From The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 36 (1982), pp. 23-49,
reprinted in his
Individuals and
Their Rights
(Open Court, 1989). I thank Professor Machan for
providing me with this slightly revised
version.
Epistemology and Moral Knowledge
Tibor R.
Machan
I
Arguments abound
against the view that it is possible to know what is morally right or
wrong, good or evil, in personal, social, political, and other realms.
Such arguments, as well as those that defend the possibility of moral
knowledge, have had varying degrees of success throughout the history of
philosophy.1 In recent times, the skeptical stance has fared
quite well, whereas in the era of Plato and Aristotle, for example,
cognitivism—in the form of essentialism or naturalism2—held the
upper hand.
The
Platonic-Aristotelian approach in meta-ethics seems once again to be
appealing to a significant number of working philosophers. But while a
resurgence of naturalism has emerged on several philosophical fronts, not
much has been done to synthesize it, to assemble its various strands. This
article will present, in outline, a position that both gives support to
and makes use of a certain rendition of the argument that we can identify
right and wrong, etc., by reference to the nature of things, that is, by
considering what something is essentially or by definition. Not all the
various argumentative strains involved will be fully developed, but the
direction of each argument that is relevant will be clearly enough
indicated. Thus the prospects of the various strains, as well as of the
entire position, will be available for scrutiny. This sort of synthesis
seems to have its importance, as much of traditional philosophical thought
suggests.
A prominent view of
what a theory of knowledge must accomplish will first be challenged since
this view has made much difference in the present endeavor, viz., basing
morality on the nature of things. Next it will be suggested why the
requirements placed on a theory of knowledge have made it appear that we
can know what is the case in non-normative domains but not when it comes
to norms—or principles of right and wrong—concerning human conduct,
institutions, laws, etc. Here the source of the famous “is/ought” gap will
be indicated. A contextualist account of human knowledge will be proposed
and it will be shown why it is quite possibly correct, suggesting how this
approach to understanding knowledge could work toward eliminating the
dichotomy between “is” and “ought.” If what is maintained in this paper is
indeed correct, the possibility of moral knowledge will (again) be seen as
a reasonably good prospect. And finally, such a prospect will be indicated
at the conclusion of this paper.
II
Analyses of human
knowledge have to a considerable extent been under the influence of the
belief that stating what knowledge is will, if true, amount to a necessary
truth—that is, a formal proposition that is timelessly incontrovertible.
Let me spell this out a bit.
Suppose someone defines
the concept “knowledge” as “P.” Suppose, also, that a complicated science
fiction story can be imagined—or a conjurer’s trick, or a very clever
conspiracy—in the light of which it appears that someone has attained a
clear grasp of some state of affairs or situation but in so doing has not
satisfied the criteria specified in “P.” Our ordinary notion that having
grasped the state of affairs—having come to be fully confident of the
relevant state of affairs— is exactly what amounts to knowing that state
of affairs now conflicts with the definition of knowledge proposed.
Accordingly, the definition will be dismissed as a bad one because the
reigning model of what knowledge must be requires that when the concept is
defined correctly as “P,” the relationship between the concept and “P” can
only amount to a mutual entailment.
That this is the
reigning model is surely not controversial, although some challenges can
be found.3 It will be useful to have a clear cut example of the
use of the model in the effort to provide an analysis of the concept of
knowledge, lest a mere general statement be construed as perhaps a slight
misrepresentation. In his well-known discussion of the topic, Keith Lehrer
tells us that he is concerned
with precisely the question of what conditions are necessary and
sufficient for a man to have knowledge, or, more precisely, to know that p
or that S is true, where “p” is a variable that would be replaced by a
declarative sentence and “S” by the name of a sentence.4
Lehrer goes on to say that
an analysis of knowledge may be given in an equivalence of one of
the following two forms:
S knows that p if and only if.
or
S
knows that Q is true if and only if.5
Furthermore, this approach, taken by many others besides Lehrer, is also
regarded to be free of any preconceptions or bias. Lehrer states, for
example, that:
In our investigation we shall begin without making any assumptions
concerning the postulates of our theory of knowledge and thus consider any
logically possible case as a potential counterexample.6
In other words, Lehrer seems to believe that his program for presenting
“an analysis of knowledge” places no restrictions on what the outcome
might turn out to be. In fact, it is clear that Lehrer’s specifications
given above are infused with certain assumptions, including the most
crucial one concerning what a theory of knowledge must produce, namely, a
proposition with a very strictly specified form.7 When Lehrer
states that “an analysis of knowledge may be given” in the manner he
states, he is restricting any purported conception or theory of knowledge
to producing necessarily true statements, ones expressed via the timeless
conditional of “if and only if,” a logical connective that can only be
satisfied if only purely formal relations of a certain sort are satisfied.
Is it reasonable to
require that knowledge be analyzed along lines suggested by Lehrer? Is the
built-in timelessness demanded of any purported analysis, definition, or
statement of the nature or essence of knowledge something indispensable,
as Lehrer suggests by his statement of how an analysis “may be given”?
Must we be asking “the question of what conditions are necessary and
sufficient for a man to have knowledge” in the formalist sense Lehrer
prefers, or does asking the question along such lines already prejudge for
us the sort of outcome that will be acceptable? And while there is little
controversy about the meaning of the phrase “logically possible,” there is
considerable debate about what is presupposed in an accurate
account of that meaning.8
While a good deal of
epistemological work follows the approach Lehrer uses, some changes are
evident. And certain philosophical positions that rely on the results of
work in epistemology need not be evaluated on the basis of whether the
arguments in support of them conform to the requirements embodied in the
approach Lehrer and others take to the analysis of knowledge. That is to
say, if one were to claim that it is possible to know some proposition
even if knowing it could not be analyzed along the lines Lehrer prefers,
there is work in epistemology that could vindicate the claim.
