Text taken from
here. Date not given; no
reference note cite cites anything published after 1989. Also on
this site is Lee's
“Does God Have Emotions?”
Lee
is the Director of the
Institute of Bioethics at Franciscan
University of Steubenville, where he is also Professor of Bioethics.
See
his site.
Evidentialism, Plantinga, and Faith and Reason
Patrick Lee
A. The False Presupposition of the Evidentialist Objection
The evidentialist objection presupposes several claims about what
is needed for a belief to be a pro-per act. Of course the evidentialist
objector claims that religious belief is not epistemically
warranted. While Plantinga and many others deny this claim, I have
argued that we should grant it to the eviden-tialist, in this sense,
that the absolute certainty of Christian belief is not epistemically
warranted. But evidentialism also presupposes that one ought not to
accept a belief that is not epistemically warranted, in other words,
that to accept a belief that is not epis-temically warranted is not
morally justified. So the heart of the evidentialist argument
concerns moral justification.
The evidentialist norm for believing has been ex-pressed in various
ways: It is wrong to believe any-thing upon insufficient evidence. Or:
One ought to proportion one’s belief in a proposition to the degree of
evidence which one has to support that propo-sition. Or: One ought not
to go beyond the evidence in one’s acts of believing. (I think the word
“evidence” here means roughly what I used it to mean above, namely,
something of which one is aware which seems to indicate that a
proposition is true or likely to be true, and evidence in this sense
need not be propositional.) These ways of expres-sing it come down to
the same thing, for what is meant is that evidence alone should be
deter-minative of what and how one believes. Nothing else should affect
one’s acts of believing except the relationship between the proposition
believed and the evidence one knows that supports it.
However, what evidence is there for this Sola Evidentia
position? After all, an act of believing is a moral act, and moral acts
typically relate to several human goods rather than just one.
Why should this human act be motivated or influenced by only one human
good—possession of truth—while there seems nothing morally wrong with
other human acts being simultaneously motivated and influenced by
several human goods?
An example frequently discussed is a mountain climber who has
climbed to a dangerous spot from which he can escape only by jumping
across a wide chasm. The evidence just on its own indicates that it is
only probable that he will make the jump. (I’ll discuss the type of
case where the available evidence goes against one’s belief in a
moment.) But if he believes with certainty he will make the jump then
his chances are greatly increased. It does not seem immoral for him to
induce in himself, or to try to induce in himself, the belief that he
will make the jump. Such an act does not seem to involve a disrespect
or a disregard for the basic good of possession of truth. The type of
act involved here is: accepting a proposition with certainty (partly)
for the sake of a good which the belief of that proposition, together
with its truth, if it turns out to be true, will help or enable one to
realize.
Another example, more closely analogous to religious belief, is
accepting a marriage proposal. Suppose George proposes marriage to
Hilda. He tells Hilda that he loves her, proposes that they set up
together a common life, and tells her of things he has done for her—that
he has, for example, bought them a house for the home they will make if
she says yes. So, Hilda seems to have a choice. She can accept what
George says as true and sincere and accept the proposal, or not. She
cannot, obviously, prove that his proposal is sincere. Let us
suppose George is not a villainous type, that there are signs that he is
a good and honest person; in other words, one would likely say his claim
is “credible,” worthy to be believed. Well, if Hilda decides to accept,
it is likely that she will have more certainty in George than the
evidence just by itself about him would epistemically warrant. But is
there anything morally improper about such belief or faith?
Religious belief is analogous to acceptance of a marriage
proposal. Religious belief in the full sense, according to Christians,
is believing what God has communicated through the words and deeds of
prophets and of Jesus. Revelation is not merely impersonal information
or a set of speculative truths. It is a personal communication. It
reveals, in part, who God is, his invitation and commitment to personal
communion, and many of the things he has done for us.1 To
be sure, there is evidence, or signs of credibility—signs indicating
that indeed it is God who is speaking here. Yet the Christian’s act of
acceptance, and the certainty of that act, are motivated not just by
that evidence or “signs”, but also by the desire for the personal
communion offered.2 Is such an act morally justified?
Moral justification primarily concerns basic human goods,
that is, aspects of human flourishing. In acts of believing the primary
good involved—although I will argue not the only good—is possession of
truth, or a grasp upon reality. I believe the basic moral norm can be
expressed in this way: In all of one’s choices and acts of willing, one
ought to respect all basic human goods, including such goods as, human
life, aesthetic experience, friendship and society, and so on.
