Conference paper,
“Eastern Orthodox Theology and Process Thought,” Center for Process
Studies, Claremont, CA, May 8-10, 1986. It is a response to Thomas J.
Hopko, “God and the World: An
Eastern Orthodox Response to Process Theology,” a paper also delivered
at that conference, based on Hopko’s Ph.D. dissertation of the same
title (Fordham Univer-sity, 1982). Griffin’s parenthetical page numbers
without symbols refer to the dissertation. (A list of the papers
delivered at this conference is given
here.)
Protopresbyter Hopko
is the Dean Emeritus of St. Vladimir's Orthodox Theological Seminary.
Posted November 14, 2009
Process Theology and Eastern Orthodox Theology: A
Response to Thomas Hopko
David Ray Griffin
Process theology as it has developed thus far has
primarily been in conversation with Western Christian theology, both
traditional and modern, and with the worldview associated with modern
science, which was to a large extent a product of Western theistic
thinking. Until now there had been little critical engagement with
Eastern Christian thought. We have for the most part been victims and
perpetrators of the typical theological curriculum. Typically, just as
Judaism’s importance is limited to its contribution to Christianity, so
that we lost interest in it after the first century C.E., Eastern
Christianity’s importance is limited to its contribution to Western
theology, so that we lost interest in it after the fifth or sixth
century. There has been little interest in looking at its fundamentally
different way of understanding Christian faith and its consequent
criticisms of Augustinian-based theology. Process theologians for the
most part have apparently shared this lack of interest, even while being
aware that our own way of understanding Christian faith is in some
respects more akin to that of Eastern Orthodoxy than it is to Western
orthodoxy, and that Whitehead himself paid some Eastern theologians the
(for him) highest possible compliment, saying that they had made a
metaphysical improvement upon Plato (AI 215). As far as I know, this
ignorance by process theologians of Eastern Orthodoxy has generally been
matched by an ignorance of process theology on the part of Orthodox
theologians.
In this presentation, and in the dissertation on which
this presentation was based, Thomas Hopko has performed the invaluable
service of beginning the long-needed conversation between process the-ologians
and representatives of Eastern Orthodoxy. In the dissertation, Hopko
initiates this conversation in four ways.
(1)He
mentions several respects in which he believes that process theologians
have misunderstood Eastern Ortho-doxy.
(2)He
points to several differences be-tween the two theological positions,
differences in regard to which he apparently holds Eastern Orthodoxy’s
position to be non-revisable.
(3)He
points out some areas in which the two views agree on the inadequacies
of classical Western theism, but in regard to which he believes that
Orthodoxy provides a more adequate alternative.
(4)
In doing so, he suggests, in response to criticisms and
affirmations by process theology, some ways in Eastern Ortho-doxy can be
re-formulated, without be-ing substantially modified, so as to be more
adequate to Christian faith and experience.
Hopko has naturally and properly initiated the
conversation in terms of the way the relation between process and
Orthodoxy appears from his Orthodox perspective. Rather than giving a
point-by-point reply to his response to process theology, I will respond
to his initiative by first saying how the relation looks to me, from my
process perspective, and why I think this conversation is important.
Then I will turn to some of those particular points on which Eastern
Orthodoxy and process theology, as they have developed thus far, appear
to be at odds.
At the top of my list of similarities between process and
Orthodox theologies is an understanding of salvation. Both traditions
reject the juridical view of the Augustinian tradition according to
which salvation primarily involves a judgment or declara-tion by God as
transcendent. Rather, salvation is understood as a process of
transformation based on the immanence of God in the creature. This
issue is directly related to the point on which Whitehead saw Eastern
theologians as having made an advance on Plato; as opposed to portraying
the world as including merely the image of God and imitations of his
ideas, they portrayed God and the ideas as directly immanent in the
world (AI 215).
