From The Journal of Religious Ethics, 8:2, Fall 1980,
330-349. Abstract:
The notion
that “the holy reality wills it” can provide both the rational
justification (the move from “is” to “ought”) and the psychological
motivation for acting morally. But can the will of God be the criterion
for the morally right? Although what is right cannot be reduced to what
God wills (due to the perceptual aspect of the meaning of “right”), it
can be deduced from it, given an under-standing of perception that
implies that an omni-scient perceiver would necessarily be an impartial
sympathizer. This, however, presupposes the ideal observer criterion of
rightness, which is based upon an appeal to holiness. Recognizing that
the criterio-logical and religious meanings of moral terms are finally
identical overcomes the problems of justifi-cation and motivation
inevitable in apparently non-religious moral theories.
Posted October 29, 2009
The Holy, Necessary Goodness, and Morality
David Ray Griffin
Ethical autonomists claim that morality must be understood to be both
logically and motivationally independent of religion. In terms of
logic, they use the well-known “Is-Ought” problem, claiming for example
that there is no way to move from statements about God’s will to
statements about what we ought to do. No way, that is, except by
inserting an independently derived ought-statement, i.e., “One
ought to obey God’s will.” In terms of motivation a similar argument is
sometimes made. And it is often pointed out that so-called religious
motivations are appeals to self-interest (e.g., “Obey God and you
will be rewarded”) and hence are antithetical to morality.
The claim to autonomy from religion is usually part of a larger claim
that morality should be understood as autonomous, logically and
motivationally, from all metaphysical beliefs, i.e., beliefs
about the ultimate nature of reality. This claim to autonomy comes at a
high price. It means that, after clarifying the nature of morality, the
autonomists have difficulties with both the ultimate rational
justification and the human motivation for being moral. They can argue
that the justifying reason for doing a particular act is that the act is
right, i.e., when viewed from the “moral point of view,”
but they have difficulty giving grounds for adopting this point of view.
Many, in fact, frankly admit that at this level one must simply
“decide,” and that there are no reasons to support this decision. In
reference to motivation, even for those who have adopted the moral point
of view, more and more authors are saying that people will be moral only
if they want to, but that philosophical ethics does not have the
job of creating this desire. These ethicists seem to be in the position
of having to hope that parents, churches, and other individuals and
institutions will keep doing whatever things they are doing that somehow
get people interested in being moral, even if these things are
irrelevant or even antithetical to the true nature of morality, so that
there will continue to be people interested enough in morality to buy
the ethicists’ books to learn finally what the true nature and status of
morality are.
I believe that morality is inextricably connected to religion, and that
the problems of justification and motivation are insoluble apart from
religious beliefs and perceptions. This view depends on the assump-tion
that religion centrally involves conceptions and perceptions of the
holy, which I will discuss in Section I. The rational justification of
morality ultimately depends upon a conception of something holy; moral
motivation ultimately depends upon a perception of something holy.
An original (as far as I know) part of my argument is a three-fold
analysis of the meaning of “right” and “ought.” (Rightness and
oughtness are not coexten-sive for at least two reasons: sometimes more
than one choice may be equally right; and some things are right that are
not obligatory but only permissible. However, for the sake of
simplicity I ignore this fine point, and equate what is right for a
person at a particular time with what that person ought to do then and
there.) Section I deals with the religious aspect of this meaning.
Section II discusses the other two aspects, the criteriological and the
percep-tual. (This perceptual aspect of the meaning of “right” and
“ought” is not to be equated with the perception of “the holy.”) The
distinction between the criteriological and perceptual aspects explains
why assertions about “the Will of the Holy Reality” can entail ought
assertions even though “ought” and “right” cannot be exhaustively
defined in terms of “the will of the Holy Reality.”
Section III is devoted to showing those who accept an “ideal observer
account of the criterion of right and wrong could, given a particular
understanding of God, accept God’s will as the criteriological meaning
of right. In Section IV it is suggested that those who implicitly
accept the ideal observer account of the meaning of moral terms do so on
the basis a perception of holiness, so that the criteriological and
religious meanings of these terms are finally identical. And I argue
that a recognition of this fact would overcome the problems of
justification and motivation that are inevitable in apparently
non-religious moral theories.
I
Max Stackhouse has recently argued persuasively that all morality is
ultimately religious in that every moral position is finally grounded,
whether explicitly or implicitly, on some appeal to the holy. The holy
is that which is taken to be (1) decisively powerful in human affairs
and (2) of self-authenticating intrinsic worth, inviolable (Stackhouse,
1976:64, 69f., 76). It determines what is important to us, since “it is
that which is held to be basically commanding and effective in life and
is simultaneously worthy of our attention, loyalty and obedience”
(Stackhouse, 1976:70).
Note that there is nothing in this definition of the holy about moral
goodness. To be intrinsically good and worthy of loyalty does not
necessarily involve being morally good. The widespread popular equation
of holiness with moral purity in our culture is based upon contingent
factors, including the fact that Jahweh, the “Holy One of Israel,” did
increasingly become perceived as morally perfect, a perception that was
not undercut by Christianity (in spite of parables and doctrines
suggesting that God’s for-giving mercy abrogated the divine justice).
In any case, the sense in which the religious drive to be in harmony
with the holy reality includes a need to be “morally righteous” depends
upon the nature of the holy reality in question.
Stackhouse distinguishes between that which is ultimately holy
for some individual or group and that which has a derivative
holiness. For example, although for Jews and Christians God alone is
(ultimately) holy, it has become customary to speak of the “sacredness
of human life.” The twofold characterization of the holy as (a)
decisively powerful and (b) of self-authenticating worth and
inviolability would seem to apply only to that which is ultimately holy,
while derivative holiness would consist in inviolability based on more
or less self-authenticating intrinsic worth.
There is another distinction I think needs to be made, that between the
perceived holy and the conceived holy. The “conceived
holy” is that which one thinks to be worthy of ultimate loyalty.
