Lexington Theological Quarterly
Vol.
28, No. 3, 1993, 240-260. For the table of contents of this lecture
series, go here.
Postmodern Theology for the Church
David Ray Griffin
3.
Overcoming the Demonic: The Church’s Mission
In the previous
lecture, I suggested that central to the rise and ever-increasing growth
of demonic power has been the rise and spread of ideologies of power.
From this perspective, the church must examine its own theology, asking
about the extent to which it has been one of these ideologies of power.
That it has been, and particularly effective one at that, is suggested by
the fact that Christian civilization, especially in its Western form and
most especially in its Protestant form, has emerged as the dominant power
on the face of the earth. Insofar as it has been the winner thus far in
what Schmookler calls “the parable of the tribes,” we must take seriously
the implication that traditional Christian theology has been a leading
contributor to the demonic’s rise to global dominance. If it seems likely
that it has been, then the first order of business for the church in our
time, now that we realize what has happened, is to get our own doctrinal
house in order, distinguishing those aspects of classical Christian
teaching that seem be genuinely based on divine revelation from those
whose origin and spread are better explained in terms of their usefulness
to the domination system. This type of “ideology critique” will be
threatening to many, of course; but it is demanded by our commitment to
the God of love, truth, and peace, the creator and lover of all.
Classical Christian
theology is not, however, the only system of belief requiring this kind of
radical ideology critique. The central formal point of these lectures is
that Christian theology in our time must be postmodern as well as
postclassical. Indeed, from the fact that the domination system has come
to threaten the continuing purposes of God on our planet only in modern
times, we should expect that the distinctively modern ideologies have been
the most useful thus far to the growth of demonic power. Accordingly, if
a postmodern theology is to be an effective instrument in the church’s
battle against the demonic in the coming century, this theology must
provide a viable alternative to the dominant modern ideologies as well as
to classical Christian theology. In the first section of this lecture,
therefore, I will briefly suggest the kind of ideology critique that we
need of the early and late modern worldviews as well as of classical
Christian doctrine. In the second section, I will suggest the kind of
alternative that postmodern Christian theology can provide.
I.
Critiques of Classical and Modern Ideologies of Power
These ideology
critiques could well fill an entire lecture—in fact, an entire lecture
series. All I can do here is to give a very superficial, impressionistic
idea of the kind of critiques that I will develop more extensively
elsewhere.1
Classical Christian Theology
At the root of
classical theology’s demonic potential is its supernaturalistic doctrine
of divine power. According to classical theism’s doctrine of omnipotence,
God can bring about events unilaterally in the world, so that there is a
one-to-one correlation between the events and the divine intention. Even
if most events in the world are brought about through natural or
“secondary” causation, God can intervene at will in this nexus of natural
cause and effect, preventing what would otherwise have occurred. Whereas
the Bible gives considerable support for this view of divine omnipotence,
classical theism bolstered it with an affirmation of creation ex nihilo,
a doctrine to which the Bible gives little if any support. According to
this doctrine, our universe was not created out of pre-existent finite
entities, which might have had some power of their own with which they
could have resisted the divine will, but out of absolute nothingness. This
doctrine of creatio ex nihilo is what effectively turns biblical
monotheism into monism, the doctrine that God essentially has all the
power. Any power that the world has is purely derivative, due to a
voluntary self-limitation on God’s part, which means that creaturely power
can be revoked or overridden at any time. This view of God can, in fact,
best be described as an extreme voluntarism, in that the very existence of
finitude is said to be contingent upon the divine will.
This extreme
voluntarism is presupposed in classical theology’s method of authority.
Revelation can be infallible, because God can unilaterally guarantee that
the events totally express the divine intention. The inspiration of
scripture can likewise be inerrant. Given these notions of infallible
revelation and inerrant inspiration, which presuppose divine omnipotence,
this doctrine of omnipotence can then (circularly) be proved by appealing
to those biblical passages that suggest this doctrine.
That same method can
then, of course, be used to prove all sorts of other things that support
participation in the war-system. For example, the fact that the Bible
refers to the practice of slavery criticism has been used even in our
century to sanction this practice.2
Another effect of the war-system reflected in the Bible the move to a
male image of deity throughout the Ancient Mid-East. Given the doctrine
of omnipotence and the method of authority, the biblical participation in
this patriarchal, androcentric movement has been taken by believers as a
word from God Himself that He is male! And, of course, the God of much of
the Bible is not simply male, but is a male warrior—which was a major
point of the move from goddesses to exclusively male gods. The biblical
image of God as the omnipotent male warrior has provided a prime stimulant
for warfare in Christian civilization. Christians not only believed that
they had explicit commands from God to fight (especially in Calvinism, in
which the literal interpretation of the Bible had replaced the allegorical
hermeneutic [according to which such passages were taken to refer to God’s
battle for the soul] and which the whole Bible was taken as equally
authoritative). But, given humanity’s religious drive to imitate deity,
the image of God as a mighty warrior gave warfare a religious aura. These
aspects of the Bible, taken as infallible revelation, were strong enough
to override, in most interpretations, those statements by Jesus that seem
to prohibit warfare.