For example, already in
J. L. Austin’s “Other Minds”9 a different characterization of
knowledge emerged. In terms of his account, it could be said, correctly,
that someone knows something while the possibility of some wild
counterexample could also be accepted.1° It seems that Austin’s idea of
what is required in an account of knowing differs considerably from what,
e.g., Lehrer assumes such an account must achieve. Suppose we claim to
know that something is a goldfinch and suppose, also, that goldfinches
are not talking birds. It does not follow, from
Austin’s
conception of knowledge, that the possibility of some such bird quoting
poems must lead us to withdraw our claim to knowledge. If some goldfinch
actually did produce poetic utterances, our concept of gold- finches would
have to be revised but all our previous knowledge claims would not be
invalidated. For those like Lehrer, however, a definition of knowledge
carries with it a claim to logical necessity (and certainty) which
then—because they are such strong requirements—admit highly implausible
defeating possibilities. Austin’s approach, however, could accommodate a
number of areas of conceptual change, leading to a position in line with
which we need not accept the view, e.g., that science is a history of
hopeless errors because it does not produce timeless truth and knowledge.
Austin’s
idea is more in accord with Gilbert Harman’s advice that “We must take
care not to adopt a very skeptical attitude nor become too lenient about
what is to count as knowledge.”11
III
In providing an
alternative to the formalist approach Lehrer takes in trying to identify
what knowledge is, let us recall a very instructive passage from an essay
by Barry Stroud in which he set out to explain Wittgenstein’s idea of
logical necessity. Stroud’s interpretation of Wittgenstein can set the
stage for a non-formalist account of human knowledge. Stroud tells us that
by Wittgenstein’s explanation, logical necessity
is not like rails that stretch to infinity and compel us always to go in
one and only one way; but neither is it the case that we are not compelled
at all. Rather, there are the rails we have already traveled, and we can
extend them beyond the present point only by depending on those that
already exist. In order for the rails to be navigable they must be
extended in smooth and natural ways; how they are to be continued is to
that extent determined by the route of those rails which are already
there.12
It is instructive to
note that Stroud adds to this characterization a point about why he has
addressed this issue. He says that he has “been primarily concerned to
explain the sense in which we are ‘responsible’ for the ways in which the
rails are extended, without destroying anything that could properly be
called their objectivity.”13 Stroud indicates by this remark
that he disapproves of the equivocation between formalism and objectivism
regarding what amounts to knowing the nature of something like knowledge.
To put it another way, objectivism does not require Platonism concerning
the nature of what is known.
To develop some of the
points suggested thus far, a different approach to answering the question
“What is knowledge?” will now be provided from that which Lehrer and other
formalists have been urging upon us. It bears mentioning at the outset
that what follows from this approach applies not only to answering the
question about the nature of knowledge but also to answering questions
concerning the nature of anything else. In other words, this paper aims to
provide the groundwork for a theory of (the character of) definitions. The
difficulty here consists, in part, in distinguishing between the general
question, “What is (the nature of) X?” and the more specific question of
“What is it to know (the nature of) X?” Even more specifically, this paper
is also concerned with shedding some light on the proper approach to the
question of “What it is to know (the nature of) knowledge?” Although the
answers to these questions overlap, they are not identical, and it will be
clear shortly why this is so.
Knowledge, to begin
with, is just as much part of the natural world as anything else we are
familiar with—e.g., chairs, trees, sorrow, explosions, months, melodies,
and so forth. Knowledge takes place on this earth, in our universe and is
found where we find all those other aspects of reality we want to
understand and define correctly. As with the rest, we could benefit
considerably from arriving at a definition of knowledge, by answering the
general question “What is (the nature of) knowledge?”—that is, by placing
knowledge into a coherent and useful scheme of categories. 14
Putting it this way by no means renders the conception of a definition of
something either nominal or conventional, linking our definitions
less to nature than to our interests. If firefighters are using some
method by which to extinguish a blaze, it is true enough that what they
are doing relates to their or society’s concerns. But it does not follow
that they therefore can go about this task in any which way we might
imagine. The fire itself, as something definite, imposes standards on the
process of fighting it. Similarly, while it is true that human beings are
concerned to understand reality, to make distinctions and to integrate
things in a coherent fashion, reality itself presents for them limits on
their options and methods, as regards both what there is to
understand and how they can go about doing this task.
Since we encounter
knowledge in nature, it is reasonable to expect that knowledge would share
some of the features or characteristics we find true of other aspects of
the natural world. For example, it is temporal and spacial.15
Of course, which aspects of knowledge are temporal, and which spacial, are
complicated issues. All that is suggested here is that knowledge is to be
construed, in its most general respect, as a natural phenomenon. As a
consequence, it is possible for knowledge to undergo some changes as time
passes and all the activities and things surrounding knowledge exert
influence on it. So understanding knowledge would suggest right off that a
purely formalistic approach to understanding it would be off the mark.
When seeking a
definition of knowledge, it would be wrong to preclude the possibility
that knowledge can change, although the conditions for such change could
be quite rigorously circumscribed. But the possibility of having to change
a definition developed by our best lights today would have to be admitted.
This, in turn, leaves it open that such a definition would not manage to
withstand the test of counterexamples based on what is only imaginable or
possibly possible.16 In terms of the approach suggested here,
defining knowledge—giving an analysis or developing a theory of it— would
have to be regarded as a task similar to those performed by botanists or
geologists or astronomers, all of whom aim at formulating definitions
without assuming the impossible task of making those definitions
timelessly correct.
In contrast, then, to
Lehrer’s approach, here definitions are not modeled on necessary truths.