Process theology’s stand with Eastern Christianity on
this point puts it not only in opposition with traditional Western
theology but also with the modern Western worldview. This worldview
began in the seventeenth century with a radical dualism between nature
and soul which denied that God could be immanent in nature. As this
dualism was increas-ingly rejected in favor of full-fledged materialism
in the eighteenth, nineteenth, and twentieth centuries, the immanence of
God in the world was rejected altogether. Modern theology has
accordingly had difficulty speaking of incarnation, Holy Spirit,
providence, and inspiration. Process thought’s pan-experientialism,
which rejects both materialism and dualism, provides a new basis for
understanding the immanence of God in all creatures. It is thereby an
ally of Eastern Orthodoxy not only directly against an Augustinianism
which exalts divine transcendence to the detriment of divine immanence,
but also against the modern worldview which is an indirect product of
this Augustinianism.
Closely related to this common stress on divine immanence
is a common stress on a dual mode of divine existence. In the Orthodox
tradition, these two modes are referred to as the divine essence and the
divine energies. The former is the divine existence as transcendent, as
in and for itself; the latter is the divine existence as immanent or
manifest in the world. The crucial point is that the divine energies
are just as divine, just as uncreated, as is the divine essence. Hopko
refers to this distinction as the divine polarity, Eastern style,
contrasting it with Whithead’s distinction between primordial and
consequent natures, and Hartshorne’s distinction between abstract
essence and concrete states. Hopko is right to see that the
Whiteheadian and Hartshornean doctrines of divine dipolarity are quite
different from his own. However, there is another distinction in
process thought which comes much closer to the Orthodox distinction
dubbed by Hopko a kind of divine dipolarity. This is the distinction
between God as subject (with primordial and consequent natures), and God
as superject (which Whitehead once calls the “superjective nature” of
God [PR 88]) God as superject is the whole God (primordial and
consequent) as immanent in the creatures (PR 350-3). This doctrine is
most intelligible if God is understood not as a single everlasting
actual entity, with Whitehead, but with Hartshorne as a “living person,”
meaning a person-ally-ordered society of divine occasions of experi-ence.
On this view, God, like every other actual enti-ty, is first an
experiencing subject, appropriating the feelings of prior occasions of
experience, then a superject, whose feelings and aims are appropriated
by subsequent occasions of experience. Of course, the superjective mode
of the divine existence differs from that of finite actual occasion by
being equally present to every part of the creation. The crucial point,
in regard to Eastern Orthodoxy, is that the superjective mode is as
essential to the divine existence as the subjective mode. For
Whitehead, every actuality is essentially a subject-superject (PR 12).
The superjective mode of existence follows from the subjective mode,
but is not thereby any less essential. In every occasion of experience,
“the many become one” (PR 212); but the rest of the description is that
they “are increased by one,” which implies that it is equally essential
that the one become many. God’s objective or superjective existence in
the many actualities of the immediate and remote past are incorporated.
This idea parallels Hopko’s Orthodox position, that the divine energies
follow causally from the divine essence and yet are equally divine (172,
175). This distinction between the subjective and superjective modes of
divine existence explains how creatures can be said to be “deified”
without abrogating the categorical difference between the creatures and
God.
Co-operation between God and the creatures is a third
point on which process and Eastern Orthodox theologies stand together
against the characteristic emphasis of Western theology. Ever since
Augustine’s anti-Pelagian tracts, the notion of divine-human “synergy,”
or “co-operation,” has been suspect in the West. In spite of the
difficulties created thereby for freedom and theodicy, Western
theologians have tended to equate monotheism with monism, lodging all
power and energy in God, and speaking of “predestination,” and “sole
efficacy of God.” Those theologies, such as Thomism, which have even
given the appearance of freedom vis-à-vis God, have been
criticized as “Pelagian” or “semi-Pelagian.” In Eastern Orthodoxy, by
contrast, “synergy” and “co-operation” have been good words (see 339).
It has said all along what process theologians have said recently, that
God does not effect our salvation unilaterally. Becoming whole or
deified is a co-operative process involving divine initiatives and human
responses.