The extreme
voluntarism of classical theism supported the warrior-image of God in yet
another sense. According to this voluntarism, not only God’s activity in
the world but also God’s response to the world is voluntary. That is, in
spite of the assertion “God is love,” which seems to say that love
characterizes the very nature of God, this voluntarism in combination with
various biblical passages has supported the idea that God’s love is
selective—that God hates some people and is at best indifferent to others.
This notion is, of course, in strong tension with classical theism’s
doctrine of divine impassibility, which says that God has no emotional
response to the world whatsoever. But that doctrine has had little effect
on popular piety and, in fact, has been reversed in most Protestant
theologies. It certainly has not prevented many Christians from accepting
at face value the notion of a “wrathful” God who becomes furious at, and
wreaks vengeance upon, the enemies of God’s chosen people. This divine
fury, by the dynamics of the imitatio dei, has sanctioned Christian
violence against enemies and infidels.
The notion of a
“chosen people” is, of course, another fruit of the classical theism’s
extreme voluntarism that has provided fuel for vigorous participation in
the war-system. There have been, to be sure, critiques of idolatrous
interpretations of the idea of chosenness both within the Bible and in
later Christian teaching. But the idolatrous interpretation, according to
which God loves some peoples more than others and promises salvation
(however defined) to them alone, has prevailed in practice. The notion
that Christianity is the “New Israel,” the really chosen people, has lain
behind much of Christianity’s imperialism, much of it extremely violent
and ruthless.3
Christology has been
a central part of classical Christian theology’s support for imperialism.
The supernaturalistic idea of God allowed classical Christian theologians
to assert that the salvific incarnation of God in Jesus was different in
kind from God’s presence in all other individuals. This doctrine provided
the basis for affirming that salvation to be available only through
Christian faith. This idea has been used to justify doing almost anything
to the bodies of nonbelievers in the name of possibly saving their souls.
Classical
Christianity’s supernaturalism also allowed for a forensic, juridical
notion of salvation, which aided Christian participation in violence.
That is, salvation was said to involve declaration by God, an imputation
of righteousness. To be “saved,” accordingly, did not require any actual
change of life, no actual sanctification. One did not, for example, have
to follow the Sermon on the Mount, or incarnate the fruits of the spirit
discussed in Galatians, such as love, patience, and peaceableness.
Violent warriors could be assured of salvation.4
Perhaps no feature
of classical Christian doctrine has distorted Christian faith demonically
more than its violent eschatology. Besides the idea that some people are
to be eternally damned, the biblical picture of the “last things,” taken
largely from the Book of Revelation, suggests that our world will
culminate in an orgy of divine violence. To be sure, nonviolent
interpretations of this book have been given, but its violent imagery,
especially under the literalistic interpretation promoted by
Protestantism, has been a major influence on the prevalent Christian
belief that God’s ultimate victory over evil will come through violent
power, not love. The central symbol of Christianity, the cross, suggests
otherwise; but thanks in large part to the Bible’s eschatological imagery,
taken together with the doctrine of divine omnipotence, Christians have
been told that even God will finally have to resort to violence to defeat
evil.
If Christian faith
is to promote a mentality that seeks to overcome the domination system
based on demonic power, accordingly, it must be a postclassical form of
Christian faith. The call for a postmodern Christianity must not be
confused with a call a postliberal form, which would involve a return to
aspects of classical Christianity that have been so useful to the demonic.
We need a theology that is fully liberal, in the sense of completely
rejecting classical Christian theology’s supernaturalism and
authoritarianism. It is equally important, of course, that this theology
be postmodern, in the sense of both rejecting and providing an effective
alternative to the modern ideologies of power. I turn now some
distinctive aspects of these ideologies.
Early Modern Ideology
To a great extent,
the early modern worldview was simply an intensification of the
supernaturalism of the classical Christian worldview. For example,
Calvinism, with its accentuation of divine omnipotence and its insistence
on the equal authority of all the Bible interpreted literally, was a major
influence on, and in fact an integral aspect of, the early modern
worldview. Calvinists were primary among those European Christians who
used the Hebrew view of God as a holy warrior, leading the Israelites in
their battles against the inhabitants of the land of Canaan, to justify
taking America from its prior inhabitants.
