From Encountering
Evil: Live Options in Theodicy, Stephen T. Davis, ed. Atlanta,
John Knox Press, 1981. A revised edition was published in 2001. (See
Amazon link in left column.) Professor Griffin's publications on the
problem of evil include two books: God, Power, and Evil: A Process
Theodicy, Philadelphia: Westminster, 1976; reprinted with a new
preface, Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1991; and Evil
Revisited: Responses and Reconsiderations, Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1991. (See Amazon links in left
column.)
Responses to Critiques
David Ray Griffin
There are
numerous issues raised in the foregoing critiques [by John K.
Roth, John H.
Hick, Frederick
Sontag, and Stephen T.
Davis]. I will organize my responses
to them under nine points. The first four deal with more limited
issues, and partly attempt to clear up misunderstandings. The latter
five deal with much more wide-ranging issues, including the basic
issue of what Christian faith and theology are all about. These
points reflect the fact that theodicy is only one part of the total
theological enterprise.
(1) Hick and
Davis both evidently misunderstand the distinction between “genuine”
and “apparent” evil. It may help to introduce a third term, “prima
facie evil.” This refers to anything that is taken to be evil at
first glance, as it were. The question is whether at least some of
this prima facie evil is genuinely evil, i.e., whether
it results in the world’s being a worse place than it might have
otherwise been, all things considered. If one were to conclude, upon
reflection, that there were no genuine evil, one would be asserting
that all prima facie evil were merely apparently evil,
i.e., that it was not evil at all. That was the position adopted by
traditional theists such as Augustine, Aquinas, and Luther.
Roth and Sontag
clearly reject this view. The positions of Hick and Davis are less
clear. They evidently think they can, without contradiction, affirm
that genuine evil exists and yet that all evil will be used to
contribute to a state better than which none is possible.
Hick’s
affirmation is clearer, as he speaks of a “limitlessly good
end-state.” If it is “limitlessly good, there would seem to be no
possible state that would be better. Hence, none of the evil is
genuine––it does not result in the world’s being a worse place overall
than it could have been.
Davis is less
clear, speaking of “the great good of the kingdom of God.” If he
means this to be the greatest possible state of affairs (or at least
one of the greatest possible), then he too has denied the
genuineness of evil––all evil is merely apparent. But if he means
only that the kingdom of God will be a great good, but less great than
it could have been, then he should tell us why his God is perfectly
good if this God allows the world to come to a worse conclusion that
would have been possible. Why didn’t his God use the divine
omnipotence to bring about the best possible result?
This is the
dilemma of those espousing omnipotence: they must either admit that
God is not totally good, or else deny that any of the prima facie
evil in the world is really evil. And if they say the latter, I fail
to see how their view finally differs from that of Mary Baker
Eddy (Davis’ protest notwithstanding).
(2) This leads
into the question of “common notions.” I claimed that the idea that
genuinely evil things occur is one of the “common notions” of
humanity, those things we all know to be true. Hick and Davis demur,
saying that not all people agree to this. Of course, a lot of people
have said that no genuine evil exists. But I defined a common
notion as one of those things that all people affirm in practice,
regardless of what they may say. Just as all Humeans
reveal in practice that they know that some things causally affect
other things, I claim that the emotions, attitudes, and actions of all
people manifest their conviction that some things have happened that
should not have happened. So, if Hick and Davis do finally deny that
any genuine evil occurs, I believe they are contradicting verbally
something they affirm in practice.
(3) Roth asks for
evidence for my hypothesis that every increase in the capacity for
positive enjoyment is necessarily an increase in the capacity to
suffer. In trying (unsuccessfully) to provide a counter example, Roth
seems to misunderstand the nature of my position. I am simply
pointing to the correlations that in fact exist, from the
bottom to the top of the evolutionary scale, and then suggesting that
these correlations exist necessarily (because of metaphysical
truths inherent in the nature of things), rather than being due to
accident or the arbitrary fiat of a creator. It simply is a fact––at
least most of us believe it to be so––that fleas can enjoy more and
suffer more than single-cell organisms, dogs more than fleas, humans
more than dogs, and normal adult humans more than babies. Increased
complexity in the structure of an individual means increased capacity
for enjoyment and for suffering. The correlation exists
universally. I am only suggesting that this universal correlation
exists necessarily, so that it would necessarily obtain in any
world God could create.