A fourth area of agreement is theological method. Two
aspects stand out. First, process and Orthodox theologians reject the
Thomistic two-level division of theology into natural and revealed. The
theological construal of the world is a unified whole, with revelation,
experience, and reason being indivisibly involved, regardless of the
feature of reality under discussion. (Hopko has been misled by
Hartshorne, who minimizes the influence of Christianity on his “natural
theology” to a vanishing point, into thinking that John Cobb and most
other process theologians think in terms of a distinction between
“natural” and “revealed” theology.) Second, experience is made
central. Hopko repeatedly emphasizes the priority of lived experience
over any received philosophical system for Orthodoxy (6-8, 26, 91).
Process theolo-gians are fond of Whitehead’s statements that “The
elucidation of immediate experience is the sole justification for any
thought” (PR 4), and that philo-sophy’s “ultimate appeal is to the
general conscious-ness of what in practice we experience” (PR 17).
These broad and important agreements do not mean,
however, that the process and Orthodox traditions, at least as they have
developed thus far, agree on everything. In fact as Hopko makes clear,
there are some radical differences (9). In the remainder of this essay,
I will deal with some of the disagreements, explaining why I as a
process theologian take the position I do and/or indicating why I do not
find persuasive the reason Hopko gives for his position.
Probably the root difference is on the issue of
creatio ex nihilo. There are some strong senses in which process
theologians can affirm this language. (Each actual entity can be said
to be created out of creativity, and creativity is no-thing. Also, each
actual entity is created out of possibilities, which are not “things” in
the usual sense of the term.) But we reject the notion that God created
our world out of a situation in which there were no finite actualities
whatsoever. The ultimate metaphysical reality is creativity, which
involves the many’s becoming one. There could not have been a time (or a
“pre-temporal” situation) in which God existed all alone, as the sole
embodiment of creativity. Creativity requires a multiplicity of
non-divine embodiments as well as divine embodiment. Hence, our
world, which evidently began some fifteen billion years ago, was not
created out of absolute nothingness, but out of a multiplicity of finite
actualities, which were probably in a relatively chaotic situation with
very simple forms of order. For process theologians, this hypo-thesis,
besides following from the basic metaphysical intuition behind process
thought, is also important for reconciling the power and goodness of the
creator with the experienced evil of the world. The fact that it does
not allow for occasional interruptions of the causal powers of the
creatures also seems to be consistent with what experience teaches about
the nature of the world.
For Hopko, it is essential to Christian faith to affirm
creatio ex nihilo in the strong sense; according to which the
world is not necessary to God (232, 239, 242). He even says that the
very nature of theology involves the contemplation of God without a
world (250). He rejects the Whiteheadian distinction between
creativity, as the ultimate metaphysical reality, and God as the
primordial embodiment and characterization of creativity. God must for
Hopko be viewed as the ultimate metaphysical ground, so that the
creativity of the creatures depends on God alone (180, 181).
Closely related in his re-affirmation of the Eastern view
of the trinity, in which the analogy of three persons is used, and the
Word and Spirit are considered acting subjects (207, 211f., 230f.).
This doctrine explains how God can be personal and loving without having
a world to which to relate (183, 227, 336-38).
On what basis does Hopko defend this view of God’s
essential independence of any realm of finitude? His primary appeal is
to experience. He says that creatio ex nihilo is based on the
direct experience of God, and that God shows himself to be a
self-sufficient being, not requiring anything beyond himself to exist
(242, 245). I would like clarification on this point. I believe in the
appeal to direct experience. But I do not see how this appeal can be
used to support the hypothesis that God does not need any world
whatsoever, and that our world was created out of nothing in the
absolute sense. Insofar as the appeal to direct experience can be said
to support either of the competing hypotheses, it would seem to support
that of process theologians, since in human experience new things are
always created out of prior situations. Also, the crucial feature of
the theory of biological evolution is that our present species show
signs of being created out of previous forms.