The “perceived holy” is that which one directly feels or
senses to be holy. It involves one’s pre-conscious outlook, a way
of perceiving reality that has become “second nature,” whereas a
conception of the holy involves one’s conscious intellectual processes.
A mere intellectual belief that something is holy will act upon one’s
attitudes and emotions and hence upon one’s outer actions. This is why
so-called “believers” can be such hypocrites, feeling and acting in ways
that are not at all consonant with their professed beliefs. And this is
why theologians distinguish between “mere belief” and “saving faith”; it
is in saving faith that one’s perception of reality is oriented around
the holy reality of the religious tradition in question. In the saving
faith that makes one (more or less) whole, it is not merely one’s “mind”
that is convinced, but one’s total “heart” and “soul.” One has a
“vision of God,” not a mere belief in God.
Combining these two distinctions accounts for the fact that those
regarded as “atheists” from the standpoint of a certain religious
tradition may be more moral, in terms of that tradition’s own values,
than the explicit believers. For, although the atheist no longer
accepts the conception of the ultimately holy reality that originally
supported the identifica-tion and relative importance of those things
that are taken to be derivatively holy, this non-believer may have a
stronger perception or sense of the holiness of these more immediate
things (such as “all sentient beings”).
If “religion” is taken to include reverence not only for things taken to
be ultimately holy (e.g., God, Brahman, the Tao) but also for things
with derivative holiness (e.g., human beings, all sentient beings,
naturalness, truth, impartiality), and is also seen to involve not only
conceptions but also perceptions of the holy, the claim that all
morality is in fact religious is much more plausible than it would
otherwise seem. The key idea is that every rational justification of an
ethical stance, whether made explicitly or implicitly, involves an
appeal to something which cannot and need not be further justified: It
just is holy and hence inviolable. That is, it is taken to be self-authenticatingly
worthy of reverence.
The idea of the holy is relevant not only to the question of
justification, but also to that of motivation. Many commentators
who have argued that there is no logical passage from
is-statements to ought-statements have pointed out that there seems to
be some psychological basis for moving from one to the other.
Beliefs about the way things are seem to influence our most fundamental
moral beliefs and motivations. This psychological basis, I claim, is a
religious drive that is common to all people. I believe this desire is
what is common to all religions: the Taoist wants to be in harmony with
the Tao, the Vedantist with Brahman (“being in harmony with” can mean
“realizing identity with”), the Jew and Christian (and Moslem) with the
will of God (or Allah), the Hegelian with Absolute Spirit, the Marxist
with the dialectical process. The desire is common; the conceptions of
the holy are various. The various religions are the various beliefs,
attitudes, emotions, and practices oriented around the desire to be in
harmony with that which is taken to be ultimately holy. Many of the
practices (e.g., both individual and corporate) are devoted to getting
the conceived holy to be more completely perceived as
holy. A con-ception of the holy provides some motivation; but
primarily people are religiously motivated to the degree that they
have a vision of holiness.
This discussion of the idea of the holy has been for the purpose of
explicating one of the three aspects of the meaning of “ought” and
“right,” the religious aspect. In regard to this aspect, something is
“right” if it is in harmony with the holy reality; something is “wrong”
if it would be a violation of it; the sense that we “ought not” do
something attaches itself to those things that would be wrong; the sense
of “oughtness” attaches itself to those things that are not merely
permitted but positively enjoined if one is to be in harmony with the
holy reality.
In terms of the religious meaning of ought, the transition from
is-statements to ought-statements is provided by the religious drive
that belongs to human nature. The “argument” that occurs implicitly in
people can be explicated as follows:
1. To be in harmony with a reality that is X, one must Y.
2. The holy reality is X.
3. If I want to be in harmony with the holy reality, I ought to Y.
4. I want to be in harmony with the holy reality.
5. Therefore I ought to Y.
Of course, this “deduction” usually does not occur in this step-by-step
form, except in cases where one is explicitly aware of the community’s
conception of the holy and is giving a theological argument for a
certain course of action, as in a sermon. Usually the perceived holy is
taken for granted, and the type of behavior that is fitting in the light
of this holiness is simply seen. This is the aspect of the meaning of
“right” and “ought” that provides the basis for those who say that these
terms refer to properties of certain entertained feelings, attitudes,
courses of action, etc., properties which are known through
“intuition.”
Te religious aspect of the meaning of moral terms, then, is concerned
with what is viewed as fitting and unfitting in the light of the
nature of the holy. There can be considerable moral tension within
a person, due to the variety that is possible within that which is taken
as holy. For one thing, many things can become derivatively holy. For
example, in a tradition in which the holy reality has been conceived as
Truth Itself, and in which human beings have been regarded as created in
the “image of God,” both truth and human feelings may come to be
regarded as holy, and in some cases loyalty to truth may dictate a
different action than does loyalty to human feelings. Also, there can
be a tension between the perceived and the conceived holies.
Accordingly, one may feel something to be wrong without being
able to give any rational justification for the claim that it is wrong;
likewise, one may, upon reflection, think that something is wrong
without having any strong feelings about it.
However, that which is conceived to be ultimately holy may also be
perceived as holy. To the extent that this is true, one and the same
thought can provide the rational justification and the motivation for a
particular action—for example the thought, “The Holy Reality wills it.”
It would seem, then, that there would be considerable advantage to be
gained if God’s will could appropriately regarded as the criterion of
what we ought to do. But this idea has been widely rejected. In the
next section I will argue not only that the objections to this idea are
inconclusive, but that a widespread consensus among philosophical
ethicists in fact implies that God’s will is the criterion.
