Matter,
Consciousness, and the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness
David Ray Griffin
II. Overcoming Misplaced Concreteness with
Regard to Both Matter and Mind
C. The Status of Sensory
Perception in Human Experience
The assumption
that sensory perception is a primary element in our experience follows
from the equation, false from Whitehead’s perspective, of primacy in
consciousness with genetic primacy in experience. Sensory
perception is a derivative form of perception, resulting from an
integration that occurs in a late phase of experience. It thus tends to
get clearly illuminated by consciousness. That sensory perception gets
lit up clearly follows not from the fact that our perceptual experience
begins with sensory perception but from the fact that it does not.
Sensory perception, in Whitehead’s analysis, is derivative from two
simpler modes of perception. The first of these is called “perception in
the mode of causal efficacy.” Perception in this mode has already been
discussed, because it is simply physical prehension described in
the language of perception.
It is through perception in the mode of causal efficacy that we know most
of those things that we inevitably presuppose in practice,
which I have called hard-core commonsense notions. Modern
philosophy has had difficulty explaining how we knew them, thereby
relegating them to the category of “practice,” “faith,” “a priori
forms of intuition,” or even “dispensable common sense,” because it has
not recognized this more primal mode of perception underlying sense
perception. It is through this more basic mode of perception, for
example, that I have the category “other actualities besides myself” and
know that there is an external world beyond my own experience,
because I directly prehend other things, such as my bodily actualities.
This is the basic reason why we are all realists in practice: “Common
sense is inflexibly objectivist. We perceive other things which are in
the world of actualities in the same sense as we are. Also our emotions
are directed towards other things, including of course our bodily organs”
(PR, 158).
This same mode of perception is, likewise, the basis for our knowledge of
the reality of causation as real influence; this point is implicit
in calling it “perception in the mode of causal efficacy.” In prehending
my body, for example, I prehend some of its parts as causally efficacious
for my own experience. This applies not only to various pleasures and
pains but also to external sensory perception itself. In opposition to
Hume’s claim that “impressions” arise in the soul “from unknown causes,”
Whitehead points out that Hume reveals elsewhere “his real
conviction—everybody’s real conviction—that visual sensations arise ‘by
the eyes.’ The causes are not a bit ‘unknown,’ and among them there is
usually to be found the efficacy of the eyes [although sometimes it may be
alcohol]. . . . The reason for the existence of oculists and
prohibitionists is that various causes are known” (PR, 171).
“The notion of causation arose,” Whitehead adds, “because mankind lives
amid experiences in the mode of causal efficacy” (PR, 175).
It is through
this mode of perception that we also know about the past and
therefore the reality of time. I mentioned earlier that memory is
an example of a physical prehension, because the present occasion of
experience prehends prior experiences. This explains why we are not in
practice afflicted by Santayana’s “solipsism of the present moment.” This
prehension of our own past occasions of experience also provides an
explanation for our sense of self-identity through time—which needs
an explanation in any philosophy such as that of Buddhism, Hume, and
Whitehead in which the notion of a soul or mind as a numerically
self-identical substance through time is denied (AI, 184, 186,
220f.; MT, 117f., 160ff.) .
Perception in the mode of causal efficacy, which is a nonsensory mode of
perception more basic than sensory, also serves to explain another
assumption presupposed in the mind-body problem: our close sense of
identification with our bodies. In a statement expressing a fact so
obvious as to be seldom noticed, Whitehead says,
Nothing is more astonishing in the history of philosophic thought than the
naive way in which our association with our human bodies is assumed. . . .
[The body] is in fact merely one among other natural objects. And yet, the
unity of “body and mind” is the obvious complex which constitutes the one
human being. . . . [O]ur feeling of bodily unity is a primary experience.
It is an experience so habitual and so completely a matter of course that
we rarely mention it. No one ever says, Here am I, and I have brought my
body with me. (MT, 114)
Whitehead’s explanation: “There is . . . every reason to believe that our
sense of unity with the body has the same original as our sense of unity
with our immediate past of personal experience. It is another case of
nonsensuous perception” (MT, 189). This sense of unity arises from
what I in the previous chapter called “basic perception,” in which one
prehends one’s own brain and through it the remainder of one’s body.
I
might add here that although Whitehead’s method is certainly based on what
can be called “introspection” in a broad sense, he is critical of
introspection as it has typically been practiced by philosophers.
The
attitude of introspection . . . lifts the clear-cut data of sensation into
primacy, and cloaks the vague compulsions and derivations which form the
main stuff of experience. In particular it rules out that intimate sense
of derivation from the body, which is the reason for our instinctive
identification of our bodies with ourselves. (AI, 226)
The
reason the top-down approach has not gotten very far in overcoming
the gap between mind and body is that it has usually started too far
up, with the superficialities of human experience rather than with its
essential ingredients. It has started with what makes our minds human,
not with what makes them actual. I move now toward that higher level of
superficialities.
The second mode
of perception, derivative from the first, is called “perception in the
mode of presentational immediacy.” It is thus named because in this mode
the data are immediately present, in themselves telling no tales of their
origin. Taken by themselves, sense data, such as those constituting the
yellow round shape before me, arise, in Hume’s words, from “unknown
causes.” In fact, when they are considered in isolation, we should not
even call them sense data, because this term implies that we do
know that they are derived from the senses. If this kind of perception
were our only mode of perception, as Hume’s theory held, then we would not
even have the idea of causal influence: “Hume’s polemic respecting
causation is,” Whitehead says, “one prolonged, convincing argument that
pure presentational immediacy does not disclose any causal influence” (PR,
123). Pure presentational immediacy also does not disclose other
actualities, a past, time, or much of anything else. Insofar as it gets
reduced to visual data, as it often does (MT, 168), it gives us
nothing but space, shapes, and colors. Given the modern tendency to
equate perception with perception in this mode of presentational
immediacy, it is no wonder that modern philosophy has had epistemological
problems (such problems, in fact, that many philosophers Want to give up
the whole epistemological enterprise).