My suggestion is
a speculative hypothesis. But it is more grounded in empirical
reality than the contrary hypothesis, accepted implicitly or
explicitly by other four authors. For, they are asserting (Roth and
Sontag), or at least assuming (Davis and Hick), that there are
possible worlds in which this correlation does not exist. This is an
empirically groundless speculation, since we have never experienced
a world in which this correlation does not exist. Hence we do not
know that such a world is really possible. But we know that a world in
which the correlation holds is possible, since ours is such a world.
Hence my speculation is much more modest and rooted in
empirical reality, since my speculation is limited to the suggestion
that the way things are (in terms of this aspect of our world)
may be the ways have to be. Recognizing that the contrary
hypothesis is not only responsible for the problem of evil, but is
also based on a groundless flight of fancy, may be enough to free
people from its embittering grip.
(4) Davis demands
an argument for the hypothesis that all actual individuals have power
of their own with which they can resist God’s will. In other words,
why is not the view that God has a monopoly on power a coherent and
hence possibly true view of the world? I have provided some
argumentation for this in God, Power, and Evil, especially
Chapters 7, 14, 16, 17 and 18. To the points made there I will add
one similar to the one made above in regard to the correlations: it
does seem to be the case that every actual individual has power. And
if God be conceived (e.g., on the basis of Christian faith) to be
perfectly good, the most natural hypothesis is that this power
includes the power to go contrary to God’s will. All the authors in
this book agree that at least some creature have this power. My
hypothesis is simply that all creaturely individuals have this power
necessarily, i.e. that creaturely individuals in any
world God could create would have this power.
Again, my
hypothesis simply takes a fundamental aspect of the empirical
situation and suggests that this aspect obtains necessarily. The
other authors, in holding that the freedom of the creatures to go
contrary to God’s will is due to a voluntary relinquishment of power
by God, are indulging in a much more speculative hypothesis. For they
do not have any experientially-based knowledge that a world of totally
controlled actualities is even possible. Hence, the demand for
argumentation falls much more heavily on their own hypothesis than on
mine. The mere fact that they represent the majority viewpoint in the
history of Christian thought and within this book does not change this
situation, though it tends to disguise it.
(5) I begin now
the points that reflect differences in our understandings of what
Christian faith and theology are all about. As I argued in my essay,
a theodicy is simply one part of an overall theological position.
Positively, this
means that to defend one’s theodicy means finally to defend one’s
entire theological position. (For example, Davis would need to
defend, in the light of the historical-critical study of the Bible in
the past 200 years, his assertion that we can still responsibly take
the Bible as an external guarantee of the truth of particular
propositions.)
Negatively, this
means that one’s theodicy is not necessarily inadequate because of its
failure to fit into someone else’s total theological position.
Yet theologians keep forgetting this. Since Roth, Sontag and Davis
hold to the traditional doctrine of omnipotence, the fact that the
world is pervaded by evil is a severe threat to the notion that there
is a God worthy of worship.
Because they do
not share Hick’s faith that divine persuasion will eventually overcome
all evil, they can justify allegiance to their God (even in the
half-way fashion advocated by Roth) only by expecting an extraordinary
act of God in which things will suddenly and dramatically change.
They then look at my doctrine of God’s power and conclude that it is
inadequate since it does not support the kind of eschatological hope
that is necessary to solve the problem of evil that was created by
their doctrine of divine power.
Davis sums up
their sentiments: “I do not believe the problem of evil can be solved
from a Christian perspective without crucial reference to the
future.” That is true for them. But within my theological
perspective God’s creative activity can be seen as the expression of
perfect goodness apart from any expectation for a radical change in
the nature of finite existence, and even apart from any expectation of
continued consciousness after bodily death.
