From Structure,
Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of Henry M. Sheffer, ed. Paul
Henle, Horace M. Kallen, and Susanne K. Langer (New York: Liberal Arts
Press, 1951), 171-182; reprinted as the Appendix to Susanne K. Langer,
Problems of Art (New York: Scribner’s, 1957), 163-180.
Abstraction in Science
and Abstraction in Art
Susanne K. Langer
All genuine art is
abstract. The schematized shapes usually called “abstractions” in
painting and sculpture present a very striking technical device for
achieving artistic abstraction, but the result is neither more nor less
abstract than any successful work in the “great tradition,” or for that
matter in Egyptian, Peruvian, or Chinese art—that is, in any tradition
whatever.
Yet the abstractness of a
work of art seems to be something quite different from that of science,
mathematics, or logic. This difference lies not in the meaning of
“abstraction,” as offhand one might suppose; we are not dealing with a
mere ambiguity. Both in art and in logic (which carries scientific
abstraction to its highest development), “abstraction” is the recognition
of a relational structure, or form, apart from the specific thing
(or event, fact, image, etc.) in which it is exemplified. The difference
lies in the way the recognition is achieved in art and science,
respectively; for abstraction is normally performed for some intellectual
purpose, and its purpose differs radically from the one context to the
other. The two characteristic processes of abstracting a form from its
concrete embodiment or exemplification go back, therefore, as far as the
fundamental distinction between art and science itself; and that is along
way back.
There seem, indeed, to be
two meanings of the word “form” involved in the two fields, respectively.
A logician, mathematician, or careful epistemologist may question what
sense it makes to call anything ”form” except the logical form of
discourse, the structure of propositions expressed either in ordinary
language or in the refined symbolism of the rational sciences. Wherever
terms exist at all for him they can be named; the relations among them can
be named (although their “names” may be indirect, may be parentheses or
even mere positions in a line of print); and no matter how complex their
combinations may be, those terms and relations are wholly expressible in
verbal or algorithmic propositions. Why, then, call anything “form” that
is not capable of such presentation?
Yet artists do speak of
“form” and know what they mean; and, moreover, their meaning is closer
than that of the logicians to what the word originally meant, namely,
“visible and tangible shape.” The artists, therefore, may ask in their
turn how one can speak of the “form” of something invisible and
intangible—for instance, the series of natural numbers, or an elaborate
mathematical expression equal to zero. Their sense of the word has
undergone refinements, too; in plastic art, it does not mean that at all.
The forms achieved by prose fiction are neither shapes nor logical
systems; for although literary works contain propositions, literary form
is not the systematic unity of a complex literal statement. The artistic
form is a perceptual unity of something seen, heard, or imagine—that is,
the configuration, or Gestalt, of an experience. One may say that
to call such an immediately perceived Gestalt “form” is merely a
metaphor; but it would be exactly as reasonable to say that the use of the
word for syntactical structure is metaphorical, derived from geometry, and
carried over into algebra, logic, and even grammar.
If one cannot tell which
of the two meanings is literal and which is figurative, it is fairly safe
to assume that both make use of a single underlying principle which is
exemplified in two different modes. The basic principle of “form”
determines that close relation between apperceptive unity and logical
distinctions which was known to the ancients as “unity in diversity”; But
they might just as well have called it “diversity in unity”; for it is
sometimes thought to relate many individually conceived things or
properties each to each, directly or indirectly, producing a whole, and
sometimes to distinguish many elements from one another where an
all-inclusive unit is the first assumption. The preposition “in” is an
unfortunate word to designate the construction of a coherent system out of
given factors; but when it serves also to designate the
articulation of structural elements of a given whole, it is as bad a
hyperbole for the expression of relational concepts as ever bedeviled
classical philosophy.
Yet the two
ideas—constructed unity and organic differentiation of an original
whole—both involve the more general concept of relative distinctness.
They are specifications of this concept that arise from epistemological
sources, from the nature of logical intuition and the nature of the
symbols whereby we elicit and promote it. Now the object of logical
intuition is form; and although there are two ways of developing
our perception of this object, and consequently two sets of associations
with the word “form,” the use of it is equally and similarly justified in
both contexts.
