Matter,
Consciousness, and the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness
David Ray Griffin
I. The Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness
What is
common to all forms of the fallacy of misplaced concreteness is the “error
of mistaking the abstract for the concrete” (SMW, 51)—of assuming
an abstraction from a concrete reality to be the totality. The version of
this error most germane to our topic is that of assuming nature as it
actually is to be composed of matter understood as having “simple
location.” For a bit of matter to be “simply located” would mean that it
could properly be said to be right here in space and time in a way
that required no essential reference to other regions of space-time (SMW,
49). In other words, the concrete units of nature would have no essential
reference either to the past or to the future.
This notion
of nature creates obvious difficulties. As Hume pointed out, it makes the
justification for scientific induction difficult.
For
[Whitehead says], if in the location of configurations of matter
throughout a stretch of time there is no inherent reference to any other
times, past or future, it immediately follows that nature within any
period does not refer to nature at any other period. Accordingly,
induction is not based on anything which can be observed as inherent in
nature. (SMW, 51)
Thinkers in
the early modern period were not bothered by this fact, because they held
that matter obeyed rigorous laws imposed by its creator; even
Darwin retained a deistic form of that belief. But what is the
justification for induction in a naturalistic framework? It is
freeloading to keep the imposition while rejecting the Imposer. It seems
that we are again presupposing something in practice for which orthodox
theory provides no basis. Also, if nature’s units have no reference to
the past, our own memory, given the assumption that we are fully natural,
would be difficult to explain (SMW, 51).
A second
feature of the materialistic view of the concrete units of nature, besides
simple location, is the notion that they can exist at an instant,
in the technical sense of an idealized slice in time completely devoid of
duration. According to this view, “if material has existed during any
period, it has equally been in existence during any portion of that
period. In other words, dividing the time does not divide the material” (SMW,
49), which means that “the lapse of time is an accident, rather than of
the essence, of the material. . . . The material is equally itself at an
instant of time” (SMW, 50). There is, accordingly, no inner
motion, no internal becoming; the only kind of motion ascribable to the
units of nature is locomotion, motion through space. Combining this
second feature with the first, we get the notion of the “simple location
of instantaneous material configurations” (SMW, 50).
A third
feature of this view of matter is that because the concrete units of
nature are assumed to have no inner duration, they are assumed to have no
intrinsic reality whatsoever, which means that they are assumed not to
have any intrinsic value, not to be things that exist for their own
sakes. They are “vacuous actualities” (PR, 167), meaning
actualities totally devoid of experience. “Nature is thus described as
made up of vacuous bits of matter with no internal values, and merely
hurrying through space” (MT, 158).
According
to this view, the units of nature, being completely timeless, are totally
different from our conscious experience as we know it immediately. We
have memory, whereas natural units are said to have no reference to the
past. We experience a present duration, in which we enjoy intrinsic value
and make choices among possible values, whereas the reality of the units
of nature is said to be exhausted by their outer features. Finally, our
present experience, with its purposes, includes an anticipation of the
future, whereas nothing analogous is said to occur in the units of nature.
Our experience is temporal through and through; the units of nature are
purely spatial.
The idea that our
experience could arise out of natural units thus conceived is indeed
paradoxical. But this paradox only arises, Whitehead says, because we
have committed the fallacy of misplaced concreteness. Employing Bergson’s
term to express the nature of the error involved, he says that we tend to
“spatialize” the objects of sensory perception (SMW, 50; PR,
209). This tendency is so strong because it arises from the conjunction
of at least three factors:
(1) We cannot perceive
contemporary events while they are becoming; we can perceive events only
when they are past, after their internal becoming is finished.
(2) Objects of sensory
perception are aggregational societies of large numbers of individuals
and, as such, are predominantly spatial entities.
(3) Conscious sensory
perception itself spatializes its data, removing in the process any
inherited affective tone.
The meaning of these
three points will be filled out in the ensuing discussion; for now, the
point is the old one of being suspicious of appearances. Modern
philosophy, in stressing the illusory nature of sensory appearances, has
congratulated itself on having fulfilled its duty to be suspicious by
distinguishing between primary and secondary qualities while accepting
unquestioningly the deeper illusion: the notion of instantaneous bits of
matter simply located in space (which lay behind the distinction between
primary and secondary qualities). Whitehead is much more suspicious than
McGinn of the conception of matter based on spatializing sensory
perceptions.