(6) Another
complex issue concerns the basis from which one constructs a doctrine
of God. Sontag and Roth portray me as having a “natural theology” and
a “Greek” God rather than a theology based upon the biblical,
especially the New Testament, revelation. These are matters of
judgment. Is their view that the divine power of the universe is
partly good and partly evil less of a “natural” theology than the view
suggested by Plato and most of the bible that God is the source only
of good? Is their view of partly malevolent deity closer to the New
Testament than my view, in which a God of perfect love is battling
against other powers?
In any case, to
take revelation seriously means, to me, to take what has
actually happened more seriously in forming our doctrines than the
ideas spun out of imaginative flights. And what actually happened
during the history that the “people of the book” take to be
revelatory? God’s “chosen” people are constantly defeated. God’s
prophets are stoned. And the one whom Christians take to be God’s
decisive revelation was crucified. There is nothing in this picture
that suggests that the God served possesses controlling power. Nor
does anything in the following two thousand years, including and
especially the Jewish Holocaust.
Sontag and Roth
think that the resurrection of Jesus supports their doctrine of
omnipotence. But what does the resurrection of Jesus reveal, in terms
of divine power? At most, that God has the power to renew life after
bodily death. It emphatically does not reveal that God created
the world ex nihilo, or that God can change the basic structure
of existence as we know it. That doctrine of omnipotence is not based
upon historical revelation, but upon imaginative flights designed to
fill egocentric wishes. Sontag admits as much, saying that “we must
decide what we expect God to do and then outline a doctrine about a
God who has power commensurate with his responsibilities and our
expectations.” Should we not instead try to discover what God is
like, on the basis of the revelation history provides us and our best
reasoning on the basis of this revelation, and then reform our
expectations in this light?
(7) Closely
related is the charge made by Sontag, Roth, and Davis that my doctrine
is “optimistic.” For this to be a source of reproach, they must mean
unrealistically optimistic. Their point is that their
view is much more realistic than mine, as they know, in Sontag’s
words, that “evil is pervasive e of the very structure of nature and
human nature,” so that God with only persuasive power could never
bring about an end to evil. Hence, they posit a God with controlling
power.
I cannot but
wonder why they find their doctrine less unrealistically optimistic
than mine. To expect, after all that has happened which any decent
being with controlling power would have stopped, that God is going to
act differently than ever before, bringing about a complete change in
the structure of existence, seems the height of unrealistic optimism.
Again, Sontag is at least candid, saying that a theodicy should be
based upon our hopes, not on our ideas of what is “likely.”
Since they have
no faith in the persuasive power of love to effect salvation, they see
my position as providing no basis for hope. It is true that my
position supplies no guarantee that we will not destroy ourselves and
perhaps all life on this planet. But there would be more basis for
hope in this regard if those who worship God would disconnect this
worship from the assumption that this God has the power
unilaterally to prevent this disaster. The complacency promoted
by this unrealistic belief is one of the reasons, in my view, that
people of good will have allowed the world to get into such a hopeless
state. There will be more basis for hope for this world when more
people perceive that God’s modus operandi is to save us
through our activities, not in spite of them.
(There is, I
believe, a sense in which our salvation is effected by God alone,
without any co-operation being required of us. But salvation in this
sense involves saving our lives from ultimate meaninglessness, from
making no difference in the ultimate scheme of things. But it is a
mistake of utmost seriousness to transmute the intuition of this truth
into the baseless doctrine that the reformation of our individual
lives and/or our world will be effected by God unilaterally.)
(8) The
differences between me and some of the other authors on the previous
three issues reflect differences in regard to what the Christian
gospel is, and what Christian faith is all about. Sontag and Roth in
particular think there is no “good news” in my position, and that my
view makes faith in God “irrelevant.”
From their
perspective (partly for reasons explained above), the good news is
that God will save us, in the sense of bringing us into a state of
existence in which evil is totally overcome; and this is the content
of faith––what God will do in the future.