This position on morality is derived from Thomas Aquinas’s natural
law theory, and has recently been articulated and developed by Germain
Grisez, Joseph Boyle and John Finnis.3 I can briefly clarify
this view by contrasting it with consequentialism or utilitari-anism.
Consequentialism is correct in this sense that moral good is closely
linked with the human good or the fulfillment of the whole person. But
conse-quentialism is incorrect in basing morality on the production of
goods or benefits rather than directly on how the will is related to
human goods. The moral norm is not that we should maximize human goods,
which would justify suppressing a particular human good for the sake of
the consequences “in the long run.” I do not think it morally right to
choose to destroy or suppress a human good for the sake of (what one
thinks will be) the balance of human goods in general. Morality does
depends how one’s action is related to human goods, but the important
relation is this: one’s choice or will should be directed to hu-man
goods, and should remain open to all of them. From this basic principle
several more specific moral norms follow. For example, one ought not to
be deterred from pursuing human goods by mere lethargy or laziness; one
ought not to prefer the mere experience or the mere appearance of a good
to its reality; and one ought not to choose to destroy, damage, or
impede one good for the sake of another. One is not required to pursue
all of the basic human goods all of the time, but one is (morally)
required to respect them at all times. Perhaps the central question
concerning the ethics of belief, then, is: what does respect for the
good of possession of truth require?
First, respect for this good seems to require that we pursue it at
least sometimes. I would be less than honest if I said I had a love for
truth but never made any effort to pursue it.
Secondly, I think respect for this good also re-quires that we
never choose precisely against it, for example, by suppressing truth for
the sake of an ulterior end. And, thirdly, respect for the good of
possession of truth requires that in any of our actions which could
affect this good (in ourselves and in others), we at least take it into
account, that is, that we not disregard this good. An example of
disre-garding the good of possession of truth is: believing in
astrology because it makes me feel good, or even, believing in God (or
trying to induce belief in God in someone else) solely because one
thinks such belief makes people morally better.
Yet believing for the sake of a good other than truth need not
include any failure to pursue truth, any suppression of truth, or
disrespect for the good of possession of truth. An action that directly
bears on one good may be chosen to promote another good without
slighting the good the action most directly bears on.4
Therefore, believing for the sake of a good other than truth need not be
immoral.
In sum: (1) religious belief can be motivated by a hope for the
realization of a basic human good; (2) religious belief need not include
a negative attitude toward or a disregard for any other instance of a
human good. From these points it follows that reli-gious belief could
be, in the appropriate conditions, a morally good act. More formally:
Every act which does not negate or disregard a basic human good is a
morally good act.
Some acts of religious belief do not negate or disregard a basic
human good.
Therefore, some acts of religious belief are morally good acts.5
Someone might object that my account leads to approving all kinds
of irrational acts. Is not the person who believes in astrology because
it makes him feel good doing just what I have described, believing for
the sake of a good other than truth? Is not irrationality precisely
allowing concerns other than that for truth to take over?
In reply, first, saying that believing for the sake of a good other
than truth need not involve disrespect for truth does not mean that
every believing for the sake of a good other than truth is
respectful of truth and morally right. If we reject the evidentialist
restriction on how concern for other goods can influence one’s actions
in relation to truth, it does not follow that we are left no
restrictions at all on such influence. Secondly, I have said that
religious belief is analogous to an act of accepting a proposition for
the sake of a good which the belief, together with the truth of the
proposition, will help one realize. If the belief by itself were
sufficient to bring about the good one is seeking by believing then it
seems that the action would be immoral. Believing in astrology because
it makes one feel good, or even, believing in God solely because such a
belief makes one more moral, are examples of doing that. If the belief
by itself—independently of the belief’s truth—were sufficient to bring
about the good one hoped for, then one’s choice to believe (or choice
to do what leads to believing) would include implicitly a willingness or
consent to believe falsely. This would violate the basic good of
possession of truth. But in the type of act we are discussing there
need be no implicit consent to believe falsely. That is, no doubt there
are acts of religious belief that do involve a disregard for truth, or
insufficient regard for truth, but it is not necessary that every act of
religious belief do so.
Thirdly, I believe some degree of evidence is needed in
order for the act of belief to be a morally responsible act. I am not
sure we can give an explicit criterion for determining how much evidence
is needed. But I think some degree of evidence is required. If,
for example, the man who proposed marriage to Hilda were known to be a
J. R. Ewing type, then it would probably be unreasonable for her to
accept his proposal as sincere. The less evidence there is, then I
think the more the other factors in the situation must contribute to
justifying (morally) a risk with respect to the good of possession of
truth.