III
Theological ethicists (as I use the term) move from the assertion that
God wills that we do A to the conclusion that we ought to
do A. Ethical auto-nomists, wanting to demonstrate that at least
our most fundamental moral principles—and hence the meaning and
justification of moral judgment—are independent of all religious
beliefs, ask how this move is made from factual assertions about God’s
will to normative conclusions as to what we ought to do. It seems to be
widely agreed that there are only two logically rigourous ways this move
can be made. The first is to insert an ought-statement between the
factual premise and the normative conclusion. For example:
A. God wills that we cultivate our loving tendencies.
B. We ought to do what God wills.
C. Therefore we ought to cultivate our loving tendencies.
This move does not show that morality is dependent upon religion, for we
have to decide independently whether what God wills is always right
before we can know whether B is true. Hence, we have to have
some independent standard of right.
The only other way to move logically from statements about God’s will to
statements about what we ought to do is to define “ought” so that
the conclusion that we ought to do A is already included in the
assertion that God wills for us to do A. For example, if the
word “ought” simply meant “willed by God,” the syllogism would be
valid. William Frankena offers the following as an example of such a
valid argument:
1. “I ought to do A” means “A is commanded by God”.
2. A is commanded by God.
3. Therefore I ought to do A. (Frankena, 1976:137)
If this definition of
“ought” could stand up to scrutiny, religious morality would be
vindicated. But it will not stand up. The usual weapon is the “open
Question” argument. One can meaningfully ask: “Ought I to do the will
of God?” or “Is the will of God always right?” But if statement using
“ought” and “right” were simply replaceable with statement about “the
will of God,” these questions would make no sense. One would be asking:
“Ought I to do what I ought to do?” or “Is the will of God always the
will of God?” Hence, these moral terms cannot simply mean “what
God wills.”
However, most commentators have evidently not noticed that this strict
identity of meaning is not required for the argument to be valid. All
that is necessary is that “I ought to do A” be entailed by “God wills
that I do A.”
Hence the argument would be:
1. “I ought to do A” is entailed by “God wills that I do A.”
2. God wills that I do A.
3. Therefore I ought to do A.
It is at this stage that
the distinction between the perceptual and the criteriological aspects
of the meaning of right and ought is relevant. By the “criteriological
aspect” I mean that which serves as the necessary and sufficient
condition for something’s being right. This criterion might be God’s
will. But this would not make “that which God wills” the meaning
of right and ought, since there is an irreducibly perceptual
aspect to the full meaning of these terms. That is, there is a “ought”
dimension to our immediate experience; we have a feeling of “rightness.”
Although this feeling attaches itself to different contents in
different cultures (due to different perceived and conceived holies),
the feeling or perception that provides the experiential basis for
understanding what the words “right” and “ought” mean is common to all
cultures. This is why people with radically different views of what is
right can still argue about what is right.
In discussing the meaning of the word “good,” G. E. Moore discusses an
analogy between the perception of a color and the perception of
goodness. You cannot explain what yellow is to someone who is blind.
Yellow is simple and therefore cannot be defined; it must be perceived
I am discussing the terms “right” and “ought” instead of “good.” And I
do not think that they are simple in the sense of being unanalyzable; I
am suggesting just the opposite. But I do think that Moore’s comparison
with colors points to one aspect of the meaning of these terms. If a
person did not have feelings of oughtness or rightness, this
person would simply not know what you were talking about when you said,
e.g., that one ought to do what God wills, or that the right
thing to do is that which would maximize goodness.
This perceptual aspect of the meaning of right and ought explains why
the open question argument defeats every attempt to provide definitions
of these terms that would exhaust their meanings, whether that
definition be “that which God wills,” “that which promotes the most
happiness,” or “that which is in harmony with the evolutionary thrust.”
There is an irreducibly experiential aspect to the meaning of right
which makes it impossible to deduce its meaning to some formula.
But this does not necessarily mean that conclusions about what is right
cannot be deduced from statements about what God wills. For, it might
be that God’s will can properly be understood as the ultimate criterion
of what is right, and hence as the criteriological meaning of “right”
and “ought.” God’s willing something would be a necessary and
sufficient condition for its being right. If this were the case, then
from the statement, “God wills that I do A,” it would follow that I
ought to do A.
The big question is hence whether God’s will can appropriately be
considered the ultimate criterion of right and wrong. There will be two
parts to my argument that it can. First, I will point to a widespread
consensus that the ultimate standard of moral rightness is what a fully
informed, impartial, sympathetic observer would will. Second, I will
suggest that God should understood in such a way that God would
necessarily exemplify this role. That is, god’s will could not be
arbitrary; God could not will otherwise. In passing, I will also point
to other changes required in the meaning of “God” for this idea not to
be counter-intuitive.
II
My first point is that there is a widespread consensus among those who
consider moral judgments to be objective and therefore capable of being
true or or false, that right and wrong must finally coincide with what a
fully informed, impartial, sympathetic observer would approve and
disapprove. The attempt to achieve this perspective is quite often
referred to as adopting the “moral point of view.” Some authors simply
equate this with the “rational” point of view. Others say that the
notion of being rational does not necessarily include the notion of
being sympathetic to the interests of others. In any case, all parties
hold that the spectator must be both impartial and sympathetic
to the interests of all as well as fully informed. ~
It should be noted that taking the preferences of such a being as the
criterion of right and wrong avoids the dilemma usually posed to those
theologians who state that God’s will is the criterion. That is, it is
usually argued that the theologian must either say God wills X because
it is right (i.e., X was right prior to God’s willing it), or
else admit that it is arbitrary that X is right (i.e., if God’s
willing X is really what makes it right). The ideal observer
theory avoids this dilemma. On the one hand, what is right is not some
truth that exists prior to the ideal observer’s reaction, so that
“reason” alone would be needed to see what is right (as Thomism is
usually interpreted as saying). Rather, what is right for Jones to do
in a particular situation is decided by what a fully informed,
impartially sympathetic observer would want Jones to do. This
reaction is the very criteriological meaning of saying that “X is the
right thing for Jones to do.” There is no higher standard by which the
right thing could be established. On the other hand, the preference of
the ideal observer is not arbitrary, in the sense of capricious,
for this observer if fully sympathetic to the interests of all the
beings involved; hence its “preference” could not be for actions that
would result in injustice and unnecessary pain.