A distinctive aspect
of modern ideology was its insistence on the mechanistic view of nature,
according to which nature is wholly devoid of any spontaneity, any
experience, any intrinsic value, and therefore any divine presence. This
doctrine, especially its denial of all spontaneity to matter, was at first
regarded as an implication of divine omnipotence. In any case, it was
used to sanction the primary interest of early modern thinkers, such as
Francis Bacon: the domination of nature for human benefit. If nature is
completely devoid of any intrinsic value, and was in fact created solely
for humanity’s use, it could be exploited with impunity.
The other
distinctive feature of modern ideology, as I stressed in the first
lecture, was its sensationist theory of perception. What this amounted
to, with regard to values, was a completely supernaturalistic explanation
of how we know right from wrong: We know it entirely through supernatural
revelation or (for more deistic thinkers) thanks to a supernatural
implantation at creation. In either case, the demise of supernaturalism
would lead to nihilism.
This early modern
worldview, with its supernatur-alism and anthropocentrism, is in large
part the worldview of contemporary evangelical and fundamentalist
Christians. One of the tasks of a postmodern theology is to show people
who (rightly) want a robust Christian faith that they can have it without
the authoritarian method and destructive worldview that have been so
central to the great increase in demonic power brought about in the modern
period.
Late
Modern Ideology
Although the early
modern ideology has been extremely useful in promoting the growth of
demonic power, even it has been outdone by the late modern ideology. With
its creation the demonic has, at last, created an ideology wholly in its
own image. This ideology, unlike that of classical Christianity and the
early modern period, contains no restraints whatsoever on the unbridled
use of power to achieve domination over nature and other peoples.
The atheism of this
late modern worldview says, in effect, that the universe has been created
by, and is now controlled by, blind omnipotence. Having rightly concluded
that the problems of evil and evolution, along with other considerations,
render implausible the view that the universe is a product of intelligent
coercion, late modernists have thought of the universe’s creative power in
terms of blind coercion (thereby rejecting or ignoring the other
possibility, intelligent persuasion). In the capitalistic world, this
blind coercive power has been thought of, in Darwinians and Social
Darwinian6
terms, as the survival of the fittest via natural or social
selection. The world is created and improved, in other words, through
ruthless competition, with no pity for the weak. In the Marxist world,
this blind coercion was conceived in different (more dialectical) terms,
but the same kind of ruthless unconcern for the weak was promoted. The
end justified any and all means.
A central
implication of the idea that the ultimate creative is blind, of course, is
that it does not envisage any values. The religious desire to imitate the
supreme power of the universe, has led late modern humans to exercise
power without any principles based on moral values. To be sure,
value-laden rhetoric has been employed, as Machiavelli recommended. But
late modernists “know” the belief that values truly exist in the nature of
things to be ilIusory.7
The materialistic world view has no place for values to abide, and the
sensationist theory of perception, when no longer part of a
supernaturalistic worldview, would not allow for the genuine perception of
values even if they did exist. All rhetoric employing value-notions is,
accordingly, just that: rhetoric, useful for the battle for power in
relation to people who still share the illusion that values are genuine.
This late modern
ideology, besides providing a justification for state’s unprincipled use
of power, also provides individuals no basis for resisting this power.
Freedom is said to be unreal, so it not provide a rallying cry. And
there are no other objective values, such as justice, in the name of which
the state’s power could challenged. This complete relativism, in fact,
implies an ultimate nihilism, according to which there is no ultimate
meaning whatsoever. Why risk one’s life or even comfort to protest
policies if, in the long run, nothing matters anyway?
The issue of risking
one’s life brings up a final denial by which modern ideology undermines
vigorous protest against the unprincipled use of power: the denial of life
after death. Through this denial, human beings are told that there is no
aspect of them that is not subject to the state’s coercive power. A
widely accepted aspect of late modern ideology, to be sure, is that it is
the belief in life after death, not the absence of such belief, that makes
people docile in the face of injustice. It is true that this belief can
and sometimes has been used as an “opiate.” But the denial of life after
death, with its implication that one’s total identity is subject to the
state’s power, can be far more effective in preventing serious protest.
This critique of
classical Christian theology and early and late modern ideology in terms
of their subjugation to, and furtherance of, demonic power has necessarily
been brief and selective. But it should at least provide some idea of
what a full-fledged ideology critique from this perspective would be like.
In any case, this discussion, as inadequate as it is, will have to serve
as the background to the formulation of liberal (and thereby
postclassical) postmodern Christian doctrines.
II.
Postmodern Christian Doctrines
In contrast with the
atheistic naturalism of late modernity, the postmodern worldview affirms
the reality of God. The supreme power of the universe is not insentient
matter, or a blind process, but a purposive reality who loves the world
and all its creatures. Normative values, accordingly, such as truth,
beauty, and the various forms of goodness, such as justice, need not be
assumed to be illusory or mere projections, created perhaps for
ideological purposes. Rather, we can understand our apprehension of such
values as part of our experience of God’s valuations, as, in other words,
the causal influence of God upon our experience. We can understand this
influence of God as the way in which God works in human history in a
creative, providential, and liberating manner.