There are certain
relational factors in experience which are either intuitively recognized
or not at all, for example, distinctness, similarity, congruence,
relevance. These are formal characteristics which are protological in
that they “must be seen to be appreciated.” Once cannot take them on
faith. The recognition of them is what I mean by “logical intuition.”
All discourse is a device for concatenating intuitions, getting from one
to another, and building up the greater intuitive apperception of a total
Gestalt, or ideal whole.
Artistic intuition is a
similar protological experience, but its normal progress is different. It
begins with the perception of a total Gestalt and proceeds to
distinctions of ideal elements within it. Therefore its symbolism is a
physical or imaginal whole whereof the details are articulated, rather
than a vocabulary of symbols that may be combined to present a coherent
structure. That is why artistic form is properly called “organic” and
discursive form “systematic,” and also why discursive symbolism is
appropriate to science and artistic symbolism to the conception and
expression of vital experience, or what is commonly termed “the life of
feeling.”
As art and discursive
reason differ in their starting points of logical intuition, so they
differ in all their intellectual processes. This makes the problem of
abstraction appear entirely different in the two domains. Yet artists and
logicians are equally concerned with abstraction, or the recognition of
pure form, which is necessary to any understanding of relationships; and
they perform it with equal spontaneity and carry it, perhaps, to equally
great lengths of skillful manipulation.
There is a widespread
belief—sometimes regarded as a very truism—that abstract thought is
essentially artificial and difficult, and that all untutored or “natural”
thought is bound to concrete experiences, in fact to physical things. But
if abstraction were really unnatural, no one could have invented it. If
the untutored mind could not perform it, how did we ever learn it? We can
develop by training only what is incipiently given by nature. Somewhere
in man’s primitive repertoire there must have been a spontaneous
intellectual practice from which the cultivated variety of abstract
thought took its rise.[1]
This instinctive mental
activity is the process of symbol-making, of which the most amazing result
is language. All symbolization rests on a recognition of congruent forms,
from the simple one-to-one correspondence of name and thing that is the
dream of speech reformers[2]
to the most sophisticated projection of thought into conventional systems
of notation. The logic of symbolic expression is an old story though not
completely told even yet; it is still gaining precision in works like C.
I. Lewis’ Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. But its main
outlines are familiar enough to need no restatement here. The interesting
thing in the present context is that the growth of language takes place at
all times in several dimensions, and each of these entails a primitive and
spontaneous form of abstractive thinking. The appreciation of pure
conceptual forms as such is indeed a late and difficult attainment of
civilized thought, but the abstraction of formal elements for other
intellectual purposes is a natural and even an irrepressible human
activity. It permeates all thought and imagination—reason, free
association, play, delirium, and dream. And although I am convinced that
some abstractions cannot be made verbally at all, but can be made by the
nondiscursive forms we call “works of art,”[3]
yet the basic abstractive processes are all exemplified in language at
various stages of its ever-productive career. Some transcend its
limitations soon, and other late; some leave it and become completely
articulate only in the various media of art; some remain essentially
linguistic and simply transform and develop language in their natural
advance, giving it more and more of what we call “literal meaning,” more
and more precise grammar, and finally the algorithmic extensions that
belong rather to written language than to speech.
We have no record of any
really archaic tongue; the origins of all known languages lie beyond the
reaches of history. But as far back as we can go, language has two
essential functions, which may be called, somewhat broadly, “connotation”
and “denotation” (the exact distinctions made by Professor Lewis[4]
are indeed relevant here), but I resort to the less precise, traditional
terms because, in the small compass of this essay, the roughest
characterization that will serve the purpose is the most economical.)
Connotation belongs to all symbols; it is the symbolic function that
corresponds to the psychological act of conception. Denotation accrues to
symbols in practical use, for the applicability of concepts to “reality”
is, after all, their constant pragmatic measure. Both conception and
denotation through language are natural activities, instinctive, popular,
and therefore freely improvisational and elaborative; and both involve a
constant practice of abstraction from the pure experience of this,
here-and-now.
