Matter,
Consciousness, and the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness
David Ray Griffin
II. Overcoming Misplaced Concreteness with
Regard to Both Matter and Mind
E. Implications of the
Bodily Origin of Sensory Perception
“How do we observe
nature?” Whitehead asks. “The conventional answer to this question,” he
says, “is that we perceive nature through our senses” (MT, 158).
We are likely, he adds, to narrow this down to sight. However, he points
out, we should be suspicious of this answer. (For all their talk about
suspicion, most philosophers who think of themselves as “postmodern” have
remained true believers in this respect.) This suspicion should follow
from what Whitehead has called the “physiological attitude” (SMW,
148). Besides the fact that we are directly (if only vaguely) aware of
the intervention of the body even in visual perception,
every type
of crucial experiment proves that what we see, and where we see it, depend
entirely upon the physiological functioning of our body. . . . All sense
perception is merely one outcome of the dependence of our experience upon
bodily functionings. Thus if we wish to understand the relation of our
personal experience to the activities of nature, the proper procedure is
to examine the dependence of our personal experiences upon our personal
bodies. (MT, 158f.)
The most
direct way to observe nature, in other words, is to observe it
working in ourselves, as it influences our own experience (which is, we
recall, as much a part of nature as anything else). If we are
empiricists, we should draw our conclusions about the nature of nature
from our best vantage point: “The human body provides our closest
experience of the interplay of actualities in nature” (MT, 115).
Of course, many today have adopted a “physiological attitude” with
respect to the mind-body relation. The dominant approach, however,
interprets the physiological and psychological evidence in externalist
categories derived from sensory perception. Whitehead means something
quite different: an approach that interprets what we know from
physiology in terms of what we know about the body from within. This
approach, while including an introspective element, is not a return to
introspective psychology in the old sense. First, as pointed out earlier,
the introspective element here does not focus on the high-level,
superficial aspects of our experience, even its medium-level mentality,
but on the truly fundamental, originating, physical dimension of
our experience, in which it takes its rise largely from bodily activities.
Second, it involves a coordination of this internal observation of nature
in action with the information acquired from the external physiological
approach.
The moral of Point D
must not be forgotten. The purely external, purely physiological approach
to the study of the body is an approach in which “all direct observation
has been identified with sense-perception” (AI, 217). But the
central lesson of physiology itself is that sense perception is not direct
observation of its objects. The physiologist looking at my brain is
not directly observing my brain cells. As Whitehead repeatedly stresses,
“unless the physicist and physiologist are talking nonsense, there is a
terrific tale of complex activity” that occurs between my brain cells and
the brain cells and conscious experiences of the observing physiologist (MT,
121). It is simply credulous to accept the results of sense perception
(even if magnified by instruments), accordingly, as giving us direct
information, and indeed the only kind of relevant information, about the
nature of brain cell activity. Sensory perception gives very indirect
information, mediated through billions of events and then modified by the
constructive and abstractive processes of one’s own unconscious and
conscious experience. Although I from within am not consciously aware of
my individual brain cells and their “firings” (all this kind of knowledge
must come from physiology) and am not even directly aware of the existence
of a brain in my head (except perhaps when I have a headache), I do in
effect observe the brain insofar as I am directly aware of the kinds of
influences that flow into my own experience from it. And I am
conscious of receiving influences from various other portions of my body,
such as my eyes, my hands, my skin in general. The purpose of the present
point and the next is to see what can be learned from this direct
observation that can be used to interpret the more indirect findings of
physiology.
In speaking
of (external) sensory perception thus far, I have for the most part been
assuming the equation of it with its dimension of presentational
immediacy, which conveys information about the world external to the body.
This information, albeit highly abstract, is still information (when all
goes well) about that external world. As I took pains to stress in Point
D, however, sensory perception involves an integration of the perceptual
mode of presentational immediacy with that of causal efficacy. If we
attend to that other mode, then even (external) sensory perception tells
us something about the body. The remainder of the present point explores
implications of the fact that sensory perception does arise out of
our perception in the mode of causal efficacy of our own bodies. Points F
and G will then explore the information directly learned from that mode.