Yet this framework does not preclude the possibility that some definitions
will be necessary truths. Inquiring into the nature of something involves
leaving open the question whether what will be discovered or formulated
will or will not have the character of necessary truth—a point that would
seem to be objectionable only if it is already taken to be necessary that
definitions are necessary truths (or, alternatively, cannot be necessary
truths). Some definitions would, accordingly, be open- ended—e.g., the
statement of the central characteristics of some little-known class of
items in astrophysics, say, black holes. Here further inquiry will
probably require considerable readjustment, yet even the most thorough
study will not yield a definition that can foreclose all further
revisions. In metaphysics, on the other hand, it is mostly likely that
definitions of key concepts will have to be necessary truths as well,
because if metaphysical propositions can be true, they would hold for the
past, present, future, and the possible—that is, for everything at all
times.17
A science—and, at the
outset, every budding scientist—begins with encountering nature in the
rough and ready, so to speak.18 Only later do detailed studies
get under way. Similarly, epistemologists first encounter knowledge in the
rough and ready and only later endeavor to embark upon formulating a
definition of their subject. Epistemologists, as other students of nature,
must leave open the possibility of being warranted to formulate a
definition of knowledge which conforms to standards of adequacy which
differ from standards applicable in other fields, including in other
branches of philosophy, e.g., metaphysics. (Yet, it seems it has
been their initial commitment to finding metaphysical truths, on which to
rest others in the firmest possible fashion, that has led them to embrace
the standards applicable in metaphysics in their search for truth about
the nature of knowledge.)19
The suitable approach
for epistemologists would seem to be to look around for cases of human
beings trying to become better and better aware of the world, more and
more surefooted in what they claim to be aware of, and so forth. They
should study human beings who embark upon comparisons of this with that,
upon differentiation and integration of what they encounter in nature.
From this study they should then develop a theory of knowledge—of what it
is to know—in general, and what differences there might be found in the
knowledge of differing aspects of reality. Along the way, the
epistemologist would very likely find that knowledge can be obtained of
not only different kinds and types of things, but also of things in
different respects—e.g., in particular and in general. This would probably
lead the epistemologist to the development of a theory of definitions. As
the epistemologist attains, at any given time, the most coherent and
complete conception of what knowledge is and states the results in an
organized proposition, what is obtained is a definition of knowledge.
Now clearly there are
some self-reflexive elements in this process, since as the epistemologist
is learning about knowledge, including about knowledge of definitions, one
of the results that will emerge is knowledge of the definition of
knowledge. This is a complication and requires extreme care, admittedly.
And there is not going to be any guarantee against error. But the last
thing that an epistemologist should demand is that the definition of
knowledge produced must withstand a test that is properly aimed at
scrutinizing timelessly necessary truths. Yet it is precisely because of
this kind of test that definitions of knowledge tend to succumb over and
over again, especially in such difficult areas of knowledge as ethics and
politics. But we will turn to that later.
Let me note here that
what has been suggested above may have two very important results. Just as
the conception of knowledge is illegitimately modeled on necessary truth,
so the conception of definitions in general must be freed from that
prerequisite. Instead, the contextually correct definition (given
time and present information) is what can and should (only) be required.
This suggests that the most rationally warranted identification of a place
in a scheme of categories that has been developed (by means of our
sorting, listing, grouping—i.e., study—as we differentiate and integrate
the available materials in some range of awareness) qualifies as the
definition which should be formulated. The definition of knowledge itself
would best be conceived of as the currently most rationally warranted end
result of the epistemologist’s study of a given range of phenomena. But
this characterization of definitions would also be part of the
epistemologist’s stock in trade. That is to say, one of the results of a
sound theory of knowledge would be that when someone knows the nature of
something—i.e., has formulated a correct definition of this something,
say, the concept “knowledge” or “human being” or “justice”—this would
enable one to produce a statement which correctly places some range of
items, events, activities, institutions, or the like in the most up to
date, well developed scheme of categories human beings have managed to
develop.
Before some additional
material to support the present approach is provided, some possible
objections need to be addressed. First, it may be argued that to abandon
the possibility of timelessly true definitions is to abandon also the
possibility of correct or true definitions, since without the prospect of
such timelessness, the generality of our definitions (and the
understanding supposedly facilitated by them) will vanish. After all, one
point of defining a concept, for example, and “knowledge,” is to have some
initial understanding of any instance of, say, someone knowing
something—i.e., so as to be able to distinguish a mere claim to knowledge
from a genuine instance. Yet without the timeless quality, what would
justify our retaining any definition from one instance or case to the
next, when all these take place at a different time from the next and so
forth?
Another challenge that
is worth meeting right off is that which would identify the present
position with out and out nominalism. If definitions are not timeless and,
indeed, are places in schemes of categories, what guarantee do we have
that they state the nature of things? What relationship do such
definitions—such purported statements of the nature of something—have to
reality, to the actual beings of things, events, etc.? Is it not more
likely that conceiving of definitions or the nature of things along such
lines drives us toward the view that what definitions are comes to no more
than labels or names which comprise, at best, a consistent system with no
established tie to reality at all?
More problems could be
discussed, but these are the most crucial ones to handle. First, then, let
me note that the requirement of timelessness, although one with a long
history, is unreasonable even though suggestive. That is to say, although
strict timelessness is an unreasonable standard to set for the adequacy of
correct definitions, stability through different spans of time is
definitely not unreasonable. As Stroud notes, there must be something
workably steady, smooth, and natural in the way in which the definition of
a concept—or the necessary and sufficient attributes of something—evolve
through time. Different aspects of nature, of course, possess different
degrees of stability, durability, integrity, and so forth, and a correct
definition of such different aspects of nature will need to take careful
account of that fact. A definition of the concept “human being” that makes
it impossible to integrate our knowledge of human life today with the
lives of the men and women of ancient China or Egypt will falter on
grounds that the evidence we have of these civilizations will be rendered
incoherent without a more durable and comprehensive conception of human
nature. What is unreasonable, however, is to require that a correct
definition of human beings should have to accommodate every logically
possible fantasy that might be imagined in connection with something
roughly akin to human life. The sort of science fiction cases often used
to test ethical and political theories—whereby some definition of human
justice is put to the test by reference to the possible or possibly
possible behavior of “human” beings that have no personal identity or any
interest in their children or personal safety—testify to the adherence of
some philosophers to a conception of timelessly true definitions which
sees the world not so much as a stable place but as a static one. In
short, then, contextually true definitions will need, still, to do justice
to the actual stability of the phenomena of the natural world and
the revisions of definitions would need to proceed along “smooth and
natural ways,” meaning that any extension of the rails should be done only
when required by the force of observation or argument. Which may mean, of
course, that some such definitions, namely, those serving the field of
metaphysics, would have to be unchangeable, if true. But the requirement
of timelessness would itself be based on our findings, not imposed a
priori.