In contrast with the
supernaturalistic theism of classical Christianity, however, the theism of
postmodern Christianity is fully naturalistic. God acts in relation to
humans only in this persuasive way, and in relation to other
creatures only in an analogous way. Because all creatures necessarily
and inherently have their own creative power, God’s power is
exclusively persuasive. There is not another kind of power, a
coercive power, held in reserve, which could be employed occasionally or
at the end of history to guarantee the desired outcome. This doctrine
means, accordingly, that no event is ever unilaterally determined by God,
which in turn means that there can be no infallible revelation, no
inerrant inspiration. It also means that belief in God is not undermined
by the problem of evil, the evolutionary origin of our world, and the
other factors that undermined classical theism. It means, finally, that
there is no reason to doubt the New Testament’s claim that God loves us
fully and without qualification, and that God is unambiguously opposed to
the demonic.
What about the
notion that God is triune—a central part of classical Christianity’s
supernaturalism that I did not discuss above? In classical Christian
theism, the idea of the trinity was the idea of three persons who were in
some sense three centers of consciousness. This notion was used to defend
the notion, which was at the root of supernaturalism, that God could exist
apart from any world whatsoever. That is, the Christian idea that God is
love, that love belongs to the eternal nature of God, might be thought to
imply that there has always been a world for God to love. That would
threaten the idea that God created the world ex nihilo. But the
classical notion of the trinity solved that problem, explaining that God’s
eternal love involves the relations among the members of the trinity: They
eternally love each other. This idea was used to argue that God’s love
for the world was optional, purely voluntary. The notion of the
trinity as three centers of consciousness also provided the presupposition
for classical Christianity’s supernaturalistic christology, according to
which the second person of the trinity was uniquely present in Jesus,
which made Christianity the One True Religion.
Although some
versions of naturalistic theism have rejected trinitarianism altogether,
partly because of these historic associations between it and
supernaturalism, a postmodern Christian faith can actually use the notion
that God is triune to express its naturalistic theism. For example, a
trinitarian approach to God has traditionally been used to describe three
ways in which we can know God. This can be called the “epistemic
trinity.” The revelation of God through the natural order has been
correlated especially with God the Father, the revelation through history
especially with the Son, and the revelation in our immediate experience
with the Holy Spirit. Naturalistic theists can employ this epistemic
trinitarianism (without the androcentric imagery) to express our
conviction that God works always and everywhere in one and the same way.
We would start where the revelation of God’s mode of activity is most
immediate, namely, in our own experience. Here we see that God acts on us
in terms of values, calling us to live in terms of truth, beauty, and the
various forms of moral goodness, such as justice. Seeing God at work in
our value experience is, no doubt, influenced by the fact that we
understand God through spectacles provided by the Bible. Paul, for
example, describes the Holy Spirit’s effects on us in terms of various
values, such as love, joy, peace, patience, kindness, goodness,
faithfulness, gentleness, and self-control (Gal. 5:22-23). In any case,
it is as persuading us in terms of values that we can understand how God
can influence human lives.
We can then
generalize what we know from immediate experience to the other ways in
which we know God. This generalization can be based on the doctrine that
all three aspects of the trinity are homoousion, and the related
notion that what is true of one aspect is true of all three. So, we can
say that God’s activity in history is of the same nature as God’s activity
in our own experience. We can, in particular, use this notion to
understand God’s activity in Jesus. In this way, we can develop a
christology that avoids any implication of supernatural intervention.
Such a christology can say that God’s incarnation in Jesus was special,
but that this specialness entails no supernaturalism.
The main empirical
support for the idea that God was supernaturally incarnate in Jesus was
provided, of course, by the reports of the miracles of Jesus. Early
modern philosophy was created in part, as I explained in the first
lecture, to say that such events would have to be given a supernatural
interpretation. From a postmodern perspective, however, events involving
action at a distance in general, and nonsensory perception in particular,
can be accepted as purely natural. We need not, accordingly, choose
between the traditional view that these events prove Jesus’ supernatural
status and the late modern a priori denial that any events of this
type happened. The science of psychical research (or parapsychology), in
other words, is an important ally in developing a credible naturalistic
theology.
The next question,
in developing a naturalistic trinity, is whether the way that God works in
our immediate experience, and in history in general, can be extended to
God’s activity in nature. That is, can we imagine God as influencing not
only other animals, but also cells and even molecules in terms of values?
