the present
situation could be transcended. And this present situation is
supported by the power of the past, which weighs heavily on the
present. Charles Peirce and William James had suggested that
the so-called laws of nature are really its most long-standing
habits,18
which would mean that any type of enduring individual, such as
a proton, a DNA molecule, or a living cell, would be a more or
less long-standing habit. Peirce held that the longer a habit
persists, the stronger it tends to become. This idea led him
to the conclusion that the universe would become increasingly
deterministic, as the habits of nature became stronger and stronger,
thereby imposing themselves more and more heavily on the present.
Whitehead, while endorsing the idea that the laws of nature
are habits,19
avoided the idea of increasing determinism partly by means of
his doctrine of the divine reality as constantly presenting
alternative possibilities. This divine influence, however,
cannot unilaterally determine either what new possibility, if
any, will be evoked or when this development will occur,
because the divine evocative power is always competing with the
power of the past embodied in the habits of enduring individuals.
It may take, accordingly, hundreds, thousands, or even millions
of years for an alternative possibility to be evoked into existence.
Although this
hypothesis is consistent with both the tempo and the direction
of the evolutionary process, it might be thought that it goes
against a scientifically established randomness in the
process. But the idea that all variations are random has more
than one meaning. I have already endorsed one possible
meaning, which is that variations involve chance in the ontological
sense, an idea that Darwin himself and some neo-Darwinists have
rejected. A meaning that many neo-Darwinists do insist upon
is that variations are random in every other possible sense,
which would exclude their being due even in the slightest to
any sort of aim that would give a bias toward variations of
a particular sort, such as variations that lead to greater
structural complexity and thereby greater richness of
experience. But the neo-Darwinian insistence that evolution is
random in this sense is simply philosophical dogma, not
grounded in any empirical discovery. The random-ness that is
central to neo-Darwinism as a scientific theory is randomness
in a third sense,20
according to which there is no tendency for variations to be
adaptational, that is, advantageous for survival in the
environment in which they occur. And the kind of tendency that
process theology posits is not in conflict with randomness in
this strict sense, because there is no necessary correlation
between increased richness of experience and success in the
struggle for survival. To give a human example: The emergence
of the capacity to do higher mathematics, while it may have
increased the satisfaction of some early human beings on the
savannas of Africa, would not have increased the likelihood of
their sowing their wild genes. The criterion of greater
richness of experience is not in tension with neo-Darwinian
randomness, except insofar as this randomness is used as a
pseudo-scientific front for antitheistic bias.
The divine aim
towards greater richness of experience means that there is, in
spite of what I said earlier about the contingency of human
beings, a sense in which we can regard ourselves as intended.
That is, insofar as human experience involves dimensions that
give it the capacity for greater intrinsic value than that
enjoyed by our evolutionary predecessors, we can say that we
reflect the divine aim. Although human beings as such were not
intended, human-like beings were, insofar as they were possible.
This would mean that, on some other planets in the universe
with the conditions for life to emerge and to evolve for many
billions of years, we should expect there to be creatures that,
no matter how different in physical constitution and appearance,
would share some of our capacities, such as those for mathematics,
music, and morality, or, more generally, truth, beauty, and
goodness.
These capacities,
however, imply the capacities for lying, for ugliness, and for
immorality, as exemplified, say, by genocide and ecological
destruction. Must we not conclude, therefore, that the divine
individual of process theology is as responsible for evil as
was the deity of traditional theism? It is true that process
theology’s deity is responsible for evil in one sense, namely,
that if human beings had not been evoked into existence, the
world would have been free from all the evils caused and
experienced by human beings. The question of theodicy,
however, is whether the divine reality is responsible in such a
way as to be indictable, that is, blameworthy.