Given this consensus, one might expect that there would be little
objection to the idea that God’s will is the criterion of right and
wrong. After all, is not the ideal observer, as Charles Reynolds
(1970:163) points out, simply a secular version of God? And yet there
is much objection. The dilemma mentioned above is repeated time and
time again; it is asserted that right and wrong would be capricious if
God’s will were the criterion.
How can one account for this widespread reaction? In terms of motives,
one can of course understand that moral philosophers who do not believe
in God, and in fact find such belief harmful, would want to reject the
suggestion that God’s will is the criterion of moral rightness. But the
question is not what their motives are, but what argument they have.
They have to have some basis for concluding that the will of God would
not necessarily be identical with the preference of a fully informed,
impartial, sympathetic perceiver.
One important factor is surely that the images and concepts of God that
have been dominant in our tradition do not make this identification
self-evident, to say the least. The image of the tribalistic, vengeful
Jehovah, especially in the earlier-written parts of the Old Testament,
still plays a powerful role in the connotation of the word “God.” And
the image of God suggested by Calvinism is that of an arbitrary tyrant.
A God who would predestine the majority of the human race to hell is
hardly an impartial sympathizer. Furthermore, traditional theism in
general has insisted that God is “impassible,” which entails that God
has no sympathetic reactions to the world. Finally, the God of
both theological and popular theism has been omnipotent, causing or at
least permitting (while having the power to prevent) all the things we
consider evil; it is certainly counter-intuitive that such a God is
sympathetic to the interests of all sentient beings. Accordingly,
although there is a sense in which the fully informed, impartially
sympathetic perceiver is a secular version of God, it is a secular
version of a minority view of God. Philosophers cannot be blamed
for being biased against the idea that the will of God is the criterion
of right and wrong, and thus rejecting this idea while endorsing, more
or less explicitly, the omniscient, impartial sympathizer as the
criterion.
Nevertheless, the understandable bias aside, the question is, What
basis is there for the assumption that the will of God would not
necessarily be identical with the preference of a fully informed,
impartially sympathetic perceiver? It is generally agreed, of
course, that God would be fully informed, since omniscience is generally
taken to belong to the very notion of God. But many commentators
believe that there is no absolute necessity that God be impartial and/or
sympathetic to the interests of all sentient beings. In particular, it
is widely stated that these other two attributes do not follow from
omniscience.
For example, Henry David Aiken (1958:82) states: “Now, there is no
logical connection between the metaphysical attributes and the moral
attributes. Logically, there is no reason why an almighty an omniscient
being might not be a perfect stinker.” P. H. Nowell-Smith (1966:97)
says: “There is nothing in the idea of an omnipotent, omniscient creator
which, by itself, entails goodness or his right to command.” J. Brenton
Stearns (cf. 214, 216) has discussed this issue most fully .
While clearly including omniscience among the essential attributes of
God, Stearns says: “However God is described, . . . his goodness remains
a logically contingent matter.” Stating it in other terms, he says that
“there is no logical reason to suppose that the being on top in the
metaphysical hierarchy is of any religious interest,” since there is no
reason to assume that the metaphysically eminent being is morally
eminent (Stearns, 1972: 212, 213). There is reason why a metaphysically
supreme being, having attributes such as omni-science, should not be
evil (Stearns, 1972: 12, 219). This, Stearns (1972:219) says, is true of
even more adequate views of God, such as that of Whitehead. It is this
position, which is asserted again and again in the literature, but
seldom ever argued, that I want to challenge.
Some theologians who view God’s will as the criterion of right have
responded to the charge of arbitrariness by arguing that goodness is
essential to the very idea of God. For example, Patterson Brown
(1963:239,241) seeks to mitigate the offense caused by his claim that
God’s will is (for the Christian) the ultimate criterion of good by
pointing out that perfect knowledge, justice, and love also belong to
the definition of God, and that God would necessarily will in accord
with these attributes. Burton Porter (1968:152) tries to solve the
is-ought problem by saying that “God is good” is analytically true.
Also, in pointing out that God’s point of view is the one and only
exemplification of the moral point of view, Charles Reynolds
(1972:511-515) and Richard Mouw (1970:65) both emphasize that this is
not true of any old concept of God, but requires that God must be
impartially benevolent.
Although I think these views are on the right track there is one problem
they share: they provide no link between the metaphysical
and the moral attributes of God. All these thinkers would hold,
I believe, that a being worthy to be called God must have certain
metaphysical and certain moral attributes. But from their writings one
could infer that it is just fortuitous that the being who has the
necessary metaphysical equipment also has the necessary moral character.
Now, this weakens the claim that “God’s will” is the criterion of right
and wrong. For, the word “God” seems to suggest metaphysical attributes
to many people more readily than it suggests a particular moral
character. For example, for Kai Nielsen (1966: 148) the word seems to
signify most basically a “necessary being.” And for many the first
attribute suggested is omnipotence.” Accordingly, despite the fact that
theologians may claim that qualities such as impartial sympathy or
loving kindness are as essential to the notion of God as the
metaphysical ones, the thought will remain that a being worthy of the
name God might be, in Aiken’s words, a “perfect stinker.” After all, if
we were convinced that there were an eternal, necessary, omniscient,
supremely powerful creator, would we withhold the name God just because
we thought this being was not morally perfect? John Roth, Fred Sontag,
and Eliezer Berkovitz certainly do not. So, no matter how much
theologians claim it to be analytic that God is good, the thought will
remain that God might be evil. In other words, that God’s
preferences would not necessarily coincide with those of a fully
informed, impartial, sympathetic observer.