Fourthly, we must remember that respect for the good of truth
requires at all times openness to evidence that may go to support a view
opposite the belief. The will to bring it about that I believe p
does not excuse suppressing evidence for not‑p. For one thing,
what looks like evidence for not‑p may turn out to be evidence
for some other proposition, or it may cause us to understand more fully
what it is we are understanding in the proposition p. It is well
to remember here that our goal is not simply to believe true
propositions and refrain from believing false ones, but to have a
cognitive grasp upon the real, or to have as accurate and complete a
picture of what the real is as we can. The evidence for not‑p
may eventually serve to reveal important aspects of the real other than
what it first seems to point to. Because of that fact, and also because
the evidence itself is part of our possession of truth, it is never
morally permissible directly to suppress evidence.
What about believing when the available evidence, or rather the
balance of the available evidence, goes the other way? I do not think
this is necessarily im-proper either. One reason why is that the
available evidence may be misleading, and I do not see that taking a
second‑order view, so to speak, and holding that the available evidence
must be misleading is necessarily disrespectful of truth. In other
words, it is difficult to arrive at many universal rules implied by the
respect due the good of possession of truth (but there is at least one
exceptionless norm here—the duty not to suppress truth).
But a further point can be added. There are three ways the
evidence and the situation could stack up. (1) The evidence and
situation might be such that one ought not to believe. (2) It might be
such that it is permissible for one to believe, but also permissible for
one not to believe. And (3), as I shall argue in more detail in
a moment, the evidence and the situation might be such that one
positively ought to believe. I think that the more the evidence points
in the opposite direction, the less likely it is going to be that I
positively ought to believe. In other words, in a situation
where the available evidence does point one way, it may be
permissible to believe the opposite, but it is not likely that one
would be obliged to do so.
In any case, I do not think God has left us in a situation where
the available evidence does point in the direction opposite religious
belief. In fact there are signs of credibility for God’s
revelation. Of course, what evidence is available to reasonably
intelligent and conscientious inquirers may not be readily available to
my next door neighbor, partly because I may be too indifferent to speak
to him or her about my belief and partly because my life may fail to
manifest any of the splendor of the Christian Faith. As Christians we
have a responsibility to help make the Faith credible. Faith, as well
as redemption and sanctification, are communal.
My argument so far has been deductive. I have appealed to ethical
principles to show that concern for a good other than truth can morally
justify certainty. However, a confirming argument can be added: It
seems that friendship, any friendship, is a good that can be realized
only by going beyond the evidence. One does not have to be a
dualist to see that crucial aspects of the person, such as a person’s
commitments, are not directly seen or experienced by other persons. And
yet it is especially with these aspects of the person that one unites
oneself in a friendship. In a friendship each friend not only cares for
the other for the other’s sake, but also in some way chooses, freely
accepts, the friendship, i.e., the relationship, itself. This could not
be so unless each friend accepted the other’s (explicit or implicit)
claim to be a friend, the other’s claim to care for that friend. But
this caring, this resolve to be a friend, is an aspect of the other
person that cannot be directly experienced or proved to exist. In other
words, reaching out to central aspects of another self, in friendship,
requires one to go beyond the evidence, for the simple reason that
central aspects of the self are beyond the evidence. One must be
willing to accept, without proof, that the other is sincere in his or
her offer or claim of friendship.
If this is true, then belief is not a necessary means toward
friendship, but a part of it. Friendship is im-possible without belief,
without accepting something upon insufficient evidence, without an
assent (accep-tance of a proposition as true) not proportioned to the
evidence. Now, friendship is a morally good thing. Therefore belief,
going beyond the evidence, which is part of it, must also be morally
permissible. Or, to state the argument differently, if the
evi-dentialist objection against religious belief were ef-fective, it
would also show that friendship is immoral, which, I think, we can take
to be a reductio ad absurdum.
In sum, according to the evidentialist objection, a belief must be
epistemically warranted in order to be morally justified, and the
evidence for religious belief is not sufficient to provide epistemic
warrant for the degree of certainty characteristic of religious belief.
Plantinga denies that evidence is needed for epis-temic warrant and
argues that belief in God is episte-mically warranted in the absence of
any evidence whatsoever. Others argue that there is sufficient evidence
to render religious belief epistemically war-ranted. I have sided,
however, with those who hold that it is incorrect to assume, as the
evidentialists do, that a belief must be epistemically warranted in
order to be morally justified. And I argue that con-cern for a good
which the belief plus the belief’s truth would help one realize can
supplement evidence in order to morally justify certainty.