With regard to this
question, process theism differs from traditional theism in two
crucial respects. In the first place, given the omnipotence
attributed to the deity of traditional theism, that deity could
have created beings who were identical to us in virtually all
respects, having the capacity for realizing most of the values
we enjoy, differing only by having much less, or even no, power
to bring about evil. Because this traditional deity created
our world ex nihilo, all the principles of our world
were freely chosen. There were no metaphysical principles
lying in the nature of things, beyond divine volition. In process
theology, by contrast, such principles do exist, and one of
these principles is that an increase in the capacity for richness
of experience is impossible without a correlative increase in
freedom and the power to affect other beings. This principle
means that every increase in the capacity for good entails an
equal increase in the capacity for evil. Any being with our
capacities to experience and create good, therefore, would
necessarily have our capacities to experience and cause evil.
Insofar as we think of the divine individual as confronting a
choice with regard to the existence of human-like beings, the
choice was only between having beings approximately like us,
with our capacities for evil as well as for good, or no
human-like beings whatsoever. The deity of process theology
can be indicted because of human evil, therefore, only by those
who can honestly say that our planet would have been better
without human-like beings altogether.21
A second crucial
difference between the two types of theism is that, according
to traditional theism, every instance of evil that has occurred
could have been unilaterally prevented by God. One version of
traditional theism, to be sure, says that God gave us genuine
freedom, so that we can freely choose to do evil. It remains
the case, however, that the deity of traditional theism could
always intervene either to determine our decisions or to cancel
out the natural effects thereof—hence the anger of virulent
antitheists such as Stephen Weinberg. In process theism, by
contrast, the divine power cannot do either of these. Although
the human degree of freedom would not exist if the divine power
had not led the evolutionary process to bring human beings into
existence, now that we do exist, the divine power cannot cancel
out our power to make our own decisions and to inflict them on
others. The sense of meaning that comes from seeing the
evolutionary process as divinely influenced is not, therefore,
undermined or rendered horrible by the conclusion that the
“divine” influence is actually demonic, or at least
indifferent.22
Design in the Sense of the Establishment of the Most Fundamental
Contingent Principles of Our Cosmic Epoch
I will conclude by
briefly explaining the second sense in which process theology
can regard our universe as designed. This second sense
involves the much-discussed idea that our universe from the
outset evidently embodied a number of “cosmic constants” that
give the impression of being finely tuned in relation to each
other, because if any of them were slightly different, life
could never have evolved. And they do not seem to be simply
“habits,” as usually understood—that is, to be modes of
behavior that have developed gradually and are only usually,
rather than always, followed. Some traditional theists have
used this fact as new evidence that our universe is the product
of Omnipotent Intelligence. Such theists might argue that, even
if process theism, with its non-omnipotent deity, can do justice
to the world’s evil, it cannot do justice to the best scientific
account of how our universe originated. A divine being whose
power can be resisted by the creatures could not, they might
argue, have imposed all of these mathematical values with sufficient
precision to pull off an initial creative event, such as a big
bang, that would bring about all the conditions necessary for
life to be possible in portions of the resulting universe. Although
that conclusion might at first glance seem to follow from what
I said earlier, I argue that it does not.
My argument is that,
in a chaotic state prior to the beginning of our cosmic epoch,
the two reasons why there is usually so much resistance to
divine ideals would not apply. One of these reasons is that,
as the evolutionary process increasingly brings forth more
complex individuals, the world thereby has creatures with
increasingly greater capacity for self-determination and
thereby increasingly greater capacity to resist divine influence.
In a chaotic state between cosmic epochs, however, the events
would be extremely trivial, with a vanishingly small capacity
to exercise self-determination.
The second reason
why divine influence usually encounters so much resistance is
that the divine intention to instill new ideals, meaning new
possible modes of being and interacting, is usually in
competition with the power of the past, the modes of being that
constitute the essence of enduring individuals. However, in
the postulated chaos between the running down of one cosmic
epoch and the starting up of another, there would, by
definition, be no enduring individuals, and therefore no
entrenched modes of being to force themselves upon present events.