The charge that this
position is but a roundabout way of putting the old-fashioned nominalist
case is a serious one, also. In order to do full justice to it, however,
one would need to develop a theory of perceptual knowledge, one which
would show that not all knowledge is propositional. Thus, although
propositional knowledge, resting as it must on the knowledge of
definitions, may appear to be ungrounded in reality, because such
knowledge is itself grounded in perceptual awareness, which does not rest
on knowledge of definitions, nominalism is avoided. The provision of the
present position that requires that a definition correctly state the place
some range of things, events, etc., occupies in a scheme of categories is
tied to the additional provision that human beings can become aware of
nature by way of their senses, that they gain evidence of existence by
direct observation, and that it is by way of the rational
organization—differentiation and integration—of what they are aware of
that a rational scheme of categories is developed by them. The places
carved in such a scheme are justified by a process of careful (scientific,
ordinary, philosophical, etc.) reasoning, at least at their best or most
accurate. And to say that some definition is correct or true is to say
just that it would properly fit into such a scheme as is rationally
developed by human beings. Anything beyond that—e.g., some alleged “real”
final order of nature—is philosophical fantasy, so the inability of the
present account to accommodate the desire for it cannot be regarded as a
genuine shortcoming. Nominalism, on the other hand, does not enable us to
secure the sort of direct ties to reality that would be made possible via
a theory of perceptual knowledge which the present viewpoint presupposes.
Of course, without the success of such a theory, the present conception of
knowledge and definitions rests on shaky grounds.20
At this point it will
be necessary to move on to a consideration of how the above may make
possible the recovery of an adequate account of moral (and political)
knowledge.
IV
Earlier it was pointed
out that a theory of knowledge would take account of the fact that
although knowledge needs to involve firm awareness of reality, the sort of
awareness of reality involved may depend on the aspect of reality in
question. For example, it was noted that while definitions of concepts in
metaphysics may have the character of necessary truths, definitions of
concepts in astrophysics probably would not. At this point it will be
necessary to go a bit further by offering what we could call an
ontological hypothesis. The proposal is that nature is fundamentally
multifaceted, multi-aspectival, or comprised of various modes of existence
which are (at least from the point of view of present understanding)
irreducibly unique.
What this proposal
comes to is that existence seems not merely the duplication or
multiplication of one kind of being into an endless number, but rather the
presence of various kinds and types and modes of being. For example, we
are aware of such drastically different types of existent things as time,
music, objects, distances, animals, memories, edicts, commands, etc., etc.
Notice that the list includes different types, not just different
kinds. Reality seems clearly to confront us with a variety of
ontological domains or spheres. At the same time, reality also seems
integrated in terms of some general, what Aristotle called first,
principles; e.g., contradictions are impossible in nature, regardless of
which ontological domain is at issue. The principle of noncontradiction
is, from all that we know, universal, transcending all particulars as well
as different types or ontological domains.
On the other hand,
there seems, also, to reign a pluralism atop this monism of basic
principles, one which embodies the fact of the widest imaginable range of
variety in what sorts of beings there are in reality. Things true of some
sorts are clearly not of others— e.g., animals need nourishment, rocks
don’t; melodies can be harmonized, weeks or days cannot. The facts
involved in some aspects of reality are entirely absent in some others, as
a matter of ontological distinctiveness. Memories may be faint but feet
could not be; commands may be firm but distances could not. The point is
that contrary to reductionist views reality is inherently diverse. That
is, it is impossible to account for the facts about all aspects of reality
by reference to just one distinct aspect, e.g., the physical or mental or
numerical, except, perhaps, by allowing for a very extensive evolutionary
process. Reductionist theorists tend, on the whole, to be promissory.
Furthermore, even if in some sense all things might be given an account of
simply in terms of some one kind of thing, that is not what is relevant
nor is it the way human beings, including those who propose that idea,
make sense of reality.
While in detailed
metaphysical discussions the above ontological hypothesis would require
extensive support, for present purposes it will have to be taken as merely
a plausible backdrop for certain epistemological considerations. Given
what has already been said about the nature of knowledge and definitions,
the ontological hypothesis suggested above may shed light on whether moral
(or political) knowledge is possible. To wit, if there are irreducible
differences between distinct ontological realms, and if we can obtain
knowledge of facts within distinct ontological realms, the character of
knowledge involved in knowing these facts could very well reflect the
differences at issue. Certainly, the idea that what we know—our objects of
knowledge—could have a decisive impact on the character (or sense) of the
knowledge involved is not implausible. Knowing the time of day could very
well be knowledge of considerable distinction compared to knowing the name
of all the kinds of alloys or compared to knowing what will most readily
upset Susan’s grandmother. The sort of things we should use to test these
different cases of alleged knowing would themselves differ considerably.
Now it is not merely
meant here that knowing one thing is different from knowing another,
something that is plain enough, of course. Rather, the possibility is
being advanced that when we in fact know some things in a given
ontological domain—e.g., a song in the musical or a rock in the physical
or, again, someone’s recollections in the mental—the character of the
requirements to be met so as to establish that we in fact have (or our
justification of) knowledge will differ. Thus to test whether someone
knows a song, one requires that at least some of the crucial passages can
be at least doodled by the person making the knowledge claim. Whereas to
test whether one knows what limestone is would appear to require the
correct listing of chemical components which comprise the material in
question. To know, what someone’s recollections of last summer at the
beach are would have to be tested, in turn, e.g., by comparing that
person’s reports with what he’s said before when asked. There are, of
course, common aspects to these tests— awareness needs to be demonstrated.
But the awareness will take a different form in the different cases,
calling to the fore different skills and utilizing different
faculties—e.g., good ear, acute observation and learning, familiarity with
an individual. In general, there can be an indefinite number of types of
knowing, with different expectations associated with each type. Knowing
the past, the present, the future, and the possible can involve very
different sorts of evidence, argument, and performance.