Such a suggestion would seem absurd, of course, from the standpoint of
modern thought, which regards natural entities, below some line, as
insentient bits of matter, devoid of all experience and therefore all
value-realization. Our constructive postmodern theology, however, is
based on panexperientialism, according to which experience of some sort
goes all the way down. From this perspective, accordingly, we can
generalize from God’s activity in relation to all individuals. In this
way, our postmodern theology overcomes one of the major weaknesses of
modern liberal theologies, their inability to speak of God’s creative and
providential work in nature.
From this
perspective, furthermore, there can be a postmodern recovery of another
traditional way of articulating God’s threefold activity in the world. I
refer to those Trinitarian formulations that speak of God’s activity at
the beginning, the middle, and the end of the
world—for example, of God as creator, redeemer, and consummator. This can
be called the “temporal trinity.” In classical theology, God’s activity
at the beginning and the end was imagined to be very different from God’s
activity in the middle. God’s activity in the middle—that is, in relation
to human history—was said in general to be persuasive activity. Aside
from occasional miracles and the unique incarnation in Jesus, God was said
generally to abstain from using coercive power in relation to humans. God
called, and we either accepted or rejected the call. Jesus’ call to
people to follow him could be regarded as revelatory of God’s way of
relating to human beings. But this divine modus operandi could
not, in classical theology, be generalized to God’s activity at the
beginning. God’s activity in creating the world had to be understood in
terms of overwhelming coercive power. Even aside from the issue as to
whether nature can respond to values, a world such as ours could not have
been created in six days by the use of persuasive power. A naturalistic
theism, according to which God acts in the beginning in the same way in
which God acts in the middle, was impossible.
However, just as the
science of parapsychology came to the rescue with regard to miracles,
evolutionary science comes to the rescue with regard to creation. We now
know that our world, rather than being created in six days, was created in
something like 16 billion years. This quantitative difference is so great
that is suggests a qualitative difference in the nature of God’s
creative activity. The idea that God spent some 16 billion years creating
our world suggests that God’s creative power must be persuasive, not
coercive, power. This is the natural inference, that is, if we continue
to think of the world as God’s creation. Modern liberal theology, having
no way to think of God’s activity in relation to nature, generally gave up
the notion of the world as God’s creation in any straightforward sense. A
postmodern theology, however, can recover the doctrine of God as creator,
by understanding God’s creative activity in nature in terms of persuasion
to actualize values of certain types. This is a postmodern view of the
world as God’s creation, rather than a return to a premodern or early
modern view, because it is naturalistic: We can understand God’s activity
at the beginning of our universe as of the same type as God’s activity in
history. No supernatural origin must be assumed.
We still have,
however, the question of God’s activity at the end. Can God as
consummator be understood in the same terms? Classical theologians
certainly did not think so. For example, a book entitled Armageddon
says:
The second coming of
Jesus Christ to earth will be no quiet manger scene. . . . Cities will
literally collapse, islands sink, and mountains disappear. Huge
hailstones, each weighing a hundred pounds, will fall from heaven. . . , [T]he
rulers and their armies who resist Christ’s return will be killed in a
mass carnage.8
No more Mister Nice
Guy! According to this theology, in other words, God’s past mode of
activity in Jesus would not suffice to bring about the eventual victory of
divine over demonic power. God would have to resort to a degree of
violence that would outdo the violence of the forces of evil. The
revelation of God’s love in Jesus was not, accordingly, a revelation of
the divine modus operandi: The true nature of divine power, which
is supernatural, has been, for the most part, held in reserve, and will be
fully manifested only at the end.
Modern liberal
theology overcame this supernaturalistic notion of the consummation of
history by giving up the notion of a final victory of divine over demonic
power altogether. In some versions, it did this by minimizing the reality
of evil, denying in effect that there is any demonic evil to be overcome.
But more realistic modern theologies overcame the notion of a
supernatural victory over demonic power by, more or less explicitly,
giving up hope that such a victory will ever occur. In Reinhold Niebuhr’s
theology, for example, salvation is virtually equated with justification;
there is little talk of sanctification. Niebuhr denies that divine power
will eventually overcome the power of sin.
By rejecting modern
assumptions; however, we can recover, in postmodern form, the expectation
of God’s eventual defeat of the demonic. The central basis for this
recovery is that, from a postmodern perspective, we can again speak of
life beyond physical death. This is a complex topic, which I have treated
at length elsewhere. Here I can only point to the central elements in the
postmodern approach that allow for life after death. One element is the
distinction between the mind or soul and the brain, which
panexperientialism allows. That is, the dualism of the early modern
worldview allowed for such a distinction, but because it could not explain
how mind and brain could interact, it collapsed, therefore, into the
materialism of the late modern view, which declares mind and brain to be
somehow identical. This identism makes life after death inconceivable, at
least in a naturalistic context that allows for no supernatural
resurrection of the body. Panexperientialism, however, by being able to
explain how mind and body can interact, enables us to reaffirm the
distinction between mind and brain.