Hopko adds that although the doctrine of creatio ex
nihilo is not based primarily on the Bible, it is more adequate to
the Biblical revelation that is any alternative view (250). But how
so? Neither the creation of Israel as a nation, or of Christianity as a
new community, was out of nothing. Nor is creatio ex nihilo in
the strong sense affirmed unambiguously in the Bible, with the possible
exception of a few passages. However these passages are read, there are
many more passages, including Genesis 1:1, which more clearly affirm
creation out of something.
Finally, Hopko simply says that “the very heart of the
Christian message . . . is that God can be known . . . without reference
to the world of his creation” (250). But this is a very debatable
interpretation of the heart of the gospel. And, some of us think it is
an interpretation with unhealthy implications, seeming to suggest a form
of Christian salvation that is ultimately indifferent to the fate of
God’s creation. In any case, I ask: What of religious importance hinges
upon the affirmation that God is independent not only of our particular
world, but of worldhood altogether? It is of obvious religious
importance to affirm that God’s existence is not contingent. This means
that it cannot depend upon anything that could contingently fail to
obtain. But process theology’s assertion that God’s existence is always
correlative with that of some world or other does not make God’s
existence dependent upon something contingent, since the assertion is
that some world or other exists necessarily.
There is also obvious religious significance in the
assertion that God is the only individual who exists necessarily and
eternally. But this affirmation is not threatened by process theology.
Some set of finite actual occasions must exist at any time, but there
is no finite individual, i.e., personally-ordered society, which exists
necessarily and eternally. God is the one and only individual who has
always existed. What of religious importance is added by the affirmation
that God can exist all alone, without any realm of finites at all?
One aspect of the Eastern position, as articulated by
Hopko, that I fail to understand is how the doctrine that the world is
unnecessary to God is consistent with the doctrine that the emanating
energies of God are not accidental, but necessary and uncreated (176,
247). The outgoing energies of God would seem to require some sort of
world to go out to. Hence, if the divine energies are not accidental to
God, then the existence of some sort of world would seem not to be
accidental. If this is not the case, then the parallel I suggested
above between Orthodoxy’s “divine energies” and “White-head’s “divine
superjects” would have to be revised.
A second major point of difference raised by Hopko
involves the question of divine impassibility in relation to divine
responsiveness to the world. This is the issue on which Hopko seems
most interested in reformulating Orthodox theology in response to
process theology (309, 322-23).
According to process theology, the idea that the universe
is a co-operative enterprise, involving inter-action between God and the
creatures, implies that there is a temporal as well as a non-temporal
aspect to the divine actuality. This is what divine dipolarity usually
means. The notion that the creatures genuinely exercise creativity
means not only that the world is not totally determined by God,
(so that predestination is rejected), but also that the future is not
fully known by God. God is omniscient, in the sense of knowing
everything knowable, but omni-science does not include prescience or
fore-knowledge, in the sense of infallibly knowing that which is future
to us. God as actual does not exist above or outside of time (only
God’s abstract essence exists “eternally” in the sense of “outside of
time”), so that God does not timelessly know that which is still future
for us. And God as presently actual does not know future actualities;
since they do not exist, there is nothing to know. Process theologians
apply here the old doctrine that even God’s power does not extend to
that which is intrinsically impossible. If the creatures genuinely make
a creative decision in the present, choosing among alternative
possibilities, then prior to that decision’s being made there is simply
nothing to be known. Hence, to say that God has perfect know-ledge,
knowing everything knowable, cannot imply that God knows the future.
God can know what is possible, and can know what is probable far better
than we. But if God could infallibly know what was to be actual,
this would imply that our sense that we are making creative decisions is
illusory. At least this is how process theologians see it.