The chaos would not be absolute, to be sure, because events
would still exemplify the necessary, metaphysical principles,
which by definition obtain in all possible worlds, including
the relatively chaotic periods between cosmic epochs. But there
would be no contingent cosmological principles constituting
well-entrenched habits. In this situation, therefore, the divine
influence, in seeking to get a set of contingent principles
embodied in the universe, would have no competition from any
other contingent principles.
In the first instant
of the creation of a particular universe, accordingly, divine
evocative power could produce quasi-coercive effects. A divine
spirit, brooding over the chaos, would only have to think “Let
there be X!”—with X standing for the finely-tuned set of
contingent principles embodied in our world at the outset. To
say this is not to suggest that this effect would necessarily
have occurred immediately. It is also not to deny the
possibility that our universe might have been preceded by a
number of brief universes, which were not sufficiently
fine-tuned to last very long. But it is to suggest an alternative
to the three major ways of thinking of the laws of physics of
our universe: that they are necessary, that they exist purely
by chance, or that they are the product of an Omnipotent Designer.
This alternative possibility is that a creator without coercive
power could, in a chaotic situation, produce quasi-coercive
effects. From then on, however, the divine persuasive activity
would always face competition from the power embodied in the
modes of being reflecting these contingent principles, so that
divine power would never again, as long as the cosmic epoch
exists, be able to produce quasi-coercive effects. In this way,
process theism, while maintaining that God’s agency in our universe
is always persuasive, can nevertheless account for the remarkable
contingent order on which our particular universe is based.
This suggestion, I should add, will not be found in Whitehead’s
writings. But it does seem consistent with his position.
In sum: Although
Whiteheadian process theology shares with late modern thought
the rejection of many of the senses in which the universe had
traditionally been thought to be designed, it can speak of our
universe as designed in two significant senses. In doing so,
furthermore, it can arguably do justice to the best scientific
evidence about cosmic and biological evolution without being
undermined by the horrendous evils that have resulted from the
creation of life, especially human life.
Notes and
References
1
Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, corrected edition, ed.
David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne (New York: Free Press, 1978
[original ed. 1929]).
2
Ibid.,
p. 15; Science and the Modern World (New York: Free Press, 1967),
p. vii.
3
For my
most extensive recent defenses, see Unsnarling the World-Knot:
Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind-Body Problem (Berkeley & Los
Angeles: University of California Press, 1998); Religion and Scientific
Naturalism: Overcoming the Conflicts (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 2000), and Reenchantment without Supernaturalism: A Process
Philosophy of Religion (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001).
4
See
the discussion of “compound individuals” in chapt. 9 of my Unsnarling
the World-Knot.
5
I have
discussed the allegation that
panexperientialism
(usually discussed under the term
“panpsychism”)
is implausible in chapt. 7 of Unsnarling the World-Knot.
6
I have
discussed the theological and sociological motives behind the modern
notion of matter as inert and insentient in chapt. 5 of Religion and
Scientific Naturalism.
7
Unsnarling the World-Knot,
especially chapts. 6, 8, and 9.
8
On
this issue, see my
“Introduction: Physics and the Ultimate Significance of
Time,”
[actual title:
"Time and the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness.--A.F.]
David Ray Griffin, ed., Physics and the Ultimate Significance of
Time: Bohm, Prigogine, and Process Philosophy (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1988), pp. 1-48, or my
“Time in Process
Theology,” KronoScope: Journal for the Study of Time, Vol. 1/1-2
(2001), pp. 75-99.
9
For
extensive discussions of the fact that the doctrine of creation ex
nihilo is not a biblical doctrine, see Jon D. Levenson, Creation
and the Persistence of Evil (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1988), and
Gerhard May, Creatio Ex Nihilo: The Doctrine of “Creation out of
Nothing” in Early Christian Thought, trans. A. S. Worrall (Edinburgh:
T & T Clark, 1994).