While that
distinction provides one of the necessary conditions for the possibility
of life after death without supernatural intervenparapsychology provides
some others.9
Many thinkers have assumed that we would not be able to exist apart from
our bodies only because continued existence is unthinkable apart from
experience, which is true, but also because they believe that perception
is impossible without the body’s sensory organs. Evidence for telepathy
and clairvoyance has demonstrated, however, what panexperientialism
suggests, which is that we have nonsensory perceptions. Now, of
course, these nonsensory perceptions generally do not rise to
consciousness, because they are usually crowded out by sensory
perceptions. In a discarnate state, however, any of these nonsensory
perceptions might regularly be conscious. This is what is suggested, in
fact, by reports of near-death experiences and other out-of-body
experiences. Another objection to any meaningful life after death is
that, without our bodies, we would not be able to act. But evidence for
psychokinesis demonstrates what panexperiential-ism suggests, which is
that we can even now act directly upon other things, apart from bodily
mediation. In a postcarnate state this power might also become
regularized. Besides showing the possibility of life after death,
furthermore, parapsychology also provides rather impressive evidence for
its actuality.10
Supernaturalists resist this evidence, because it undermines the
uniqueness of Jesus’ resurrection appearances. This insistence on the
absolute uniqueness of Jesus’ resurrection, however, has contributed to
the arrogance of supernaturalist Christianity, on the one hand, and to the
general loss of belief in life after death altogether, on the other. By
reaffirming the reality of Jesus’ resurrection and our own life after
death, on the basis of experience and reason, we recover within a liberal
framework the essential concern of conservative Christians on this point.
From this
standpoint, in turn, we can recover the hope for an eventual
sanctification of our souls within the framework of a theistic naturalism.
The belief in life after death plays the same role in relation to this
issue as the belief in evolution plays with regard to understanding the
creation of our universe in terms of divine persuasive power. That is,
just as the evolutionary perspective extends the history of the world far
into the past, belief in life after death extends our own spiritual
journey far into the future. In both cases, the time available for the
effects to be achieved is so extended that it becomes credible that a
divine power, acting by persuasive power alone, could bring about these
effects. From the point of view of modern liberal theology, God had only
our present lifetime to work on our souls. Given that presupposition, it
was indeed realistic to be very skeptical of the divine power to
transfigure you and me. Classical Protestant theology, having rejected
the notion of purgatory, also assumed that God’s persuasive grace had only
the present lifetime to work on us; it held, accordingly, that the actual
transformation of our souls into fit inhabitants for heaven would be
effected unilaterally, by God’s supernatural power. If we assume,
however, that our trinitarian God has a very long time to batter our
hearts with divine values, we can realistically believe that this divine
power will eventually overcome our present subjugation to demonic values.
In this eschatology, there are no threats of supernatural punishment, as
if the only effective kind of divine persuasion were a very coercive
persuasion, in which God scares the hell out of us. In this naturalistic
eschatology, God eventually loves the hell out of us, thereby
demonstrating what should be the fundamental axiom of Christian faith,
that love—God’s love for the world—is the supreme power in the universe.
One practical
implication of this perspective is that it recovers, in postmodern form,
the notion of human life as a spiritual journey. People can, to be sure,
understand their lives this way even apart from life after death. But the
loss of that belief has probably been the most important reason why modern
human beings in general, and modern liberal theologians in particular, do
not generally think of life as a spiritual journey. By contrast, when
people recover, especially in a naturalistic context, the notion that our
present life is part of a larger journey, they tend to begin seeing
spiritual development as the most important thing in life. Some sort of
spiritual discipline becomes more important than the search for pleasure,
power, fame, or riches.11
This postmodern
theology also provides other presuppositions of a life of spiritual
self-discipline that late modern thought undermined. One such
presupposition is that we have genuine freedom. Self-discipline makes no
sense apart from the power of self-determination. The postmodern view of
the mind-body relation shows how our minds can have this power. Another
presupposition is the objective existence of values. If there are no such
values, as modern materialism implies, then there are no standards in
terms of which we should discipline our power of self-determination. The
postmodern view that such values exist in God, and that God acts upon our
souls by whetting our appetites for these values, provides the basis for
understanding how values can be transcendent to our experience and also
immanent in it. The other postmodern support for this notion is the
recognition of our nonsensory perception, which we can be receptive to the
divinely-rooted values.