To remedy this situation, it would be necessary to show that the moral
attributes of God in question (namely, impartiality and sympathy) follow
from at least one of the metaphysical attributes. This would mean
refuting Stearns’ (1972:214) claim that, “given any metaphysical
description of God, God’s goodness is logically contingent.” This would
show that, in terms of at least one metaphysical position, the
metaphysically eminent being would necessarily be more morally eminent.
In terms of what metaphysical attribute can the link be made? Most
critics, in rejecting any linkage, pounce on omnipotence, pointing out
that making the linkage on this basis would be to endorse the
unacceptable view that “might makes right.” Kai Nielsen (1966:147, 148)
for some reason picks necessary existence, and indeed it would be hard
to deduce necessary moral goodness from this charac-teristic. But what
about omniscience, which is the one metaphysical characteristic shared
in common by the traditional notion of God and the ideal observer? (I
should perhaps point out that omniscience, defined as “knowledge of
everything knowable,” need not include knowledge of the future.) What
if to know other sentient beings immediately with
perfect knowledge is necessarily to share their
enjoyments, their sufferings, and their desires? Then an
omniscient being would necessarily be sympathetic, and
impartially so, since this being would equally share the
feelings of all other sentient beings.
The idea of omniscience is the idea of knowledge that is
not only complete but also direct and immediate.
There would be no knowledge based on inference, and in fact none that
is mediated in any way. On what basis can we plausibly contend that
omniscience would involve perfect sympathy? Only if it is true in
general that the degree of sympathy we feel for others increases
proportionately with the completeness and directness of our knowledge of
them. Alfred North Whitehead and Charles Hart-shorne, among others,
argue that this is the case.
Whitehead distinguishes what we ordinarily call perception, i.e.,
sense perception, from a more direct and fundamental form, which he
calls “perception in the mode of causal efficacy.” The big mistake of
most epistemologists, he holds, is that they have assumed that sense
perception, because it is clearer and more distinct in our conscious
awareness, is the fundamental type of perception. But this is backwards
(Whitehead, 1978:162 [246]). The basic or primitive type of perception
involves a direct transfer of feeling, in which the perceiver’s
experience conforms to the subjective forms (the emotions, desires,
purposes) felt by the perceived. In short, perception in its most direct
form is sympathy. Here is Whitehead’s (1978:162 [246]) statement:
The primitive form of physical experience is emotional—blind
emotion—received as felt elsewhere in another occasion and conformally
appropriated as a subjective passion. In the language appropriate to
the higher stages of experience, the primitive element is sym-pathy,
that is, feeling the feeling in another and feeling conformally with
another.
Our best examples of
this in our own experience are our perception of our bodily cells and
our perception of our own immediate past experience. Our body is that
part of nature with which we have the most direct, intimate relations.
And clearly our knowledge of what goes on in it is sympathetic
knowledge, as when we step on a nail, have a stomach-ache, or, more
happily, when we enjoy good food or an orgasm. Apart from telepathy,
which most of us do not experience—at least vividly—the only “others” on
our own level that we know directly and with any adequacy are our own
past experiences. And this is clearly a relation of sympathy; in fact,
the sympathy is so strong that we have often thought that the relation
was one of ontological identity. But, once we see that it is not, that
our soul is not an enduring substance but a series of discrete
experiences, it becomes our clearest illustration of the coincidence of
knowledge and sympathy. We feel very strongly the disappointments, the
boredom, the joys, the desires, and the purposes of our past
experiences, especially those within the past few seconds. They, along
with the current feelings derived directly from the body, usually
provide our strongest motivations.
This positive relation between knowledge and sympathy, which becomes
identity in the supreme instance, is discussed often in Hartshorne’s
writing, usually with an eye towards its ethical implications. He
stresses the difference between inferential, indirect “knowledge about,”
which we have of external things through intermediary signals or
symbols, and the direct, intuitive, “knowledge by acquaintance,” which
is sympathetic, and which alone should serve as the model for divine
omniscience (Hartshorne, 1964: 241; 1968:196f.) And he stresses the
importance of taking the mind-body relation as our basis for
understanding unmediated knowledge, since, other than memory, this is
the only type of knowledge that is obviously sympathetic (Hartshorne,
1968:208). Using the mind-body relation as a model for the God-world
relation leads to the view that God, as omniscient, naturally and
necessarily is motivated by the interests of others, since they become
God’s own interests (Hartshorne, 1964:162). We can imagine this through
a thought experiment: “suppose all ‘others’ were within the body, as its
members; then, since the need of the body is for the flourishing of its
own parts or members, bodily desire and altruism would be coincident”
(Hartshorne, 1953:141). This that God would not be altruistic:
“Omniscience thus removes from God the sole reason for that form of
altruism which seeks the good of another in partial disregard of whether
or not it is good for self” (Hartshorne, 1953:140). This lack of a need
for altruism removes any basis for imaging that an omniscient being
might not be sympathetic to the interests of other sentient beings,
since omniscience makes for a “certain and absolute coincidence
of other-interest and self-interest” (Hartshorne, 1953:141, italics
added). Is it then proper to call God “ethical”? Hartshorne
(1964:162f.) explains, in a passage that nicely summarizes the points
being made here, that this depends on how one understands the term.
. . . if “ethical” means resistant to temptation, or willing to
sacrifice joy (not just to suffer pain) for others, then in so far God
is not ethical. But if it means being motivated by concern for the
interests of others, then God alone is absolutely ethical; for to know
interests, fully and concretely, and to share them are
indistinguishable. The “simplicity” of God has here its true meaning,
that there can be no duality of understanding and motivation in a being
in which either understanding or motivation is perfect. Both come down
to love pure and simple and indivisible. To fully sympathize with and
to fully know the feelings of others are the same relationship,
separable in our human case only because there the “fully” never
applies, . . . .
The claim of the ethical autonomists is that every metaphysical
description of God leaves God’s goodness logically contingent. It only
takes one counter-example to refute this sweeping claim. Hartshorne’s
metaphysical description of God explicitly provides such a
counter-example (and Whitehead’s does implicitly). My argument has been
designed to show that the necessary connection between divine
omniscience and impartial sympathy for all sentient beings is not an
ad hoc assertion, but one which follows from a general analysis of
the nature of direct perceptual knowledge of other sentient beings.