B. Why Reasons Are Needed For Religious Belief
I have said that evidence is needed for the belief to be
reasonable. But one might question this. Why are reasons needed at all
for religious belief? Why not just say that concern for a good other
than truth can by itself morally justify a belief?
Whenever one acts one ought to be concerned with how one’s action
is related to the various goods that will be affected by one’s action.
Epistemic warrant is secondary. The purpose of epistemic warrant is
solely to ensure that one is more likely to possess more of the truth
than one would if one’s beliefs were not epistemically warranted. So,
in every act of belief—an action which necessarily bears on the good of
possession of truth—one ought to be concerned with how one’s action
affects the good of possession of truth. Therefore, if one stops and
asks oneself whether one’s religious belief is a good thing, then one
morally ought to examine or consider how that belief is related to the
good of possession of truth before one accepts or continues to accept
it. That is, one morally ought to consider how likely it is that this
belief is true. So if one considered whether one’s religious belief is
a good thing, but failed to examine how this belief is likely to be
related to truth, that is, if one failed to consider the evidence, then
one would act without sufficient regard for the good of possession of
truth. For this reason, for those who reflect on their religious
belief, to believe in the absence of reasons or evidence seems
objectively immoral.
What about someone who does not reflect on his religious belief,
someone who believes sponta-neously, without asking himself whether his
religious belief is a good thing—for example, a child? Is such belief
objectively immoral or improper? I believe the answer to this question
is no, for there does not seem to be any general moral duty to
scrutinize every spontaneous choice, and I see no special ground for
there being such a duty in the area of choices which involve how one
is related to the good of possession of truth. So, for those who
reflect on their religious belief evidence is necessary.
C. How Evidence or Reasons Function In Religious Belief
The main function of evidence or reasons in religious belief is not
to show the truth of what is believed—for then faith would not be
required. Nor is the main function of reasons even to show the truth of
the factual proposition that God has spoken. Rather, the main function
of reasons in religious belief is to show the truth of the moral
proposition that I ought to believe.
Suppose a young man has just been in a serious motorcycle accident
and almost killed. He is lying in the hospital bed with his head
bandaged so that he can only see dimly and hear vaguely. Suppose also
that the hospital authorities have informed him that his treatment will
be discontinued unless he proves himself able to pay the bill, and he
cannot do that. Further, the boy was estranged from his family a few
years back; he left home, say, after a heated argument with his
parents. While he is lying in the hospital bed a man comes into his
room, claims to be his brother, and claims to have a message from their
father, that the father is in town and would like to visit the boy and
receive the boy back into the family.
Since the boy cannot see or hear well, it is not immediately
evident that the person speaking to him really is who he says he is.
Maybe, the boy reflects, the man is really a doctor trying to make him
feel good before he dies. So, it seems that the boy has a choice; he
can believe the claim or not. What should the boy do?
Perhaps he would listen to the alleged brother very carefully.
Perhaps he would investigate him and what he says, to determine as well
as he could whether he acts like his brother would act, whether he does
and says just the kinds of things his brother would say and do.
Similarly, people looking into the Christian claim should look at Jesus,
his deeds, and his teaching to see whether Jesus does indeed act like a
messenger from God, and whether he does and says the things that only a
messenger of God would and could do.
The boy might scrutinize the alleged brother’s message to see if it
is the sort of message his father would give, whether, perhaps, it
reveals things only his father would know, whether, that is, it has the
marks or signs of really being a message from his father. Likewise,
people can investigate Christian teaching and ask whether it has signs
of having a divine origin.
Suppose that in the boy’s case the evidence is not sufficient to
compel the boy’s assent. Suppose that the evidence by itself does not
warrant absolute certainty, but, say, only a high degree of
probability. Nevertheless, at some point there might be enough evidence
so that the boy ought to accept the claim. The basic goods of
friendship (with his father) and health (his own) could require this;
that is, there could be situations in which anyone who has a love for
these goods would accept the claim. The boy ought not to demand
absolute proof before he accepts the claim made by the (alleged)
brother. Were he to do so, this would indicate an ungracious or impious
attitude toward his father and perhaps an insufficient regard for his
own health.
Similarly, at some point the evidence for the Chris-tian claim
might be such that it does not provide epistemic warrant for absolute
certainty, but is enough so that one morally ought to accept the
proposal as certainly true. Just as in the boy’s situation, so here, to
demand absolute proof, to demand proof that would be proportionate to
the assent asked of one, is lacking in the virtues of gratitude and
piety, and perhaps an intelligent con-cern for one’s ultimate welfare.