The principles of
abstraction that govern the making of symbolic expressions vary, however,
with the purposes (conscious or unconscious) to which those expressions
are to be put. One outstanding purpose is, certainly, to attain
generality in thought. The tremendous practical value of language
lies largely in its power of generalization, whereby the naming of any
object immediately establishes the calls of such objects. This is
a very rudimentary abstractive function inherent in language as such, as
Ribot observed more than fifty years ago,[5]
and as Cassirer has demonstrated in
The Philosophy of
Symbolic Forms.[6]
The earliest classconcepts, therefore, are
directly linked with the assignment of names to objects.
The modern empiricists,
notably Locke, took it for granted that the “simple qualities”—such as
colors, tones, smells and tastes, pressures—were the items most directly
presented to the mind through primitive, unguided sense experience, and
therefore remembered—that is, conceived—even as meaningless “data.” Oddly
enough, the development of language, which mirrors the history of those
twin functions, perception and conception, gives a different view of
elementary qualities. Judging by early nomenclature, we find that colors,
for instance, were not always distinguished by their actual spectrum
values—that is, as “red,” “blue,” “yellow,” and so forth—but primarily as
warm or cold, clear or dull. Walde’s comparative etymological dictionary[7]
renders the meaning of the IndoEuropean root ĝhel as “glänzen,
schimmern, gelb, grün, grau oder blau.” The names for definite
pigments were late established, and often changed their signification
completely from one hue to another. Thus the current word “blue,” German
blau, derives from blavus, a Middle Latin form of flavus,
meaning, not “blue,” but “yellow.”[8]
Black is descended from bhleg, and cognate with blanc,
blank, Swedish black, Norwegian blakk, meaning “white.”
The oldest sense is probably preserved in “bleak.” But what is even more
surprising is that the connotation of an adjective often shifts entirely
from one sensory field to another. The German word hell, now
applied literally only to light and color—that is, to visual
impressions—and sometimes used metaphorically of tones, seems originally
to have referred to sounds first and foremost, and to have come into use
for visual effects only around the time of Martin Luther. In fact, when
Luther employs it to describe light, he always says “hell licht,” “am
hellen lichten Tag,” and the old meaning is still preserved in the
idiom “ein heller Haufe,” which refers not to a bright throng but a
noisy one.
Yet the apparently
capricious changes of meaning, often from the original quality to its very
opposite, follow a perfectly obvious principle: a word designates any
quality that can symbolize a certain feeling. This seems to be the law of
that metaphorical extension whereby whole groups of words arise out of one
phonetic “root,” all embodying this root in their sound and deriving their
meaning from its archaic sense, which Max Müller aptly called the “root
metaphor.” The original reference of adjectives especially appears to
have been primarily to feeling tones, and hence, quite freely and
naturally, to any sense-qualities that helped the conception of them.
Therefore extreme opposites of sensation were often designated by the same
word: white and black, hot and cold,[9]
high and deep (Latin altus). Both extremes of a sensation
symbolize the same intensity of feeling. The true opposite of their value
is a low-keyed sensation—dim, gray; lukewarm; flat, shallow. Primitive
thought is fairly indifferent to the particular order of sensation from
which the qualitative symbol is taken, so long as it conveys the
subjective value of the experience to be recorded.