Given this analysis, if God is omniscient, God could not be a “perfect
stinker.” Since the idea that an increase in knowledge necessarily means
an increase in virtue is in general so false (I am a Niebuhrian on this
and most points), I should perhaps summarize the very restricted sense
in which I am suggesting that it is true. First, I am not speaking of
the knowledge of propositional truths, but only of the knowledge of
other sentient beings. Second, I am not speaking of “knowledge about,”
but of “knowledge by acquaintance,” i.e., of perceptual
knowledge. In the third place, I am not referring to the kind of
“perception” most people probably first think of when they think of
perception, viz., sense perception. Rather, I am referring to
knowledge that is “based on that non-sensuous type of perception
we have of our bodily feelings and our own past thoughts and feelings.
Finally, I am not suggesting that this type of knowledge leads to moral
virtue in human beings at all, since the only “sentient beings” of which
we have this type of knowledge are our own bodily cells and past moments
of our own soul1, and we usually think of moral virtue as
involving relations to sentient beings beyond our-selves. Rather, the
suggestion is only that we have an experiential basis for seeing that
divine omni-science, in which all sentient beings would be known with
even more complete and immediate perceptual knowledge, would necessarily
be impartially sympathetic knowledge.
There is one other reason why philosophers who would not object to
taking the preferences of a hypothetical ideal observer as the criterion
of right might object to thinking of the will of an actual being as the
criterion. This is the fear that the ontological doctrine that
the will of God constitutes the criteriological meaning of moral terms
would imply an unacceptable epistemological doctrine of how to
ascertain the right. Those philosophical ethicists who accept the ideal
observer criterion are generally committed to the view that trying to
discern the right thing to do involves learning all the relevant facts,
including the interests of all the parties concerned, and then deciding
through impartial reflection what course of action would be best. In
other words, one tries to discern the right through rational procedures,
with “rational” understood to involve empirical, deductive, and
imaginative elements. Autonomists are afraid that these rational
procedures will be short-circuited if the criterion of right is the will
of an actual being, since this will might be thought to be known through
some means other than rational reflection. One might believe that this
being has revealed its will with adequate clarity in the past, and that
this revelation is adequately reflected in some Scriptures. For
example, after arguing it to be a necessary truth that God’s moral
judgments are always correct if God is understood as a perfectly
omniscient, rational, and benevolent being, Richard Mouw (1970:65, 66)
goes on to say that “that being has publicized his moral views,” and he
contrasts “God’s moral advice” with “our own deliberations.”
Whether one believes that the process of rational ethical reflection can
be supplanted or at least supplemented by some other means for
discerning the will of God will depend upon one’s conception of God,
especially God’s mode of relating to the world. For example, if one
rejects the doctrine of divine omnipotence and with it the idea that God
could unilaterally determine the nature of events of events in the
world, one will not be able to believe in an infallible revelation by
God. This might lead one to conclude that taking God’s will as the
criterion of right and wrong would not imply a different procedure for
making moral judgments than that implied by taking the preferences of a
purely hypothetical ideal observer as the criterion. This move is made
in two excellent articles by Charles Reynolds (1970, 1972), who has
adopted Hartshorne’s view of God.
However, there is no gainsaying that taking the will of an actual being
as the criterion might lead to the conclusion that a different
procedure should be used to discern the right. And this conclusion
could well be based upon the kind of rational reflection that is usually
urged by philosophical ethicists. To see this point, we must
distinguish between the procedure recommended for making actual moral
decisions and the procedure for deciding how best to go about making
these actual moral decisions. The former decision procedure can be
called the “existential decision procedure”; it is the procedure to be
used when one is confronted with a concrete moral issue. The latter can
be called the “ivory-tower decision procedure”; it is the procedure used
in a time of disengagement from concrete moral decisions. One sits in
one’s ivory tower and contemplates how one should make a concrete moral
decision, the next time one comes up. I am assuming that all parties
would agree upon the ivory-tower decision procedure: One should consider
all the relevant facts impartially. But different people using this
same ivory tower procedure may come to different conclusions as to the
proper existential decision procedure, since they may have different
ideas about the “relevant facts.” In one person’s list might be the
“fact” that our moral sense and practical reason been corrupted by
original sin, and the “fact” that an omnipotent God has provided a
remedy for this in the form of revealed moral laws. Accordingly, the
ivory-tower reflecting may lead to the conclusion that existential
judgments should be made by appealing to the Bible. Another person,
using the same ivory-tower procedure but not including God and original
sin among the facts of reality, may conclude that existential judgments
should be made in the same way as ivory-tower judgments, that is, by
impartial reflection upon all the relevant facts. Still another thinker
might reject the idea of a moral law infallibly given in the past and
yet believe in a God whose present will can be discerned by those who
have taken the proper measures to be open to the promptings of God’s
Spirit. And this thinker might conclude while in the ivory tower that
sensitiveness to the present promptings of the Holy Spirit would, at
least for some people, lead to correct existential judgments more often
than the attempt to try to discern the right through purely rational
procedures.
Accordingly, it cannot be denied that taking the will of an actual God
as the criterion of right might lead to an existential decision
procedure that would differ from that advocated by non-theistic
ethicists. But that fact alone cannot be used by ethical autonomists to
reject theological ethics without begging the question, since the
question as to the “proper” existential decision procedure cannot be
answered without answering the prior question as to the “relevant
facts.” One cannot begin with the assumption that rational reflection
is always the proper decision procedure for making existential moral
judgments; one can only establish this by first arguing convincingly
that the relevant facts about reality do not include a God, at least a
God who is impartially sympathetic to all and whose will could sometimes
be best known through means other than rational reflection alone.