While the reality of
freedom and values supports the meaningfulness of spiritual discipline,
yet another dimension of theology supports its importance, indeed its
necessity. I refer here to the recognition that our souls influence the
world our bodies, for good or ill, not only through the mediation our
bodies, but also directly. Most importantly, we directly influence other
human souls for good or for ill. And, insofar as our influence is for
ill, we thereby contribute to the demonic power on our planet, adding to
the demonic aspect of the general psychic matrix into which other souls
are born and by which they are influenced willy-nilly. The contrary view,
which is that we only influence the world through our bodies—through our
words, actions, and facial expressions—promotes the complacent view that
we can be successful hypocrites: that we will do no harm to anyone as long
as we watch our words and body language. But insofar as we recognize the
reality of psychokinesis and nonsensory perception, we will recognize that
hypocrisy cannot be totally successful. What we are inside will have its
effects, regardless of our external demeanor. And these effects may well
be lethal. As Carl Jung recognized, spiritual discipline is important not
only for the sake of our own individual journeys, but also for the sake of
the world.12
I have been
discussing several elements involved in the postmodern recovery of the
hope for the eventual victory of divine over demonic power. Yet another
element in this recovery, of course, is the conception of the demonic
itself. Because I have already developed this notion at some length, I
will here simply refer to some of its main implications for the question
of its eventual overcoming. One important point is that the demonic is
very much a latecomer, having emerged as a real possibility only about
fifty thousand years ago, and having actually emerged only within the last
10,000 years, after the rise of civilization. Unlike classical
Christianity, then, which came perilously close to Manicheanism, this new
perspective says that demonic evil has not distorted God’s creation
virtually from the beginning, and that it has not even infected human
existence from virtually its beginning. Human existence has existed
without the curse of demonic evil for far longer than it has suffered
under it. This perspective can help us affirm with conviction that life,
including human life, is essentially good. Original sin is dwarfed by
original blessing.13
Besides not being
original in the sense of going back to the origin of humanity as such,
“original sin” is not now somehow inherent in human nature as such.
Rather than being a state or tendency originating from the depths of the
human soul as such, it is to be understood more as a power to which our
souls are subjugated,14
a power that arose in history under particular conditions. We can,
accordingly, suppose that, when we no longer live under those conditions,
the power of divine love will be able to overcome our present subjugation
to demonic impulses. This provides a basis for understanding the medieval
idea that sins that are not purged from our souls in this world by divine
power will be purged in a future state.
This perspective on
the demonic does not, however, offer hope only for the victory of divine
over demonic power in a post-earthly existence. It also provides a basis
for seeing that the present subjugation of the earth to demonic power can
be overcome. If the demonic arose historically, there is no reason to be
resigned to its perpetual existence. If it arose with the emergence of
civilization, and if we can identify that dimension of civilization that
led to its rise, then we will know what needs to be overcome in order to
overcome the demonic itself. I have suggested that this dimension of
civilization as it has existed thus far is its anarchy. What we need to
do, therefore, is to move toward a post-anarchical form of civilization.
This means moving towards a form of global governance, in which
inter-state relations are settled not in terms of brute power, but in
terms of democratic deliberations on the good of the whole, which would
make values, such as truth, beauty, and fairness, politically relevant.
From this perspective, the past several thousand years, which so-called
realists have taken as normative, is instead to be an aberrant interlude.
The idea of a primal paradise can, while being an exaggeration, be taken
as an authentic memory of a time before the rise of the demonic. The idea
of a future of God on earth can be accepted as a true intuition or
revelation of a form of civilization that could really come about, if we
can survive and transcend our present aberration.
If the church would
come to accept this postmodern theology, its mission would be clear. It
would see its task to be that of seeking, through its message and
activity, to lead the way in God’s battle against demonic power. There
would be two foci to this effort. On the one hand, the church would help
individuals in their personal spiritual journeys to overcome, as fully as
possible, their subjugation to demonic influence. Important in his regard
is the postmodern recovery of the various doctrines I have discussed
related to the power of God, the power of the soul, the reality of values,
and the reality of life after death.
On the other hand,
the church would seek to lead the way in overcoming the power of the
demonic in the public sphere. It would do all it can to weaken the hold
of demonic values upon our various institutions, such as schools,
corporations, congress, and the presidency. This effort should be carried
out in terms of both spiritual and physical means. That is, the
postmodern liberal church, like the modern liberal church, should engage
in ethical and political activity as usually understood. But this
activity should be carried out in the context of a spiritual
offensive, in which the power of prayer is used to reinforce the divine
influence upon the individuals and institutions involved. Praying for
those who are especially enslaved to demonic power, and who are
incarnating it in especially destructive ways, will not only serve to
remind us that they are essentially good creatures of God who are loved by
God and that our battle is not with them but with the power to which they
are enslaved. It will also greatly increase the church’s effectiveness.