10
For
arguments for the existence of a divine reality as conceived by
Whiteheadian process theology, see chapt. 5 of my Reenchantment without
Supernatural-ism. For the argument that this reality should be
understood, with Charles Hartshorne, as an everlasting temporal society of
events, rather than, with Whitehead himself, as a single everlasting
actual entity, see chapt. 4 of that book.
11
A.N.
Whitehead,
Religion in the
Making
(1923; New York: Fordham University Press, 1996), p. 77. I have offered a
Whiteheadian solution to the problem of evil in God, Power, and Evil: A
Process Theodicy (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976; 2nd edition
with a new preface, Lanham, MD.: University Press of America, 1991) and
Evil Revisited: Responses and Reconsiderations (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1991). I have explicitly discussed the
connection of this theodicy with the rejection of creatio ex nihilo
in “Creation out of Nothing, Creation out of Chaos, and the Problem of
Evil,” in Encountering Evil: Live Options in Theodicy, 2nd edition,
ed. Stephen T. Davis (Philadelphia, PA: Westminster/John Knox, 2001), pp.
108-125.
[An
earlier (1981) version of this essay is available elsewhere on this site
as “Creation
out of Chaos and the Problem of Evil.”—A.F.]
12
I have
discussed Johnson’s position in “Christian Faith and Scientific
Naturalism: An Appreciative Critique of Phillip Johnson’s Proposal,”
Christian Scholars Review, Vol. 28/2: 308-328 (1998). A modified
version of this critique, dealing also with Plantinga, is contained in
chapt. 3 of Religion and Scientific Naturalism.
13
A
discussion of Otto’s position is included in chapt. 3 of Religion and
Scientific Naturalism.
14
Darwin’s deism and determinism are discussed in chapt. 8, “Creation and
Evolution,” of my Religion and Scientific Naturalism.
15
In
A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes (New York:
Bantam, 1988), Stephen Hawking, while giving up the older ideal of a
completely deterministic science, still says that the goal of science
should be “the discovery of laws that will enable us to predict events up
to the limits set by the uncertainty principle” (p. 173). He evidently
holds, furthermore, that those limits are purely epistemic; as he suggests
we can “still imagine that there is a set of laws that determines events
completely for some supernatural being, who could observe the present
state of the universe without disturbing it” (p. 55).
16
Thomas
Nagel, “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” in his Mortal Questions
(London: Cambridge University Press, 1979).
17
For
recent discussions of whether we can speak of progress in the evolutionary
process, see Matthew H. Nitecki, Evolutionary Progress (Chicago &
London: University of Chicago Press, 1988). I have discussed this issue in
chapt. 8 of Religion and Scientific Naturalism.
18
See
William James, The Principles of Psychology (1890; New York: Dover,
1950), I: 104-105; and Peter Ochs, “Charles Sanders Peirce,” in David Ray
Griffin et al., Founders of Constructive Postmodern Philoso-phy
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993), pp. 43-87, esp. pp.
67-68, 73-75.
19
A. N.
Whitehead, Modes of Thought (1938; New York: Free Press, 1968), p.
154.
20
I have
discussed these different meanings of randomness in chapt. 8 of
Religion and Scientific Naturalism.
21
I have
discussed this point in my three discussions of the problem of evil
mentioned in note 11.
22
Antitheists sometimes charge that revisionary theists can overcome the
problem of evil only by revising the conventional understanding of theism
so drastically that the resulting position is no longer intelligibly
called “theism,” because the resulting referent of the word “God” has been
redefined out of all recognition. That charge does indeed apply to many
modern theologies. But, by showing that the deity of process theism
embodies all the features of what can be called the “generic idea of God”
in cultures primarily shaped by biblically based religions (Evil
Revisited, pp.10-12), I have shown that this charge does not apply to
process theism.
[See
also Griffin’s
summary elsewhere on this site.--AF]
Posted April 16, 2007