IV
I have argued (in Section II) that one can move logically from beliefs
about God’s will to ought-statements if one stipulates that “what God
wills” is the criteriological meaning of “what is right” and
“what one ought to do,” so that saying “God wills that I do Y” entails
“I ought to do Y.” But how can one justify the stipulation that what
God wills is the criterion of what is right? I have argued that many
contemporary philosophers should find this stipulation unobjectionable,
given a Whiteheadian-Hartshornean understanding of God, since this
stipulation does not differ substantively from their own formulations of
the criteriological meaning of right. But one can still ask, Why should
we take the preference of a fully informed, impartially sympa-thetic
observer as the criterion of right and wrong? Is this a universally held
criterion? Obviously not, as many tribes have held that it is right to
treat people in other tribes totally differently than those in one’s
own. The viewpoint of an observer who would be impartial as between the
interests of the people in the various tribes was not recognized as a
higher standard, and would have been rejected if proposed. And indeed
there are philosophers today who say that the right thing is always that
which promotes one’s self-interest as it is understood by the person in
question, no matter how “selfish” those interests might be. So, how can
one simply say that the moral standard is a perspective that is
impartially sympathetic to the interests of all people (or even all
sentient beings)?
The answer seems to be that the philosophers who accept this standard do
so on the basis of a perception of holiness. In our Western
tradition, biblical ideas of a God who is the creator of all people, who
loves all people equally, wills equal treatment to those within and
without one’s tribe, and is ‘‘no respecter of persons,” were combined
with universalistic ideas and also the ideas about divine reason
in the Stoic, Platonic, and Aristotelian philosophies, which were
themselves developments out of earlier religious traditions. For about
twenty centuries this conception of the holy has been focused on
in almost all the explicitly religious worship, and has been dominant in
the various areas of thought and activity for most of those centuries.
The perception of the holy among people in the West has thereby
been heavily influenced. Many people who no longer share the
conception of the holy of holies that was for so long the orthodox
synthesis, and who may not have replaced it with a reformed or radically
different conception, still more or less see the world,
especially in regard to fundamental moral issues, through lenses that
were ground during centuries of trying to conform one’s perceptions to
those of the Holy One of Israel, Rome, and Athens. This fact was the
basis for Nietzsche’s criticism against the British moralists who had
given up the Christian (conception of) God but still tried to retain the
Christian morality, rather than seeing that a complete reversal of
values was called for (i.e., by Nietzsche’s new view of the
holy).
This influence can be seen in recent philosophical discussions of the
nature of morality. One of the major divisions within these discussions
is between those who do and the “rational” point of view. But both
groups show the influence of the Christian conception of the holy on
their understandings of the nature of morality. G. J. Warnock is one
who rejects the equation of morality with rationality. He lists several
ways in which one might reject morality, or at least seldom take its
dictates to be overriding, without being guilty of irrationality. For
example, one simply might believe that aesthetic consider-ations were
usually more important than moral ones, which are concerned with the
amelioration and prevention of suffering and injustice (Warnock,
1971:157f.). Or, concern for the welfare of the weak might be thought
to be bad for the race in general. So, there is nothing about
“rationality” that dictates impartial sympathetic consideration of the
interests of all human beings (or sentient creatures). But Warnock
builds this requirement into the meaning of “morality” itself. The
general object of morality as such, he (Warnock, 1971: 16) says, is the
amelior-ation of the human predicament. There is hence a
universalism built into this definition by virtue of the term “human.”
One of the essentials of the moral point of view is a respect for
persons simply as persons, and hence the principle that no human being
is to be regarded as having no rights (Warnock, 1971:148, 141).
Accordingly, Warnock will not allow so-called “tribal moralities” to be
called “moralities,” since their notions are not really moral ones.
This exclusion, he (Warnock, 1971 :149) says, is not arbitrary, but
analytic, since it follows “from what morality is.”
Warnock, incidentally, believes that theistic religious beliefs can help
instill a moral point of view, but that such beliefs do not make any
difference in principle. People are capable of arriving at the feeling
of respect for all persons without seeing them as the object of deity’s
care; and in civilized religions religious sanctions are simply attached
to things that would anyway be regarded as moral or immoral
(Warnock, 1971:140-141). Warnock has evidently so come to see as
holy those things (i.e., people qua people) that were made
derivatively holy by the Christian God that he believes the
perception of this holiness to be independent of any perception or
conception of deity.
Paul Taylor (1961:113) provides an example of one who builds
universalistic requirements into the concept of rationality, rather than
directly into the concept of morality. He says that we must speak of
the moral codes of head-hunting societies and of street gangs as
moral codes. How does one choose among moral codes? In particular,
how can one justify an impartial morality, in which everyone’s
interests should be taken into account (Taylor, 1961: 146, 148)? Taylor
argues that Kurt Baier’s answer to this question is circular, in that
Baier presupposes the way of life that includes this “moral point of
view” in the very attempt to justify it. Taylor (1961:146f.) argues
that we must have a procedure for justifying the inclusive way of life
itself. But Taylor’s own procedure is circular. His procedure is to
see which way of life would be rationally chosen. He (Taylor,
1961:164f., italics his) stipulates that “a choice is rational to the
extent that it is free, enlightened, and impartial.” We see
here the characteristics of our old friend, the ideal observer, indeed,
Taylor (1961:165) points out that no human being can fulfill these
conditions. Impartiality includes disinterestedness, which requires
that “the choice is not at all determined by . . . desire to protect
one’s privileges (or those of one’s family, friends, or class), or by
any emotional prejudices . . . .” (Taylor, 1961:170).