But language is not only
an intellectual tool whereby concepts are formed; it is also a common
currency for the exchange of them; and this public interest puts a premium
on objective reference and develops the function of denotation. The
attachment of verbal labels to things is the major purpose of words
in social use. Every device that facilitates naming is naturally accepted
and exploited; and perhaps the greatest of such devices is generalization,
the treatment of every actually given thing as a representative of its
kind—that is, of every “this” as a “such-as-this.” The establishment
of kinds, or classes of things, requires some easily recognizable mark of
membership in otherwise diverse objects, and this interest was probably
what led people from the conception of qualities through feeling-tones to
the more precise observation of publicly comparable features—the hues,
shapes, sizes, noises, temperatures, and the rest that modern languages
honor with adjectives: blue, round, big, loud, cold, and so forth. With
this fixation of characters, the old contrast between “extreme” and
“middling” would be broken down by the discovery that there are two
different “extremes”; and their close association, amounting even to
fusion in a single root-metaphor, would lead to a new, powerful,
abstracted notion—the notion of a dimension, a range or gamut of
experiences. Then the qualities within one dimension could be
distinguished, named, comparatively treated; the principles of empirical
analysis supervene over the earlier recognition of feeling-tones; and
language become the mighty instrument of discursive thought in which
Aristotle found the laws of logic reflected.
The “simple qualities” of
empiricism, the “data” that are obviously distinct for us, are so by
virtue of language; and their classification in sensory orders—such as
hues, sounds, tastes, and so on—is already a long step toward science.
This step is effected by the spontaneous processes of symbolic
transformation that give rise to language in the first place: metaphor,
which always involves a basic recognition of the common form that
justifies the substitution of one image for another; and the principle of
pars pro toto, exemplifying the class-concept involved. But these
primitive insights into formal conditions do not constitute “abstraction”
in a strict sense. They are abstractive processes implicit in
symbol-making and symbol-using, rather than a recognition of abstracted
elements as such. Genuine abstraction is a relatively late achievement,
born of reflection on the works of art and science, and fully understood
only by means of the latter. But once we attain the concept of abstract
form, or pure structure apart from the things in which it is exemplified,
we find that both art and science constantly tend toward the maximum
revelation of abstract elements, and both for the same purpose—namely, to
create more and more powerful symbols—but by different procedures, born of
their different intuitive starting points.
The driving principle of
science is generalization. Its subject matter is really something
perfectly concrete—namely, the physical world; its aim is to make
statements of utmost generality about the world. And generalization, as
we have just seen, arises from the denotative character of language, from
the fact that a named thing is at once a focus of “reality”—that is, a
fixed entity—and a symbol for its kind; since a name is always a class
label as well as a handle for its specific object. (Even supposedly
individual, or proper, names tend to serve in this double capacity: “A
Daniel come to judgment!) The principle of classification, inherent
in language, begets the logic of quantified statement that underlies the
development of scientific thought. There was good reason why a logic
guided by scientific aims should have been developed in extension rather
than intension; the extension of a term is the range of its denotation,
and denotation is its link with the world, the object of science.
Bertrand Russell, in one of his brilliant early essays, called this
extensionalism “the Principle of Abstraction . . . which might equally
well be called the principle that dispenses with abstraction.”[10]
Actually, it does not dispense with them at all, but moves over them
without explicit recognition, because its aim is to put all abstracted
forms to further use—much as we do in making our unconscious abstractions
by the common-sense use of language—and to make general statements about
reality—that is, assert general facts of nature.
It was only with the
development of mathematics that abstract logical forms became so apparent
and, in their appearance, so interesting that some logicians turned their
attention to the study of form as such and undertook the
abstraction of relational patterns from any and every concrete
exemplification. Russell, despite his proposal to dispense with
abstractions, was one of the first advocates of that new logic and
(together with Whitehead) one of its great promoters; for, oddly enough,
systematic generalization—the principle that was to obviate the need of
abstraction—furnished exactly the technique whereby structures were
brought to light, symbolically expressed and recognized as pure abstract
forms. Russell’s leanings toward physical science are so strong that
perhaps he does not see the entire potential range of philosophical
studies built on the study of relational logic. Whitehead came nearer to
it; Peirce and Royce saw it;[11]
but the actual development of systematic abstraction to the point where it
can be an eyeopener to philosophers has been the special task of the man
to whom these essays are dedicated
[Henry M. Sheffer].