Accordingly, instead of
the familiar distinction between knowledge of is and knowledge of
ought, a much more diverse conception of knowledge is being
suggested here. The idea is that, probably, parallel to each ontological
domain a mode or type of knowledge has emerged. For example, mathematical
knowledge probably has its unique features, distinct from biological
knowledge. In turn, if there is a genuine, irreducible moral domain—either
fully or partially merged with the political, or, perhaps autonomous—there
is, probably, also a unique mode of knowledge that corresponds to it.
The reason for the
hesitancy in putting these points forth is that one would not be able to
argue for them in any ordinary way, certainly not in the way familiar in
the sort of epistemological and meta-ethical works as Lehrer’s,
Chisholm’s, and von Wright’s and Hare’s, respectively.21 But
there is an argument here, and it takes the form of an attempt to make the
best sense of a range of phenomena, namely, that range that constitutes
the interrelated concerns involved in trying to understand morality. In
short the general framework is being spelled out in such a way that we can
accept that moral knowledge is possible without jeopardizing evident
differences between purported moral knowledge and other knowledge the
denial of which would be unreasonable. If the model of a conception or
definition of knowledge Lehrer and others embrace is indeed prejudiced, as
argued, and if it is reasonable to open up our conception of definitions,
including the nature of something, then, with the possibility of the
multifaceted ideas of both reality and knowledge, there could be ample
room for moral knowledge despite the type of arguments that moral skeptics
present. Of course, this last point would benefit from some illustration.
For example, the sort
of argument presented in the so-called naturalistic fallacy objection to
moral knowledge trades heavily on a narrow conception of what it means
that the nature of goodness is X. The open question argument assumes that
when something has X as its nature, it must be inconceivable that anything
without X could nevertheless be best regarded as being an X. But if thing
is X—has as its nature X—that thing in some perfectly respectable manner
could be imagined not to be X. Clint Eastwood is a macho character
in the movies but he is easily imaginable as not being such a character in
some movies. That horse down the field can be imagined to be but a statue
of a horse, or perhaps a movie image of one.
Earlier it was noted
that any logically possible counterexample need not serve to place doubt
in our definition of knowledge, with Gettier type cases in mind. In
connection with a complex field such as moral knowledge, the Gettier type
counterexamples can be overwhelming. (Judith Jarvis Thomson is an artist
in producing them, as is Robert Nozick.) But if definitions can be right
without conforming to that strict conception of what they must be,
as spelled out in so much of recent epistemology, then the definition of
goodness and of moral goodness might not be so insurmountable a task as it
has seemed.
Apart from that very
general point, which in a broad sense illustrates how moral knowledge
might be possible—i.e., by removing some familiar obstacles from its path
to success—it would also help considering some specific example of judging
some deed as right or wrong. But this is equally difficult, if not more
so, as making the general point. The familiar desert-island or raft-boat
cases, or even the fat man on the San Francisco bridge who should or should not be used to save the life of many
others in a run away cable car, are inadequate because their context is
hopelessly sketchy. They establish nothing much, whichever way they go. It
is no wonder that the intuitionist approach appears to suit those cases
best—at least the subconscious mind has developed the needed reflexes, in
most cases, to come to grips with some such cases. But the complexity and
number of the facts that are filled in for purposes of getting a
reasonably complete picture—a “real life” situation—are duplicable usually
only in actual case histories or very well constructed novels, plays,
songs, etc.
There is, moreover,
something special about moral knowledge which is perhaps not there
in any other sort, namely, that it is severely self-referential and
tempting of self-deception. The stake any person has in particular moral
knowledge is considerable— provided there is indeed a genuine, bona fide
moral realm of human life. Such a realm concerns the very quality of a
person’s actions and, ultimately the person’s life—himself or herself.
That alone poses problems, because there is special interest, tempting
everyone, to plead the case for some way of conceiving of goodness so that
one enhances it more than not. In other fields of human understanding
there is some of that temptation, too, but mostly confined to special
competence. The moral dimensions of being lazy on the job, stealing
someone else’s ideas or property at work, faking some task a bit, even
being merely negligent with rather meager impact—the dimensions of these
are narrow, although sometimes intensely felt. A scientist who
betrays the standards of the profession is morally guilty. Yet mistakes,
even failures, in special fields do not seem to cast general aspersions on
the person. The answer to the sort of question, “What, in general, is to
be morally good?” in contrast unearths fundamentals, matters that span the
details of one’s life.
These last points alone
prove nothing. They suggest, however, that lack of wide agreement,
widespread disagreement, as to what is morally right or good need not be
due to the truth of moral skepticism. They also aid in appreciating the
impact of the wrong- headed model of moral knowledge imported from general
epistemology and the model of definitional knowledge. With many people
having a special interest in watering down any moral theory—some even
having a professional or sporting interest in debunking its very
possibility—the interest in constructing possible counterexamples may be
considerable.
Furthermore, moral
knowledge could indeed be extremely diverse in itself, making room for
variations based on all sorts of factors. We should perhaps think again,
of morality as the science, and of ethics or applied morality or praxis,
as the resulting engineering, with the important addition that a lot of
the science is inadequate, even fake, and much of the engineering ill
guided and even misdirected. Even apart from these features, moral
knowledge at its best will be highly individuated in some practical
situations. Weighing the importance of things for any person, even with a
very general common framework available and shared with others, is
difficult. Against this it should, however, be recalled that within all
the variations of what is morally right, there runs the widespread
awareness of some commonality, one that prompts the question in such
categorical ways as “What, in general, ought a human being be like?,”
“What is the morally good life?” and “How can I lead my life in a
virtuous, proper, self-respecting manner?” Even convinced skeptics
transform such questions rather than treat them as on par with those of
palmistry or voodoo?22
Given, then, that moral
knowledge is not precluded by any general “is/ought” problem, given that
defining moral goodness could be managed, and given that something else
besides its impossibility explains the problems found with moral
knowledge, where does this leave us?