Philosophy’s task, Whitehead suggests, is to be “the critic of
abstractions.” By playing this role, it can be helpful to society,
including society’s science (SMW, 59, 87). For a period, of
course, society in general and science in particular were not interested
in this help, thanks to the “narrow efficiency” of the scheme of ideas
based on scientific materialism. That is, this scheme of ideas was
extremely successful in directing attention to, and getting relevant
knowledge about, “just those groups of facts which, in the state of
knowledge then existing, required investigation” (SMW, 17). This
scheme of ideas was efficient precisely because it was narrow,
suitable only for a particular range of facts that needed to be considered
first, namely, the “simplest things” (MT, 154). The great success
of this method made it impervious to philosophical criticism, such as that
of Berkeley and Hume (SMW, 59, 66). Because of “its expulsion by
science from the objectivist sphere of matter,” philosophy “retreated into
the subjectivist sphere of mind,” thereby losing “its proper role as a
constant critic of partial formulations” (SMW, 142).
Now,
however, Whitehead says, this scientific materialism, with its
abstractions, has become too narrow for science itself, “too narrow for
the concrete facts which are before it for analysis. This is true even in
physics, and is more especially urgent in the biological sciences” (SMW,
66).
Whitehead’s attempt to
provide a “wider basis for scientific thought” (SMW, 67) has, of
course, been largely ignored. Like previous philosophical critics of the
abstractions that the scientific community has inherited from the dualists
of the seventeenth century, Whitehead has until now been left crying in
the wilderness. However, the present attempt to develop a science of mind
or consciousness, which requires putting mind back into nature, provides
the context in which Whitehead’s analysis of misplaced concreteness may
get a hearing. The attempt to produce a fully naturalistic science of
mind makes abundantly obvious—even more so than does biology, including
physiology—that the received ideas are “too narrow for the concrete facts
which are before [science] for analysis.” This is the recognition behind
the dissatisfaction of Madell, the perplexity of Nagel, the agnosticism of
Strawson, and the pessimism of McGinn, Robinson, and Campbell. The basic
reason for the problem, as these thinkers more or less clearly recognize,
is the one Whitehead gave—that this scheme of ideas “provides none of the
elements which compose the immediate psychological experiences of mankind.
Nor does it provide any elementary trace of the organic unity of a whole”
(SMW, 73).
Whitehead
bases his criticism of these abstractions, as well as his own proffered
replacements, on the conviction that although the tendency to spatialize
the objects of sensory perception is a very general tendency, it is not,
as McGinn’s analysis seems to suppose, an inherent necessity of the
intellect (SMW, 51; PR, 209). He rejects the idea that “the
abstractions of science are irreformable,” offering his own program of
reform “in the interest of science itself” (SMW, 83).
Besides
hindering the progress of science, Whitehead says, the fallacy of
misplaced concreteness, resulting in the idea of instantaneous matter with
simple location, has been “the occasion of great confusion in philosophy”
(SMW, 51). This confusion has not been limited, however, to the
abstract view of matter. The usual notion of the mind, as consisting
essentially of consciousness and distinctively mental operations, is also
a high abstraction (SMW, 58). This twofold abstraction lies behind
the reason that neither the top-down strategy nor the bottom-up strategy,
as described by McGinn, could go very far toward overcoming the gap
between matter and mind. Closing the apparent gap requires overcoming
both parts of the twofold abstraction. That is, although my Whiteheadian
approach agrees with Strawson that the primary reason for the
intractability of the mind-body problem has been the received view of the
physical body, not, as the majority view holds, the received notion of
conscious experience, my approach holds that this notion of consciousness
shares some of the blame—partly because it contributes significantly to
the false view of the body.
The
mind-body problem has been generated, Whitehead suggests, because the bits
of matter that enter into scientific description, as well as the conscious
minds thought to be doing the observing and describing, are entities “of a
high degree of abstraction” resulting from “a process of constructive
abstraction” (SMW, 52, 58). Unlike extremists on this point,
Whitehead does not say that the very notion of matter is a complete
fiction, created out of whole cloth, with no correspondence to reality.
Nor does he, unlike other extremists, say this about consciousness.