Now, many people, including many philosophers, would say that a choice
is rational (although perhaps immoral) if it is well suited to achieving
what a person wants, to furthering an interest (whether that interest be
selfish or impersonal). But Taylor will not allow “rational” to be so
used: to be rational, a choice must be completely disinterested. Hasn’t
Taylor simply built the perspective of a universalistic deity into his
concept of rationality, thus guaranteeing that the only moral codes that
could be “rationally chosen” would be ones that would be in harmony with
the will of a universal, impartial, sympathetic deity? Taylor denies
that he has built a commitment to his own way of life into his concept
of rationality, so that his procedure would be circular. Rather, he
(Taylor, 1961:176) claims, the conditions of rational choice that he has
specified “are the conditions which I presume anyone, in any way of
life, would accept as defining a rational choice, in the ordinary sense
of the word ‘rational.’”
But a definition of rational that includes the notion of complete
impartiality is clearly a normative definition. It appears that Taylor,
through being raised in a tradition whose people had so long believed in
a holy reality that combined the universalistic aspects of Hebrew, Greek
and Roman thought, has come to perceive impartial rationality as itself
holy, and to be unable to grant the term “rational” to any process of
thinking that does not strive for and achieve a significant degree of
impartiality.
My argument is that the reason why the preference of a fully informed,
impartially sympathetic observer can be regarded as the criterion of
right is that this perspective is implicitly conceived as holy. This
means that the criteriological meaning of right is not really distinct
from the religious meaning insofar as it deals with the conceived holy,
which, I argued, is the ultimate basis for the justification of moral
judgments. The only difference is that sometimes it is not explicitly
recognized that the acceptance of something as an ultimate standard
involves an acceptance of this something as holy. Once this is
recognized, it becomes evident that the transition from is- to
ought-statements depends upon the psychological fact that we have an
interest in being in harmony with that which is holy.
Recognizing the religious nature of all morality has several
advantages. First, it undercuts the claim that explicitly religious
moralities are illegitimate in principle. Second, it has the purely
philosophical advantage of increased understanding by uncovering the
appeals to ultimacy that are often made only covertly. Third, by
revealing that there is no purely “rational” justification for moral
judgments, and getting the appeal to the holy out in the open, it makes
clear what the quest for justification has to deal with, i.e.,
the conception of the holy. Fourth, as stated earlier, it allows us to
see that that which is the final ground for the justification of moral
judgments is also a basis or a motivation to be moral.2
Accordingly, it does not leave those who want to promote morality in
the position of having to hope passively that people will have the
emotions, attitudes and interests that are the precondition for moral
reflection and action. Rather, they can promote the moral life by
promoting the vision of the holy reality. In the words of Kenneth E.
Kirk, the way to promote morality is not to set codes of behavior before
people, but to “stimulate the spirit of worship.”
Notes
1
At least this seems to be true of most of us, especially so far as
conscious awareness is con-cerned. Some “sensitives” do seem to
feel sympa-thetically the feelings of other people. And, according to
Abraham Heschel’s interpretation, the prophets were consciously
sympathetic to God’s feelings.
2
To avoid misunderstanding, I should add that I do not assume that to
know the good is, for humans, necessarily a sufficient motivation for
doing it. Beyond the fact that we will never adequately know “the
good,” in that our partial perspective will always distort our
perception of it, our anxieties about our own place in the scheme of
things will inevitably hinder an uncompromising pursuit of the good even
insofar as we have glimpsed it. (Of course, I am assuming here that we
have a vision of a good that transcends our partial perceived
interests.) Also, while our religious drive to be in harmony with the
holy provides some motivation for acting, and especially to the extent
that our perception and conception of the holy coincide, the religious
drive varies greatly in strength from person to person, in comparison
with other drives. Also, even in the most integrated people there will
surely be some divergence between the perceived and conceived holies.
References
Aiken, Henry David
1958 “God and evil: a study of some relations between faith and morals.”
Ethics 68/2 (January):77-97.
Brown, Patterson
1963 “Religious morality.” Mind 72 (April):235-244.
Frankena, William
1976 ‘‘‘Ought’ and ‘is’ once more.” Pp. 133-147 in Kenneth E.
Goodpaster, editor, Perspectives on Morality: Essays of William K.
Frankena. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame.
Hartshorne, Charles
1953 Beyond Humanism: Essays in the Philosophy of Nature. Lincoln:
University of Nebraska. (Originally published in 1937.)
1964 Man’s Vision of God and the Logic of Theism. Hamden, Conn.: Archon
Books. (Originally published in 1941.)
1968 Reality as Social Process: Studies In Metaphysics and Religion.
Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press.
Kirk, Kenneth E.
1931 The Vision of God: The Christian Doctrine of the Summum Bonum.
London, New York, Toronto: Longmans, Green and Company.
Mouw, Richard J.
1970 “The status of God’s moral judgments.” Canadian Journal of Theology
16:61-66.
Nielsen, Kai
1966 “Some remarks on the independence of morality from religion.” Pp.
140-151 in Ian T. Ramsey, editor, Christian Ethics and Contemporary
Philosophy. London: SCM Press.
Nowell-Smith, P. H.
1966 “Morality: religious and secular.” Pp. 95-112 in Ian T. Ramsey,
editor, Christian Ethics and Contemporary Philosophy. London: SCM Press.
Porter, Burton
1968 Deity and Morality: With Regard to the Naturalistic Fallacy.
London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.
Reynolds, Charles
1970 “A proposal for understanding the place of reason in Christian
ethics.” The Journal of Religion 50:155-168.
1972 “Elements of a decision procedure for Christian social ethics.”
Harvard Theological Review 65:509-530.
Stackhouse, Max L.
1976 “The location of the holy.” The Journal of Religious Ethics 4/1
(Spring): 63-104.
Stearns, J. Brenton
1972 “The naturalistic fallacy and the question of the existence of
God.” Religious Studies 8:207-220.
Taylor, Paul W.
1961 Normative Discourse. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
Warnock, G. J.
1971 The Object of Morality. London: Methuen & Company Ltd.
Whitehead, A. N.
1978 Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. Corrected Edition,
edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. New York: The Free
Press. (Pagination to the 1929 Macmillan edition given in brackets.)
David Ray Griffin Page