One promising approach
appears to be intuitionism in its best form, as spelled out by Mark Platt,23
for example, where we are told that there simply are clear cases of moral
knowledge no one can reasonably dispute. I will not spend time disputing
this doctrine but merely state my dissatisfaction with it, which is based
on the fact that the integration of this intuitionism with the rest of
epistemology is problematic. It leaves as a problem, I believe, the
coherence of the relationship between moral knowledge and knowledge of
other matters. It also makes it difficult if not entirely hopeless to try
to resolve conflicting intuitions. But whether this is indeed the way that
theory stands cannot be examined here.
It may now be
suggested, instead, that the distinctive moral domain emerges when we
reflect on the fact of human life. First of all, the broad domain of value
appears with the emergence of life per se.24 When we consider
the nature of life as self-generated behavior that can foster either
sustenance or demise, the category of something being of value to the
living thing emerges and acquires clear significance and meaning. It is
for the living that something is of value or disvalue, since living
things alone are faced with the constant possibility of extinction.
Now even before
proceeding, we can see the way that a defective epistemological framework
invites devastating challenges to the above. Consider some of the
objections Robert Nozick poses to Ayn Rand’s efforts to develop a similar
theme.25 Nozick constructs some rather wild counterexamples,
involving computers and other sorts of indestructible beings and imagines
that these can benefit from something or experience harm, thus suggesting
that the points made above about life are certainly not necessarily true.
Therefore, Nozick concludes, the view that the basis of value is the
existence of life is unfounded. If, however, we reject the epistemology
presupposed in such attempted refutations, a lot more than cleverly
imagined counterexamples would be needed to create serious doubt about the
view.26 It is clearly a plausible view and on reflection it
makes very good sense. We in fact judge things to be good and bad, in
connection with not just human life but life in general, based on whether
something flourishes or is aided in its flourishing. Botanists,
zoologists, and physicians clearly use the sort of life at issue as their
standard for judging the goodness or value of particular cases under
consideration—e.g., some tree in a park, some animal in a zoo, or some
patient on the operating table. And the whole array of judgments of good
and bad seem to be grounded on considerations of whether something
contributes to, rather than hinders, the life that is of concern to the
judge.
When we turn to
moral values, it seems evident, again, that a special form of life
gives rise to the topic. In general, we see that being as fully human and
as completely consistent within ourselves as the case makes possible
(i.e., fully integrated) is in our own power, and exercising our power in
the various ways we do is just what gives rise to moral evaluation.27
In the case of human life, whether it goes well or badly—never mind for
the present by what standard—is an issue of personal achievement or
failure, respectively, at least in the bulk of cases. At least where
matters over which persons can exercise control are concerned, their
actions and life, in general, are exposed to moral scrutiny. This category
of goodness, namely, moral goodness (or evil) emerges in conjunction with
the apparently distinctive human capacity for freedom of choice, for then
there can arise the issue of whether a person has chosen to act in
accordance with a standard appropriate for leading a human life. (It
should be noted here that while all this may appear to be wedded to some
absolutist, universalist ethical perspective, once the metaphysical status
of individual human beings is recognized—namely, that “human being” exists
only insofar as there are individuals whose place is best fixed in a
rational scheme of classification by the definition of that concept—it is
possible to show that the standard is not so abstract as it may appear.)
It is the fact (if it is one, which I will not discuss here) that human
beings are self-determined that introduces a distinctive ontological
domain wherein the standard of knowledge—of what something must be to
count as bona fide knowledge—could be different from what it is in others
(e.g., physics, biology, economics.)3° An entity that can cause at least
some of its action, that presupposes a degree of causal agency, really
appears to warrant differentiation from others. Here again, however, the
differentiation need not be understood as some kind of absolutely fixed,
timeless category—the definition of the concept “human being” need not
involve some necessary truth in the formalist sense. This means that it is
not necessarily ruled out that some heretofore nonrational animals will
join the category of beings properly designated as human or that such an
animal will join that category in some significant respect and thus
possibly acquire rights.31
Now we can consider
that the category of moral knowledge may involve what is the case
concerning actions, institutions, decisions, etc., pertaining to human
living and see what form such knowledge might take. If morality involved
standards for conducting a human life, and if human beings are largely
free to choose what they will do, we might have for the facts of morality
a set of hypothetical imperatives rather than categorical truths. If
one is to live one’s (human) life, then one must, in general,
carry on appropriately (consistent with what and who one is). The content
of this hypothetical will depend on facts pertaining to human beings as
such, i.e., human nature, and facts about the individual person in
question. There is no room for a categorical moral judgment here because
whether one is to live a human life is, in the last analysis, a matter
of choice. Granted, such a fundamental choice, if it is to be
coherent, meaningful, and capable of implementation, is itself limited to
either living a human life—for that is what a human being is free to do in
view of being a human being—or not living a human life, that is,
extinction, ceasing to live at all. The former choice, if made, commits a
person (i.e., oneself) to some very general principles of conduct, based
on what it is to be a human being, but leaves much to the determination of
the special circumstances of one’s particular sort of life—age, culture,
sex, talents, capacities, opportunities, etc. The hypothetical imperative
of “If one chooses to live, one must, in general, live as it is fitting
for a human being” can now be filled out a bit by noting that human beings
are, as such, free and rational animals. Their freedom and reason are not,
in fact, separate but related aspects—it is in their capacity to reason
(to reflect and act by judgments, principles, theories that they can
evaluate as sound or unsound) that persons embody their freedom of choice.32
The proper standards for human life, then, must ultimately be related to
the fact that each person is free/rational and a biological entity whose
life is lived well (as a matter of his or her choices, apart from
accidents that cannot be controlled) insofar as it does justice to the
fact of an essential dependence on reasoning and a natural requirement for
biological health.