The modern liberal church’s ineffectiveness can, in fact, be attributed
to a significant degree to the fact that it has not believed in the
reality of spiritual influence.
The postmodern
recovery of belief in life after death can help empower Christians to
battle valiantly against demonic power in high places. As I suggested
above, if we believe that our essential identity is in the hands of the
state, it is very hard to protest strongly against the state’s
participation in demonic activities, such as Nazi Germany’s genocide
against European Jews, the Soviet Union’s murderous purges under Stalin,
or the United States’ villainy in Vietnam and its leadership in the
nuclear arms race. The postmodern recovery of life after death can
provide a necessary condition for courage to overcome the demonic’s
intimidating power.
However, if the
church restricts its efforts in the public sphere to improving our
institutions within the present structure of civilization, it will
continue to fight a losing battle. Within the context of anarchical
civilization, the reign of demonic power necessarily grows increasingly
stronger. The church in our time should understand its commitment to the
coming rule of God, which it repeats in every utterance of the Lord’s
Prayer, primarily to entail its wholehearted commitment to overcoming the
anarchic stage of civilization. This means envisioning and then working
for a plan for global governance. This is, of course, an enormous and
controversial topic, to which I can here only allude. I am, however, at
work on a book tentatively entitled “The Divine Cry of Our Time: War,
Religion, and a New World Order.” With that title I signal my conviction
that the emergence of a peaceable and sustainable form of civilization
must be assumed to be the chief concern of God for our planet in this
time. In working for this goal, the church should employ the same twofold
means, carrying on its physical activities in the context of a mighty
spiritual effort.
In sum, the church
should understand its mission as that of serving as a counterforce to the
demonic dimension of the psychic matrix in which the human race lives. We
should understand God’s incarnationaI activity in Jesus as a divine
offensive against the spreading power of the demonic. There is no better
source for understanding Jesus in these terms than Walter Wink’s trilogy
on the powers, especially the third volume, Engaging the Powers.
The church, as the intentional extension of this liberating incarnation
in Jesus, should be an opposing field of force, an instrument, perhaps the
chief instrument, through which divine power liberates the world from
subjugation to demonic power before it is too late.15
Notes
1
In a book tentatively titled ‘‘The Divine Cry of Our Time: War, Religion,
and a New World Order.”
2
For references, see Chapter 5 of James H. Evans, Jr., We Have Been
Believers: An African-American Systematic Theology (Minneapolis:
Fortress, 1992).
3
See Ernest Lee Tuveson, Redeemer Nation: The Idea of America’s
Millennial Role (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968).
4
This point has been made by Charles E. Raven, The Theological Basis of
Christian Pacifism (New York: Fellowship Publications, 1951), 36-37.
5
See Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker (New York: W. Norton,
1987).
6
See Richard Hofstadter, Social Darwinism in American Thought, rev.
ed. (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955).
7
See Stephen P.L. Turner and Regis A. Factor, Max Weber and the Dispute
over Reason and Value: A Study in Philosophy, Ethics, and Politics
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984).
8
John F. and John E. Walvoord, Armageddon: Oil and the Middle East
Crisis (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1976); quoted in
Robert Jewett, Jesus Against the Rapture (Philadelphia:
Westminster, 1979), 16.
9
For a fuller discussion of the ideas to follow, see my “Postmodern Animism
and Life After Death,” which is Chapter 6 of God and Religion in the
Postmodern World, or “Parapsychology and Philosophy” (see note 8 of
the first lecture).
10
For an overview, see David Lorimer, Survival? Body, Mind and Death in
the Light of Psychic Experience (London and Boston: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1984), Chapters 8-11.
11
This is a central point of a book, tentatively titled “Parapsychology,
Philosophy, and Spirituality,” which I anticipate publishing in 1995.
[Parapsychology,
Philosophy, and Spirituality: A Postmodern Exploration.
Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997. – A. F.]
12
C. G. Jung, Memories, Dreams, Recollections, ed. Aneila Jaffe,
trans. Richard and Clara Winston (New York: Random House, 1963), 192, 252.
13
The allusion is to Matthew Fox’s Original Blessing (Santa Fe: Bear
and Co., 1983).
14
I was first led to this conception by Arthur C. McGill’s Suffering: A
Test of Theological Method (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1982),
which I have discussed in “Power Divine and Demonic: A Review Article,”
Encounter 45:1 (Winter 1984):67-75.
15
These lectures, especially the second, are based in part on research done
while I was a Fellow at the Rockefeller Foundation’s Study and Conference
Center at Bellagio, Italy, in September and October of 1992. I hereby
publicly express my gratitude for this grand opportunity. Bellagio is as
close to Heaven on Earth for Scholars as any of us will ever find.
Back to Table of Contents
Posted September 12, 2007
Go to David Ray Griffin Page