From my
perspective, central to the good news is the cry, “Emmanuel––God is
with us and for us!” The key question, in this evil-riddled world, in
which every movement, every structure, every dimension of existence is
ambiguous at best, is whether there is any reality which is
working unambiguously for good, to which we can give our allegiance
without reservation (with our whole heart, soul, and mind),
which can empower us to overcome the evil within ourselves and the
world around us, and the worship of which can integrate our lives and
give them purpose and direction.
The Christian
gospel, as I understand it, is that there is. God is with us here and
now, and is totally for us. Accordingly, from this perspective it is
Sontag and Roth who deny the good news by transposing the world’s
ambiguity into the very heart of God. Their God needs help as much or
more than we do (which makes their characterization of my God as
“pathetic” somewhat humorous). And if what we most need, in order to
prevent this whole planet from premature death, is empowerment to
co-operate with God’s purposes, then it is Sontag, Roth and Davis,
with their focus on what God will unilaterally do in the future, who
present a faith that is irrelevant.
(9) Most of the
other authors agree that my theodicy solves the problem of evil.
Their central reason for considering it inadequate is that it does so
by portraying a God who is not worshipful. This charge can mean that
this God either (i) does not evoke worship or (ii) should
not evoke worship. Unfortunately they do no distinguish these two
meanings. In any case, there are several reasons given as to why the
process doctrine of God is inadequate.
(A) One such
reason is that this God is “limited” or “finite.” These terms are
acceptable if they are properly understood; but often they are used
as synonymous with “imperfect.”
My God is
finite if this means that God is not the totality of reality, that
there are other actualities besides God. (The biblical God is
clearly “finite” in this sense.)
My God is
limited if this means that these other actualities have power of
their own that cannot be totally controlled by God. (The biblical
witness is ambiguous on this point.)
But my God is
not finite or limited if this means that God’s power is
imperfect in comparison with that of some other conceivable deity.
As I stated in the last section of my essay, I conceive God to be
perfect in power (as well as goodness), which means having the
greatest power it is possible for one being to have. Accordingly,
what is at issue is not a God whose power is imperfect in contrast
with a God whose power is perfect; rather, what we have is a
conflict between two conceptions of perfect power.
Insofar as the
arguments (referred to in point 4) as to why the idea of a divine
monopoly on power is an incoherent idea are convincing, an answer is
provided to the claim that my God is not worthy of worship because
“not powerful enough”––i.e., one cannot reasonably ask for more than
the possible.
Hick indicates
that his chief criticism of my theodicy would be directed toward its
idea of a limited God. The only suggestion he gives as to what his
criticism would be is that this idea is “metaphysically
unsatisfying.” He gives no hint in his critique as to the direction
his argument would take. However, in his Evil and the God of
Love (pp. 35-36) he provides this explanation: if God were not
“the creator of everything other than Himself,” God would not be “an
eternal self-existent Being.” Hence one would have to ask who
created God.
Unfortunately,
this argument itself is metaphysically unsatisfying, since a being
could well be eternal and self-existent without being creator of
everything else. If that is the worst challenge the process
doctrine of God must face, it is in good shape.
(B) Hick and
Davis almost seem to think that the mere fact that the traditional
doctrine of omnipotence, including creation ex nihilo, has
been the dominant view in Christian theology settles the issue as to
the Christian position. But, for example, a good case can be
made for the proposition that anti-Semitism has characterized “the
main Christian tradition”; this does not make anti-Semitism
Christian in a normative sense. So, more argument than an appeal to
the past majority opinion will be needed to support the idea that
Jews and Christians today should continue to accept divine
omnipotence.
(C) Sontag,
Davis and especially Roth say that the God of persuasion I portray
has not been effective enough in the world to inspire awe and
worship. Roth speaks of God’s “unpersuasive performance in the
world to date.” But when I contemplate the creation as a whole, I am
rather overwhelmed. When I view the heavens, and the beauty of our
own planet, and when I reflect upon the fact that creatures as
wondrously complex as ourselves were brought into being out of
minute trajectories of energy such as protons and electrons, I am
quite impressed. I do stand in awe before the directive
power that could bring about such results out of partially
self-determining entities, and a sense of holiness is
produced in me. So to some extent it may simply be that Roth is
more difficult to impress than I am.