One thing
that an examination of our own sensory perception tells us is based on the
recognition that the human body is the “self-sufficient organ of human
sense-perception” (AI, 214). Although generally, to be sure, the
body in producing sensory perceptions in us does convey information
transmitted through the body from the outside world, this need not be the
case: By doing various things with the body, such as with drugs or
electrodes, the same kinds of sensory impressions can be generated; and
our dreaming activity shows most clearly that the body can be quite
self-sufficient in producing sensory imagery. The pertinent question from
this realization is: What does this fact, plus the fact that waking
sensory perception normally does convey information about the world
external to the body, tell us about the bodily parts themselves?
Whitehead’s answer: It tells us that our bodily units must incorporate
within themselves aspects of the world beyond themselves.
Your
perception takes place where you are, and is entirely dependent on how
your body is functioning. But this functioning of the body in one place,
exhibits for your cognisance an aspect of the distant environment. . . .
If this cognisance conveys knowledge of a transcendent world, it must be
because the event which is the bodily life unifies in itself aspects of
the universe. (SMW, 91–92)
For
example, if my sensory perception of the sun arises completely from my
prehension of my brain cells and yet my sensory data in some sense
correspond to the sun itself (and who really doubts that? ), then
my brain cells must in some sense incorporate aspects of the sun into
themselves. This recognition implies that the notion of these cells as
“simply located” is false. The functioning of the brain cells in
conveying this information suggests that each cellular event contains a
reference to the past world, in this case the events that occurred on the
surface of the sun eight minutes ago, and to the future, in this case to
my experience that comes immediately after the neuronal events. (If you
doubt that a temporal distinction can be made here, simply think about the
cellular events in the eye: They certainly occur prior to the mind’s
sensory perception based on data received from them, so in this case the
temporal relation is clear.) Each event seems essentially to prehend
aspects of past events and to pass on aspects to future events, which
prehend it. What we know from sensory perception by combining
inner and outer knowledge, accordingly, is that bodily cells are
analogous to our own experiences, at least in respect to being
prehenders. And if they are prehenders, they cannot be purely
spatial entities: They must have an inside, into which the prehended
material is taken before it is passed along to subsequent prehenders.
Having an inside would mean that they have an inner duration,
which is the time it takes each event to occur—the time between its
reception of information and its transmission of this information to
subsequent events. Looking at sensory perception from this
perspective, accordingly, gives us a much different idea of the nature of
nature than we get simply from the sense data of presentational immediacy
alone.
In light of
this idea, I will pause to look at a particularly interesting part of
McGinn’s argument, which I passed over before. In discussing
intentionality, he says that the most fundamental question is not the
nature of its content but “what this directedness, grasping, apprehension,
encompassing, reaching out ultimately consists in” (PC, 37). It is
this feature of our own experience that leads McGinn, given his assumption
that the mind is ontologically reducible to the brain, to despair of ever
solving the mind-body problem in physicalist terms (which would require an
epistemic reduction). “Phenomenologically, we feel that the mind ‘lays
hold’ of things out there, mentally ‘grasps’ them, but we have no physical
model of what this might consist in.” To make the point vivid, he says:
“If I may put it so: how on earth could my brain make that
possible? No ethereal prehensile organ protrudes from my skull!” (PC,
40).
In light of Whitehead’s
analysis, we can give a twofold answer. First, we need not think of the
brain as somehow having the ontological unity to prehend other things into
the unity of experience that we know directly (“phenomenologically”). By
distinguishing between the brain as a multiplicity and the mind-event as a
unification of aspects of brain events into an experiential unity, we can
attribute that unifying capacity to the mind. Second, we can,
however, think of each brain cell event as indeed having a grasping or
prehensive capacity, by which it unifies aspects of what it has received
from beyond itself into an (albeit much less complex and sophisticated)
experiential unity. This means, of course, that we must think of the
remainder of the bodily cells in a similar way; for example, those
constituting the remainder of the central nervous system must be able to
prehend and be prehended so that the information from the surface of the
body can be transmitted to the brain cells.