We will not go beyond
these sketchy remarks to formulate a complete moral theory because the
present discussion needs now to be extended into the public normative
realm, namely politics, and because elsewhere the details of the above
perspective have been developed to a considerable extent. Certainly more
could be said about moral knowledge and its content, but there is no room
for this here.33
V
Much of Western political theory has rested on the conclusion that moral
knowledge is impossible.34 Defenses of liberal democracies have
tended to stress considerations of general welfare and diversity, not the
moral worth of the system or its capacity to give rise to morally good
citizens and morally worthwhile institutions. The common normative theme
of such societies has been the political equality of all persons, a theme
that is then often extended to imply each person’s (at least prima facie)
moral equality. Without the prospect of moral knowledge the only, albeit
very meager, moral message that is plausible is that we are all of equal
worth.
It seems clear that
many Western thinkers, from the time of David Hume to our own, have
equated the possibility of moral knowledge with the entitlement to impose
conformity to that knowledge on others. There is ultimately no logic in
this extension, but a certain prevailing view of the human good has lent
support to it. Both utilitarians and Marxists are intrincisists with
respect to the human good—for the former, the greatest happiness of the
greatest number; for the latter, the fullest realization of human nature
constitutes the human good—and the right course of conduct amounts to
furthering the probability of reaching this human good. Thus, if by chance
making another behave in certain ways can enhance the likelihood of the
realization of this good, then we must institute perhaps even coercive
means to ensure performance of various kinds of appropriate behavior. The
best defense against this threat to moral independence and civil liberties
seems to be to maintain that no one can know what the human good is (or to
maintain that it is relative).35
The main problem with
this approach is that it accepts a false dichotomy between two equally
flawed views. It is false that we cannot know what is morally right, but
it is equally false that knowing it entitles one to force another to
behave accordingly. This is evident enough to most, whatever a philosopher
says. It is clearly enough recognized that moral knowledge does not by
itself entitle us to force another to act according to it. We know in the
case of many people that it is morally bad that they are gluttonous and
morally good that they practice temperance, but we also know that this
alone does not entitle us to force such a person to reform.
The conception of the
good human life implicit in the points raised earlier is different from
the intrincisist view. It is not an end-state that is to be achieved by
living a morally worthwhile life; it is such a life itself that is the
good, and it is choosing to live it that makes it both possible and
morally praiseworthy. Making another live a morally good life is,
in turn, impossible, for the morally good life requires free choice.36 In
contrast, the current concern with the public interest or common good, as
evident in virtually all discussions of morality and public
policy—discussions that too often avoid reference to personal virtues or
character— invokes the end-state approach. This assumes, largely on the
basis of intuitions or considered moral judgments, so called, that certain
states are morally imperative—equality, harmony, family life, chastity,
political stability, employment, safety, security. Then means are
discerned for reaching some combination of such states, regardless of how
these means bear on the personal and moral independence or autonomy of
individual members of society. Such a conception of the public or common
good is questionable and advanced largely independently of the rest of
philosophy.
The metaphysical
necessity of freedom, or self-determination, for living a morally worthy
life based on the rest of the points raised earlier in this essay,
suggests different ways of conceiving of a good community life. Any
community’s basic standards of human intercourse must incorporate a
recognition of the indispensability of a sphere of moral responsibility
for each person. Persons need room to realize themselves through
themselves—that is, need a sphere of authority for reaching the highest
possibility qua the human beings and the individual they are. This
abstract point supports a feature of the Western liberal political
tradition, namely, that the life of the individual is the center of
value—i.e., the common political good—from which the various institutions
of society gain their importance and according to which the legal
framework of a society ought to be devised, reformed, maintained,
protected, and so forth. But when we consider the matter along lines
suggested here, we see that a system of political and economic liberty
that leaves it to individual and cooperative effort morally to secure the
diverse goals of human existence, is not just a next- best system based on
skeptical humility. It is a rational consequence—derived (but not deduced)
from our knowledge of man qua man—of the fact that each person has
a moral task and none other can perform it for him.
There are some
disappointments, of course, with this perspective. For one, nothing so
robust as the total emancipation of humankind or society is demanded in
the political arena, because human beings as such are always free to fail
at their moral tasks of becoming what they should become as human beings
and the individuals they are. Furthermore, it will not be possible, as the
liberal Zeitgeist seems to desire, to proclaim all lifestyles
morally worthy, however politically proper and indispensable it
is that many such lifestyles (namely all that do not involve infringement
of others’ right to liberty) receive the full protection of the law.
What some supporters of
Western values have argued is quite true, and furthermore the truth is not
a result of our inability to know better but our ability to know quite
well. Liberty is the highest political value, the deciding
principle within the public domain. But it is so because it is right for
human beings in one another’s company to refrain from obstructing others’
basic task, namely, to live in dignity, to make for themselves a morally
worthwhile life.
There is nothing
philosophically odd about this point of view, nothing in a reasonable
theory of knowledge that cannot support it as a viable competing
alternative. Furthermore, the approach sketched is comparable to the
approaches of the great political theorists, excepting that the conception
of the good life for man is not idealistic to the point, as under a
prominent interpretation of Plato (and even of Aristotle), of being an
impossible dream. Thus, a task urged upon many Western thinkers may be met
by way of a detailed development of the present approach, namely, to
formulate a comprehensive alternative to the seductive holism of Marxist
ideology without, however, encouraging totalitarianism. Marxism, unlike
the position sketched here, subsumes all normative considerations under
political economy, whereas the present view leaves to individuals (in
their various positions—alone, in families, with friends, with colleagues,
etc.) the task of moral excellence and to political organizations the task
of enabling the individual, in the face of dangers from his fellows, to
carry out this task in peace. This limited conception of government is in
need of moral justification, and the present approach would appear to be a
very hopeful try at that.