Rather, he says, “‘matter’ and ‘consciousness’ both express something so
evident in ordinary experience that any philosophy must provide some
things which answer to their respective meanings” (SMW, 143). To
speak of them as abstractions is to say that, rather than being simply
fictions, they are “simplified editions of immediate matters of fact” (SMW,
52). Overcoming the twofold abstractness of vacuous bits of matter
and consciousness as the stuff of mind can be described as the
central purpose of Whitehead’s philosophy.
The fallacious view of
matter resulting from misplaced concreteness, Whitehead believes, can be
overcome by starting from the bottom, with physics, or at the top, with
human psychology, supplemented by physiology. The “organic realism”
toward which he is heading (PR, 309) could also be reached, he
says, by beginning in the middle, with biology, which most readily
suggests the concept of organism in place of mechanism (SMW,
41, 103) and which, with its doctrine of evolution, demands a doctrine of
elementary units that are capable of evolution (which the aboriginal stuff
of the materialistic philosophy is not [SMW, 107]). But he devotes
most of his attention to psychological and physiological studies of human
beings and to physics, reporting that he in fact arrived at his own
convictions by means of an analysis of fundamental notions in physics (SMW,
152). Part of what he means can be learned from chapters 1 through 10 of
Science and the Modern World or, more briefly, from chapter 7 of
Modes of Thought.
Developments in modern
physics, he argues in these chapters, have undermined all the elements on
which the materialistic view of nature was based. In the new view, in
particular, “there is no nature at an instant” (MT, 146), and the
notion of passive, enduring matter has been undermined: “Matter has been
identified with energy, and energy is sheer activity” (MT, 137).
Physics as such, to be sure, does not completely overcome the dualism
between experience and matter, because of the limited interests of
physics: “In physics there is an abstraction. The science ignores what
anything is in itself,” that is, its intrinsic reality, considering
its entities only with regard to their extrinsic reality, and only
certain aspects of this, namely, the modifications of spatiotemporal
specifications of other things (SMW, 153).[*]
[*]
I quoted
earlier Strawson’s statement that physics provides “what we think of as
our best account of the nature of the physical” (MR, 47). Although
Strawson’s statement can be accepted as a sociological statement about the
dominant view today in scientific and philosophical circles, from
Whitehead’s analysis it follows that we emphatically should not
think of (present-day) physics as performing this role. To do so involves
doubly misplaced concreteness, given the double abstraction involved in
the conceptions provided by (present-day) physics. Of course, Strawson’s
statement does not mean that he himself is guilty of this fallacy, given
his assertion that the account of the physical provided by present-day
physics must, at a general level, be radically incomplete. It does seem,
however, that by and large scientists and philosophers reinforce each
other in this fallacy of misplaced concreteness: Most philosophers seem
to think that the materialistic view of nature’s ultimate units is
vouchsafed by physics, whereas most physicists, generally being aware
that, because they deal only with abstractions, they are not in a position
to settle philosophical questions about the nature of nature, seem to
assume that the materialistic view of their realm is based on good
philosophical reasoning (whether of professional philosophers or of fellow
physicists functioning as their own philosophers). If philosophy would,
as Whitehead proposes, recover its role as the critic of abstractions,
this vicious cycle might be broken.
Also, although the
notion of energy as fundamental is an advance on the older idea of matter,
“the physicists’ energy is obviously an abstraction” (SMW, 36).
But, in sweeping away the Cartesian-Newtonian “essential distinction
between matter at an instant and the agitations of experience,” the new
physics now at least allows “bodily activities and forms of experience
[to] be construed in terms of each other” (MT, 115). That is, we
can add content to the notion of “bare activity” by fusing experience and
nature (MT, 166).
The
bottom-up approach from physics, however, can only take us part of the
way. Bridging the apparent gap requires supplementation from the top-down
approach. That approach, however, faces great obstacles, especially given
inherited modes of thought. I turn now to this approach.
Posted
August 31, 2007
Next
Abbreviations of Works Cited
·
AI
Alfred North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas
·
SMW
Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World
·
MBS
John R. Searle, Minds, Brains and Science: The 1984 Reith Lectures
·
MR
Galen Strawson, Mental Reality
·
MT
Alfred North Whitehead, Modes of Thought
·
PCH
Lewis Edwin Hahn, ed., The Philosophy of Charles Hartshorne: Library of
Living Philosophers XX
·
PR
Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology
·
VN
Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere
Return
to This Essay's Introduction
Go to David Ray Griffin Page