In natural science, generalization is all we require, and mathematics is
valued for its power of general statement and complex manipulations
without any loss of generality. But in pure mathematics the element of
logical form is so commandingly evident that mathematical studies
naturally lead to a theory of structure as such and to a systematic study
of abstraction. That study is logic, and its technique is progressive
generalization. The use of generalization to make abstract structure
apparent was more or less accidental until Sheffer saw its possibilities
and built a pure logic of forms upon it. This work gave logic a different
aim, not only from the old traditional “art and science of inference,” but
even from the modern development of truth-value systems; for instead of
being essentially a scientific tool, logic thus becomes an extension of
human interest beyond the generalized empirical thought of science, to the
domain of abstract form, where the very principles of symbolism,
conception, and expression lie open to inquiry and technical
demonstration.
If we now turn to the
domain of the arts, it seems as though nothing comparable to logical
abstractness could be found there at all, but everything were immediate,
unintellectual, and concrete. Yet a little conversance with any art
quickly reveals its abstract character. A work of art is a symbol; and
the artist’s task is, from beginning to end, the making of the symbol.
And symbol-making requires abstraction, the more so where the symbolic
function is not conventionally assigned, but the presented form is
significant simply by virtue of its articulate character. The meanings of
a work of art have to be imaginatively grasped through the forms it
presents to the sense or senses to which it is addressed; and, to do this,
the work must make a forceful abstraction of “significant form” from the
concrete stuff that is its medium.
But the abstractive
process of art is entirely different from that of science, mathematics,
and logic; just as the forms abstracted in art are not those of rational
discourse, which serve us to symbolize public “fact,” but complex forms
capable of symbolizing the dynamics of subjective experience, the pattern
of vitality, sentience, feeling, and emotion. Such forms cannot be
revealed by means of progressive generalization; this makes the whole
development of art and all its techniques radically different from those
of discursive thought. Although art and science spring from the same
root, namely, the impulse to symbolic expression—of which the richest,
strongest and undoubtedly oldest manifestation is language—they separate
practically from the beginning.[12]
A work of art is and
remains specific. It is “this,” and not “this kind”; unique instead of
exemplary. A physical copy of it belongs to the class of its copies, but
the original is not itself a member of this class to which it furnishes
the class concept. We may, of course, classify it in numberless ways, for
example, according to its theme, from which it may take its name—“Madonna
and Child,” “Last Supper,” and so on. And as many artists as wish may use
the same theme, or one artist may use it many times; there may be many
“Raphael Madonnas” and many “Last Suppers” in the Louvre. But such
class-membership has nothing to do with the artistic importance of a work
(the classification of a scientific object, on the other hand, always
affects its scientific importance).
The artist’s problem,
then, is to treat a specific object abstractly; to make it clearly an
instance of a form, without resorting to a class of similar objects from
which the form underlying their similarity could be abstracted by the
logical method of progressive generalization. The first step is usually
to make the object unimportant from any other standpoint than that
of appearance. Illusion, fiction, all elements of unreality in art serve
this purpose. The work has to be uncoupled from all realistic connections
and its appearance made self-sufficient in such a way that one’s interest
does not tend to go beyond it. At the same time, this purely apparent
entity is simplified so that the ea, eye, or (in the case of literary art)
the constructive imagination can take in the whole pattern all the time,
and every detail be seen in a fundamental, unfailing context—seen
related, not seen then rationally related. Whether there is much
detail or little, what there is must seem an articulation of the total
semblance. In the case of a piece that is not physically perceivable at
one time, as for instance a novel, a long drama or opera, or a series of
frescoes constituting a single work, the proportion of the whole has to be
established at all times by implication, which is a special and technical
problem. In any event, the perception of a work of art as “significant
form”—significant of the nature of human feeling—always proceeds from the
total form to its subordinate features.