These problems have arisen because of the false assumption,
discussed earlier, that those elements that are primary in
consciousness must be primary in the perceptual process. After the
passage in which Whitehead argues that “those elements of our experience
which stand out clearly and distinctly in our consciousness are not its
basic facts; they are the derivative modifications which arise in the
process,” he writes:
For
example, consciousness only dimly illuminates the prehensions in the mode
of causal efficacy, because these prehensions are primitive elements in
our experience. But prehensions in the mode of presentational immediacy
are among those prehensions which we enjoy with the most vivid
consciousness. These prehensions are late derivatives in the concrescence
of an experient subject. (PR, 162)
“Most of the difficulties of philosophy,” Whitehead continues, are due to
assuming the opposite: “Experience has been explained in a thoroughly
topsy-turvy fashion, the wrong end first” (PR, 162).
What, then, is sensory perception? It is a synthesis of these two more
primitive forms. It is thus a form of “perception in the mode of symbolic
reference,” because data from one of the two former modes (usually
presentational immediacy) are used to interpret data arising from the
other mode (usually causal efficacy). To continue the example begun
above, I use the yellow round patch that is immediately present to my mind
to interpret the feeling of causal efficacy from my body, particularly my
eyes. I say, accordingly, that I am seeing the sun. I may be wrong about
that. I cannot be wrong about experiencing the yellow shape; and I cannot
be wrong about feeling the causal efficacy (although I may be wrong in
thinking that it originated from the eyes). In those two pure modes of
perception, there is simple givenness. But perception in the mode of
symbolic reference introduces interpretation and thereby the possibility
of error (PR, 168, 172).
The
fact that sensory perception includes perception in the mode of causal
efficacy explains why we are all realists about sensory perception. We do
not, as Whitehead says, begin dancing with sense data and then infer a
partner (PR, 315f.). However, the fact that presentational
immediacy generally far outweighs causal efficacy in consciousness,
especially when one is involved in philosophical introspection, has led
most philosophers simply to equate sensory perception with presentational
immediacy. Some of the problems of this equation have already been
mentioned. Another problem—which I touched on in the previous chapter—is
the resulting assumption that entities without sensory organs can have
no perceptual experience at all. This assumption lies behind the fact
that most philosophers and scientists, even if they will allow some form
of experience to most animals, draw the line at the point where there seem
to be no sensory organs. However, if presentational immediacy and
therefore sensory perception are derivative forms of perception even in
us, then it is not impossible in principle to generalize some kind of
perceptual experience to all individuals, however primitive. This
point is the basis for Whitehead’s generalization:
The
perceptive mode of presentational immediacy arises in the later,
originative, integrative phases of the process of concrescence. The
perceptive mode of causal efficacy is to be traced to the constitution of
the datum by reason of which there is a concrete percipient entity. Thus
we must assign the mode of causal efficacy to the fundamental constitution
of an occasion so that in germ this mode belongs even to organisms of the
lowest grade; while the mode of presentational immediacy requires the more
sophistical activity of the later stages of process, so as to belong only
to organisms of a relatively high grade. (PR, 172)
Besides taking as primary a mode of perception that could not possibly be
generalized to all levels of the actual world, the “topsy-turvy”
interpretation of our experience also ignores, or takes as secondary,
those dimensions of our experience that in principle could be
generalized. The fallacious assumption that the notion of causation
depends on vivid sense data, I have just argued, rules out the
generalizability of perception in the mode of causal efficacy. Other
relevant dimensions of experience are our emotions and purposes. In fact,
just after the “topsy-turvy” sentence quoted above, Whitehead says: “In
particular, emotional and purposeful experience have been made to follow
upon Hume’s impressions of sensation” (PR, 162). If we think,
instead, of our experience as consisting most fundamentally of emotional,
appetitive, and purposive (recall the discussion of “physical purposes”)
responses to physical feelings of other things, most basically our body
and our own past of a split second ago, then we have elements some faint
analogy to which can less implausibly be ascribed all the way down.
This completes my formulation of Whitehead’s response to the first
question, raised at the end of the first point in this section, regarding
the plausibility of generalizing any aspect of human experience to the
simplest actualities. Because much skepticism will surely remain, let me
recall Whitehead’s challenge:
Any
doctrine which refuses to place human experience outside nature, must find
in descriptions of human experience factors which also enter into the
descriptions of less specialized natural occurrences. If there be no such
factors, then the doctrine of human experience as a fact within nature is
mere bluff. . . . We should either admit dualism, . . . or we should point
out the identical elements connecting human experience with physical
science. (AI, 185)
Assuming that the threat of (ontological) dualism is sufficient to prod
even the most skeptical of my antidualist readers into continuing, I will
proceed to the second question, which asks what basis there is in
experience for thinking of the units of nature as the kind of entities
to which primitive emotions, appetites, and purposes could be ascribed.
Posted
August 31, 2007
Next
Abbreviations of Works Cited
·
AI Alfred
North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas
·
SMW Alfred
North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World
·
MBS John
R. Searle, Minds, Brains and Science: The 1984 Reith Lectures
·
MR Galen
Strawson, Mental Reality
·
MT Alfred
North Whitehead, Modes of Thought
·
PCH Lewis
Edwin Hahn, ed., The Philosophy of Charles Hartshorne: Library of
Living Philosophers XX
·
PR Alfred
North Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology
·
VN Thomas
Nagel, The View from Nowhere
Return
to This Essay's Introduction
Go to David Ray Griffin Page