And this shows how evidence or reasons function. They function, not to
show with absolute certainty the theoretical proposition that the claim
is a fact, but to show the moral proposition that I ought to
believe. Without such reasons or signs of credibility it may still be
permissible to believe. But it seems that reasons or signs of
credibility are needed to put one in a situation where one morally ought
to believe.
It is worth remembering that someone may have reasons for believing
something without being able to articulate those reasons. The reasons
for holding that God has indeed spoken, the signs of credibility, need
not be the same as what one may read in an apologetics book. The
sublimity and evident sanctity of Christian doctrine, of the liturgy,
and of the Church (or members of the Church), these are signs indicating
that the gospel is God’s message and that the Church has a divine origin
and guidance.
One’s ability to see this sublimity or more-than-human quality is
aided, or perhaps in most cases, made possible, by divine help, i.e.,
divine grace. The recognition of beauty and the recognition of gene-rosity
in other people require an ability or “sense” on the part of the
subject. An art critic sees beauty in a painting where others without
his “aesthetic sense” will see only paint on a canvas. Someone who has
no generosity himself is typically unable to see gene-rosity in others,
so that such a person continually asks, “What’s that person’s angle?”
The beauty and generosity are really there, only they require an ability
or sense on the part of the subject to be recognized. In a similar way,
the presence of the Holy Spirit in a human person enables her to
recognize the sublime and the holy, or really, the divine, in the words
and deeds of the prophets and of Jesus, handed on to us in the Church.
Thus, of the Good Shepherd, Jesus says that he calls his own sheep by
name and the sheep hear his voice, “And the sheep follow him because
they know his voice. But a stranger they will not follow, but will
flee from him because they do not know the voice of strangers.” (Jn,
10:4‑6)
In sum, I have argued that Plantinga’s account of epistemic warrant
is mistaken or incomplete, and have argued for an internalist constraint
upon the circumstances that provide epistemic warrant. Second, with
this stricter or narrower view of epistemic warrant, I argued that we
should probably grant that the certainty of Christian belief does not
have epistemic warrant (although it is not irrational either).
Third, I argued that the certainty of Christian belief is morally
justified, because it is morally proper to believe partly for the sake
of a good other than possession of truth, in the case of Christian
belief, for the sake of the personal communion offered. Fourth, I
argued that to be morally justified, the religious belief of reflective
believers must have evidence or reasons, for only then does such an act
of belief have the morally required regard for the basic good of
possession of truth. And, fifth, I argued that the function that
reasons or evidence play in a reasonable act of faith is to make it
clear to oneself that one’s act of belief is a morally responsible act,
or that one morally ought to believe.
Notes
4 Perhaps the
ethics of belief can be clarified by comparing it with the ethics of
sex, although of course there are also important differences. The
sexual power is naturally oriented to the procreative good, while the
cognitive power is naturally oriented to the possession of truth. But
just as it does not follow that the sexual power must be used only
for procreation (no one argues this) so also it does not follow
that one’s cognitive acts, one’s acts of believing, must be influenced
only by the goal of truth. What follows is that all of the basic goods
that could be affected by the action carrying out one’s choice must be
respected. Just as one ought not to negate the procreative good, so one
ought not to negate the good of possession of truth.
But just as
the choice to engage in sex for the sake of expressing marital communion
is morally good if it is a choice that does not disregard the
procreative good; so it would seem that the choice to believe for the
sake of a basic good which the belief, together with the truth of the
belief, will help one realize, could in some instances be morally good,
i.e., in those instances where truth is not disregarded. In neither
case does there seem to be a choice to impede or destroy an instance of
a basic good; in neither case does it seem necessary that one disregard
an instance of a basic good. The two cases seem to be similar in this
respect.
Yet there is
this significant disanalogy. In sex, failing to procreate is only not
realizing a good that could have been realized. With the intellect, if
one’s belief fails to attain truth, it is false, which means one’s
cognitive grasp upon reality is harmed (in an important matter) instead
of simply not being realized. For this reason, while one need not
intend or try to bring it about in every sexual act that conception
result (it is enough that one’s sexual act be open to conception, I
would argue); in every act of belief one ought to hope, and if necessary
make an effort to bring it about, that one’s belief is true. Still, in
both cases there seems to nothing wrong in one’s act being influenced
simultaneously by more than one good.
Posted July 7, 2010