This manner of
perception, which the work is designed to elicit, causes it to appear
organic; for the evolution of detail out of an indivisible,
self-sufficient whole is characteristic of organisms and is the material
counterpart of their function, life. And so the work of art seems to have
organic structure and rhythms of life, though it is patently not a real
organism but a lifeless subject. If the semblance is forcible enough—that
is, if the artist is successful—the impression of living form becomes
commanding and the physical status of the piece insignificant. The form
of organic process which characterizes all vital function has been
abstracted, and the abstraction made directly from one specific
phenomenon, without the aid of several examples from which a general
pattern emerges that may then be symbolically rendered. In art, the one
instance is intelligibly constructed and is given the character of a
symbol by suppression of its actual constitution as painted cloth,
vibrating air, or (somewhat less simply) a string of the conventional
counters called “words,” whose relative values are recorded in the
dictionary. When its proper material status is cancelled by the illusion
of organic structure, its phenomenal character becomes paramount; the
specific object is made to reveal its logical form.
Yet it does not present
an abstracted concept for our contemplation; the abstractive process is
only an incident in the whole function of a work of art, which is to
symbolize subjective experience—that is, to formulate and convey ideas of
sentience and emotion. The abstracted form of organic relations and vital
rhythms is only an ingredient in the total expression of feeling, and
remains implicit in that greater process. But it is the framework; and,
once it is established, the whole realm of sense-perception furnishes
symbolic material. Here the inherent emotive significance of sense-data
comes into play. The natural relationship between sensory qualities and
feelings, which governs the extension of language by the development of
“root-metaphors,” also determines the function of sensuous materials in
art. Surfaces, colors, textures and lights and shadows, tones of every
pitch and quality, vowels and consonants, swift or heavy motions—all
things that exhibit definite qualities—are potential symbols of feeling,
and out of these the illusion of organic structure is made. That is why
art is essentially qualitative and at the same time abstract. But the
sensuous elements, often spoken of as the “sense-content” of a work, are
not content at all but pure symbol; and the whole phenomenon is an
expanded metaphor of feeling, invented and recognized by the same
intuition that makes language grow from the “root-metaphors” of
fundamentally emotive significance.
Artistic abstraction,
being incidental to a symbolic process that aims at the expression and
knowledge of something quite concrete—the facts of human feeling, which
are just as concrete as physical occurrences—does not furnish elements of
genuine abstract thought. The abstractive processes in art would probably
always remain unconscious if we did not know from discursive logic what
abstraction is. They are intuitive, and often most successful and
complete in primitive art. It is through science that we recognize the
existence of pure form, for here it is slowly achieved by conscious method
and finally becomes an end in itself for the entirely unempirical
discipline of logic. That is probably why so many people stoutly maintain
that art is concrete and science abstract. What they should properly
say—and perhaps really mean—is that science is general and art specific.
For science moves from general denotation to precise abstraction; art,
from precise abstraction to vital connotation, without the aid of
generality.
[1]
This fact was noted by T. Ribot in an article, “Abstraction Prior to
Speech,” in The Open Court (1899), Vol. XIII, pp. 14-20.
[2]
Cf. Bertrand Russell’s Philosophy (New York, 1927), Ch. IV; and
his later and more elaborate Inquiry into Meaning and Truth
(New York, 1940), especially the first four chapters; also G. B.
Shaw’s Preface to R. A. Wilson’s The Miraculous Birth of Language
(New York, 1948).
[3]
Here I regret to disagree radically with Professor
Lewis, who says: “It is doubtful that there are, or could be, meanings
which it is intrinsically impossible for words to express.”—An
Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (La Salle, Ill., 1946), p. 73.
[5] In the essay previously
alluded to.
[6] See especially Vol. I, Chs.
IV and V.
[7] Walde, Vergleichendes
Wörterbuch der indoger-manischen
Sprachen (Leipzig, 1926).
[9] Walde gives the meanings
of the root kel as: “(1)
frieren, kalt. (2) warm.”
[10] Our Knowledge of the
External World, 2nd ed.
(New York, 1929), p. 44
[11] C. S. Peirce, “The
Architecture of Ideas,” in
Chance, Love and Logic; Josiah Royce, “The Principles of
Logic,” especially Sec. III, in Encyclopedia of the Philosophical
Sciences, edited by Windelband and Ruge, Eng. Transl. (1913).
[12] For a full discussion of
this point, see E. Cassirer,
The
Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, especially Vol. I, ch. I.