Hopko, as we have seen, affirms divine-human
co-operation. He also agrees with process theo-logy’s rejection of
predestination (294). And he agrees with process theologians that, to
be faithful to the Biblical revelation, we need to talk of God as really
receptive and responsive to the world, even suffering with it (284, 288,
320-22, 338). However, Hopko also believes that it is necessary to say
that God knows all things before they happen (277, 285, 287), or
eternally from above time (291, 296, 298), and that God is absolutely
unchanging, having no temporality or becoming (263, 342). How is this
un-changing knowledge of the temporal world made con-sistent with
genuine responsiveness to the world? By the assertion that God is
eternally responsive to the free actions of the creatures (288, 289,
309, 316). That is, how the creatures who are created will use their
freedom is known to God, and responded to, prior to the actual creation
of the world. This eternal response by God to the creatures’ decisions
con-tributed to God’s decision to bring about this particular world
(which is the best of all possible [288]). Hence,
creation itself is as it is not by divine determination
alone, but by the inter-action of creaturely freedom and divine good
will. There is synergy between God and creatures even before creation.
What creatures think and do is known to God before the foundation of
the world (284).
Hopko believes that this doctrine provides for more
divine responsiveness to the world than one has in process theology by
saying that the divine responsiveness is eternal, even pre-eternal
(what-ever “pre-eternal” might mean) (289, 340). But to me, the notion
that God’s response to us is eternal, rather than moment-by-moment,
seems not to aug-ment the divine responsiveness, but to empty it of all
meaning. A “response” made to my present deci-sions prior to the
creation of this world I cannot un-derstand as a response at all. And
if this world at its inception included my present decisions, I cannot
understand these as free decisions at all. Indeed, after having
rejected predestination, Hopko reverses himself, saying: “How things
actually are, therefore, is truly decided by God, and there is such a
thing as providence and even ‘predestination’” (295f.). He adds the
qualification that this is “what God and the world have determined
together” (296). But I cannot understand this to be a meaningful
qualification. The issue between us is compatibilism: Hopko thinks
genuine freedom is compatible with infallible fore-knowledge (or
timeless knowledge), process thinkers do not.
Hopko probably agrees that this doctrine of com-patibilism
is not without difficulty. But he evidently believes himself driven to
affirm it because Christian faith seems to require the affirmation of
divine foreknowledge as well as creaturely freedom. He asserts that
this affirmation of divine foreknowledge is based not on an argument
about what God must be like to be worshipful (a Hartshorne, he says,
wrongly assumes), but on spiritual experience, the fact that God “has
demonstrated His foreknowledge” (292; cf. 297, 200). Here we would
evidently disagree em-pirically. I know of no events that prove that
God knows the future. Certainly some people have said that God
knows the future, but this does not by itself mean that it is true.
Certainly some people have had certain visions, sometimes called
“prophetic,” some-times called “precognitive,” which closely corres-pond
to what later came about. But such events do not prove that these
people, or God, had infallible knowledge in advance (or timelessly) of
what would actually come about. Other interpretations are possible,
some of which seem to me more adequate. In any case, I need
clarification from Hopko on what he means by saying that God’s
foreknowledge has been “demonstrated.”
While claiming that the doctrine of divine
fore-knowledge, or timeless knowledge, rests primarily on demonstration,
not argument, Hopko does offer an argument for it. He says that if the
future were un-known to God, God could not “in any sense be the guar-dian
and provider of the world’s processes in any way different from that of
any participant in the process” (292). That is surely extreme.
According to process theology, God differs decisively from other
participants in the process in several ways relevant to the question of
providence.
(1)
God knows the totality of the actual, whereas finite
knowers know only a small portion of it.
(2)
God knows what has happened perfectly, directly and
concretely, whereas most of the knowledge of finite knowers is
imperfect, abstract, and based partially on inference.
(3)
God knows all the possibilities open to any situation,
whereas finite beings know at most only some of them.
(4)
God knows the probabilities in any situation far better
than any finite knower can.
(5)
God knows which possibilities in any particular situation
are most compatible with the probabilities elsewhere and with the
over-all good of the world.