In any
case, besides learning from this dual mode of observation that our bodily
units must be prehensive events, we learn that they must embody, to use
the current jargon, “qualia.” This conclusion follows from the same kind
of reasoning, being already implicit in the analysis of “secondary
qualities” in the previous point. Sensory qualities such as red as we
see it, it is agreed on virtually all sides, do not exist in external
nature; for example, the molecules in a red ball are not red as we see
it apart from someone’s seeing it, and they certainly do not
see red. But we do see red, and this sensory quality surely
arises out of our bodily activities. It is impossible to understand how,
apart from supernatural intervention, this could be so if these bodily
activities were purely quantitative in nature, devoid of all qualia. A
naturalistic perspective leads to the inference that our bodily cells must
embody qualia of some sort, even if they do not experience them in the
same way that we experience them in conscious sensory perception. That
is, cells surely do not enjoy red as we see it. But perhaps red
for them is an emotion. Perhaps red as it exists throughout most of
nature is a subjective form of immediate feeling, whereas it is only in
the conscious presentational immediacy of animals with sensory organs that
that subjective form is turned into an objective datum projected onto
outer things. “Red as seen,” then, would be a transmutation effected by
more or less high-level experiences out of “red as felt. ” This is a kind
of transmutation that requires no supernatural assistance.
This suggestion, of
course, will be widely repudiated out of hand. Many philosophers will
respond angrily, or at least smile knowingly, muttering, “This suggestion
violates common sense.” That is true: It violates soft-core common sense
based on an uncritical acceptance of the deliverances of sensory
perception reinforced by several centuries of dualistic thinking and
language. Most philosophers (including scientists qua philosophers) have
become so strongly enculturated with this soft-core commonsense
perspective that they are willing to carry out its implications, to
violate several of our hard-core commonsense convictions, even
though this leaves them with a violent contradiction between their
theories and the presuppositions of their practice, including the practice
of formulating theories. Alternatively, they are willing to countenance
an unintelligible dualism, to accept a magical emergentism, or to proclaim
the mind-body problem permanently insoluble. Is Whitehead’s suggestion,
in spite of its violation of long-standing soft-core prejudices, not both
more rational and more empirical? Do we not indeed have good reason to be
suspicious of the conceptions of matter based on (sensory)
perception-based categories alone? Has Whitehead not provided good reason
to reject the notion that entities in nature in themselves have only the
spatial properties that we assign them on the basis of perception in the
mode of presentational immediacy? Has he not provided good reason to
think, instead, that bodily events involve prehension and therefore an
inside? And does that not remove one of the basic reasons for assuming
that cells could not experience subjective forms such as emotions of a
lowly sort? This is a defensive paragraph, but I do know from experience
what kind of response to expect from the suggestion that colors are
emotions and that cells could experience them. My response is an appeal
to Searle’s regulative principle that we constantly remind ourselves of
what we know for sure. This carries with it the negative principle that
we keep reminding ourselves of what we do not know. We do not know
directly that cells do not feel emotions, and we do not know anything from
which this could be deduced. However, we do know a lot of things that
this idea helps us make sense of.
The present
point is based on inference: We derive such and such from our brain,
therefore the brain’s units must embody such and such. The next point
appeals to direct experience.
Posted
August 31, 2007
Next
Abbreviations of Works Cited
·
AI Alfred
North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas
·
SMW Alfred
North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World
·
MBS John
R. Searle, Minds, Brains and Science: The 1984 Reith Lectures
·
MR Galen
Strawson, Mental Reality
·
MT Alfred
North Whitehead, Modes of Thought
·
PCH Lewis
Edwin Hahn, ed., The Philosophy of Charles Hartshorne: Library of
Living Philosophers XX
·
PR Alfred
North Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology
·
VN Thomas
Nagel, The View from Nowhere
Return
to This Essay's Introduction
Go to David Ray Griffin Page