However, to
some extent it seems that Roth takes an anthropocentric view of
things. In saying that there has been little progress, he speaks
only of moral progress; in speaking of resistance, he speaks
only of human recalcitrance. This suggests that Roth begins
grading God only after human beings have been produced. Perhaps if
he would extend his vision a few billion years further back, he
would see that we really have come along way. Further, even during
the extremely short period of human history, Roth admits that “many
human beings have rallied nobly to their perception of God’s call.”
I wonder why this alone does not impress him.
Davis finds the
God of process theology unworthy of worship because this God cannot
guarantee that the risk involved in creating the world “was worth
taking.” If the world were to end in a situation in which “all human
beings die, cursing God, after years of horrible physical and mental
suffering,” it would have been better, Davis maintains, that human
beings had never been created. In fact, like many who want to
emphasize the necessity for a dramatic eschatological act of God,
Davis says “the world is not worthwhile as it stands.”
So, even apart
from the grim scenario he sketches, if he were to be convinced that
no such eschatological act were going to occur, he would presumably
be one of those carrying a sign reading, “Doom, doom, the world is
not going to end.” Of course, if he seriously finds his own
present life intrinsically unworthwhile (it would be presumptuous of
him to say that his own is worthwhile but that of the majority of
humanity is not), I can only respect his feelings while witnessing
that I do not find my own and that of those I know well to be so.
Nor can I judge
that, for the majority of humanity, it would have been better that
they had not lived, even if there is to be no future existence for
them. Furthermore, I have distinguished between the kind of power
needed to change the very structure of existence, which I think God
does not have, and the power needed to renew our lives beyond bodily
death, which I think God does have.
So, even if one
did think that human life were not intrinsically worthwhile, so that
a future life for humans would be necessary to justify God’s
creation of us, it does not follow that God must be omnipotent in
the traditional sense to be justified in bringing forth human life.
One of the
stranger complaints from Sontag and Roth is that, given the enormity
of evil in the world, a deity that is doing its best is not worthy of
worship. The implication is that a deity that is not doing its
best is worthy of worship.
For example, in
reference to Auschwitz, Roth mocks my God with the statement that “the
best that God could possibly do was to permit 10,000 Jews a day to go
up in smoke.” Roth prefers a God who had the power to prevent this
Holocaust but did not do it! This illustrates how much people can
differ in what they consider worthy of worship. For Roth, it is
clearly brute power that evokes worship. The question: is this
what should evoke worship?
To refer back to
the point about revelation: is this kind of power worship consistent
with the Christian claim that divinity is decisively revealed in
Jesus? Roth finds my God too small to evoke worship; I find his too
gross.
POSTSCRIPT: In
writing this response, it became obvious that many of the criticisms
to which I was called to reply were made in triplicate: from Davis,
Roth, and Sontag. They have common objections to process theology.
This is probably not coincidental: Roth and Sontag have written books
together, and Roth and Davis have adjoining offices. Also, all three
did their doctoral work in philosophy and presently teach in
philosophy departments, whereas my graduate work was more concentrated
in biblical studies, history of Christian thought, history or
religions, and modern theology. This probably has something to do
with our different evaluations of the normative status of
prepositional formulations of Christian faith coming from the early
centuries of Christianity.
It also became
more obvious than it previously was to me how much Hick and I have in
common. We both see God as relying solely upon persuasion to effect
our salvation––we do not expect God one of these days to give up on
this method and to resort to coercive measures. We both place our
faith in the attractiveness of the divine, agreeing with Whitehead
that “the power of God is the worship He inspires."[1]
The crucial difference between us is that Hick continues to insist
that God has that other kind of power, i.e., the coercive kind. And
this is the idea that creates all of the objectionable aspects in his
theodicy. Since Hick, unlike Roth, Sontag, and Davis, believes that
God will never use this coercive power, I wonder what value is
derived from continuing to maintain that God has it.
_________________________
[1] Alfred North
Whitehead, Science and the Modern World (New York:
Macmillan Co. 1953), p. 192.