So, the idea that the future is real for God does not
seem to process theologians to rule out divine providence in a
meaningful sense. God is not reduced to merely one more participant in
the process on the same level as others.
The concern behind Hopko’s argument is perhaps
eschatological. There is a widespread conviction, which he possibly
shares, that a God who does not already know how the world will
ultimately turn out cannot be trusted to bring it to a satisfactory
end. But that is not necessarily true. My own statement of the “heart
of the Christian message” would involve the conviction that perfect
loving wisdom is the ultimate power of the universe, and that we can
safely entrust our everlasting security to it. To believe that God is
love is to believe that love is ultimately more powerful than anything
else and that it will ultimately be victorious. Perfect love exercised
with perfect wisdom can ultimately be victorious without knowing in
advance the exact details of how the victory will be won.
Hopko’s affirmation of divine foreknowledge is based on
the idea that it is “an indisputable biblical and patristic doctrine.”
(285) The word “indis-putable” here seems to carry a double meaning,
viz., that it is indisputable that it is affirmed by biblical and
patristic writers, and that it must (therefore) be con-sidered
indisputably true by Christian theologians today. This points us to
what is surely one of the deepest differences between typical Orthodox
and typical process theologians. The former tend to believe in an
infallible revelation in the Bible, and in a fairly irreformable
formulation of that revelation in the biblical and patristic period.
Process theologians, by contrast, while perhaps in some sense affirming
a “final” or “decisive” self-revelation of God in Jesus or the New
Testament, do not accept any biblical or patristic formulation as final
or irreformable. The idea of such a final formulation would seem to go
against the genuine creativity or freedom of human experience, and its
conditionedness by the fallible ideas and inadequate conceptualities of
any cultural epoch.
The difference on this point, and on the closely related
point of human freedom and divine deter-mination, seems ultimately to go
back to the issue with which we began—the issue of creation ex
nihilo, and of God’s relation to creaturely creativity. Because
Hopko affirms that God is the world’s ulti-mate metaphysical ground, who
created the world out of absolutely nothing, so that the creativity of
all creatures depends on God alone (180-81), he can say that the
creatures’ “action itself is in a real sense God’s action even
when it is realized by free creatures in the full integrity of their own
creaturely being” (341). Hence, he can believe that at one particular
place in the history of the world God produced a verbal formulation of
the nature of reality that coincides rather exactly with the way things
truly are. Process theologians, by contrast, given our understanding of
the relation between divine and human creativity, are more likely to
think in terms of “continuing revelation,” or at least of continuing
“reformulations” or “transformations” of inherited doctrines.
Hence, insofar as there are irresolvable differ-ences
between process and orthodox theologians, at least at the present time,
they involve both formal and substantive issues. Accordingly, any appeal
by either side to some criterion on the basis of which to settle a
dispute will involve circularity. The Orthodox theologian’s appeal to
scriptural or patristic evidence to settle questions of truth for today
would presuppose a substantive view of the God-world relationship that
process theologians reject. Like-wise, the views of process theologians
on substan-tive doctrines both support and are supported by our views of
scripture and tradition, which are not ac-cepted by Orthodox
theologians. Even my optimistic way of speaking of the irresolvable
differences be-tween us, indicating that they may only be irre-solvable
“at the present time,” reflects my process view that every tradition can
be crea-tively trans-formed through interaction with other traditions
while being faithful to its heritage. Although contemporary
process and Orthodox theologians may not overcome their present
differences, those in the future who stand in historic continuity with
one of these two traditions may find themselves much closer together.
Indeed, there may be people who see themselves as inheriting from both
traditions more or less equally. Because of my great respect for the
Eastern Orthodox tradition, I at least hope that that is the case
References
PR Alfred North Whitehead, Process and
Reality, cor-rected edition (The Free Press, 1978).
AI Alfred North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas
(Macmillan, 1933).
David Ray Griffin Page