VI
The possibility of
objective knowledge that is not reducible to knowledge of one or another
kind of stuff (ideas, sense data) makes possible the introduction of a
means by which the “is/ought” gap may be avoided. The possibility of a
definition of man (or of the concept “human being”) makes possible a
theory of the human moral good that avoids relativism. The fact that this
moral good must be of a very general type, with application to all human
beings, suggests that enormous variety will exist at the numerous less
general normative levels—e.g., what is morally right conduct for senators
in 350 B.C. Athens, what is a proper code for students in a society where
there exists compulsory education, and what scientists should do with
reference to globally destructive weapons, how parents in Central Africa
should rear their children, etc. That the nature of man involves the
freedom to choose one’s conduct given one’s situation, and the
responsibility to do this well, requires that others abstain from coercing
one to act in certain ways—i.e., that they respect political or civil and
economic liberty.
We can only evaluate the case for objectivity in the domain of norms
when we compare it to the case for relativism or skepticism in this
domain. In this respect, we need to be like detectives or scientists and
engage in comparative analysis. The approach advanced here in outline
seems to account for the various needs we have in the area of norms and it
seems, also, to take account of some of the attractive aspects of
different theories. The skeptic is concerned not to cut off further
inquiry, not to get boxed into agreeing to what is not so. The nominalist
wants to account for creativity and evolution. The moral and political
relativist wishes to make room for the enormous diversity in human life,
diversity of which it would be odd to claim that it signifies moral evil.
The position I have sketched here begins to achieve the task of
assimilating these various features. Of course, it will not assimilate all
features. It is better than others, and those who find themselves in
fundamental disagreement with it cannot expect that it will yield to their
position. In this it satisfies the need we have for some stability, for
standards for distinguishing right from wrong.
Some controversial implications of this approach have now been
indicated. Indeed, the present position, with its contextualist
epistemology, its ontological pluralism, and its individualist ethics does
lead to a political system that favors individual rights over collective
goals, the present over the future, and liberty over equality—to give just
a few important results. Unfortunately, a great deal had to be
accomplished in a short space, and giving the position full evaluation at
yet another comparative level requires further work.37
1 By “success” I mean the achievement of prominence in the philosophical
community. For some reflections on why such variation of success has
occurred, see Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1953).
2 In some contexts these terms are interchangeable. But more strictly
considered, the essence of something is what is distinctive about it,
while its nature is what it requires to be. For example, if human beings
are by nature rational animals, they are essentially rational. I am here
concerned with the nature of something, not merely its essence.
3 See John Tienson, “On Analyzing Knowledge,” Philosophical Studies,
25 (May 1974): 289-93 and Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1981), chapter 3.
4 Keith Lehrer, Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1974), p. 6.
5 Ibid., p. 7.
6
Ibid., p. 6.
7
As noted, Lehrer is not alone. Nor is he alone in drawing skeptical
conclusion from the ensuing analysis. See, for example, Peter Unger,
Ignorance (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975).
8 See, for example, Douglas Rasmussen, “Logical Possibility, Iron Bars,
and Necessary Truths,” New Scholasticism, 51 (Winter 1977): 117—
22.
9 J. L. Austin, Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Oxford University
Press,
1961).
10
C.f., Edmund Gettier, Jr., “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”
Analysis, 23 (1963): 121—123.
11 Gilbert Harman, Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1973), p. 145.
12
Barry Stroud, “Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity,” in G. Pitcher,
ed., Wittgenstein (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books, 1966), p. 496.
13
Ibid.
14
This scheme need not be a final, closed one. For the
full view of
definitions invoked here, see Ayn Rand, Introduction to Objectivist
Epistemology (New York: Mentor Books, 1979). But see, Larry Briskman,
“Skinnerism and Pseudo-Science,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences,
9 (1979): 81—103, and see, also, Larry Briskman, “Essentialism Without
Inner Natures?” Philosophy of the Social Sciences (forthcoming)
where our initial reflections are severely criticized from a Popperian
point of view. Many of the points we make here can serve as answers to
this criticism.
15 We have in mind the point that when there is knowledge, as it is
familiar to us in our daily experiences, it is had by someone, somewhere,
at some time.
16 There is also a distinction to be made between counterexamples and
borderline cases. The view that if there are borderline cases, then we
have no justification for adopting a definition as correct assumes,
usually, that definitions are necessary truths. As to the character of
successful counterexamples, see Kenneth S. Lucey, “Counterexamples and
Borderline Cases,” The Personalist, 57 (1976): 351—355. Arthur W.
Collins, “Philosophical Imagination,” American Philosophical Quarterly,
4 (January 1967): 49—56.
17 For example, in the domain of metaphysics, it would turn out that
concepts are defined so that a valid concept must be defined by a
necessary truth, mainly because such a concept will serve in a proposition
that refers to everything, everywhere, at all times, so changes could
spell having to give up the truth of the proposition. The same may hold
for other fundamental fields, e.g., mathematics and logic. Our concepts of
the atom and of cells, however, have undergone considerable change. But it
is not justified to believe that such change entails that the
earlier understanding was wrong.
18 Even a neo-Platonist such as Leo Strauss sees the matter along these
lines, when he says:
Socrates started in his understanding of the natures of things from the
opinions about their natures. For every opinion is based on some
awareness, on some perception with the mind’s eye, of something. Socrates
implied that disregarding the opinions about the natures of things would
amount to abandoning the most important access to reality which we have,
or the most important vestiges of the truth which are within our reach.
(Natural Right and History, pp. 123- 124.)
The problem with Socrates seems to me to have been his extreme reliance on
a method of comparing and contrasting such opinions. This method seems to
have been based, in part, on the acceptance of the participants’ goodwill.
Still, this engagement of the opinions of attentive people seems justified
because it is first of all through the immediate encounter of reality that
we sort things out and begin to take more interest in some things than in
others. Thus, Plato has Socrates consider many problems by embarking on
the construction of solutions with the aid of loyal pupils, whereas,
observes Leo Strauss in The City and Man (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1964), “in the conversation between Socrates and
Thrasymachus, justice is treated in a bantering and hence unjust manner
(since) Thrasymachus . . . does not take seriously the virtue under
discussion” (p. 85).
19
Descartes exemplifies this unfortunate approach, in my view, and his
influence seems to be responsible, in large measure, for subsequent trends
in epistemology. It is Kant’s continuation of the trend set by Descartes
that provoked Nietzsche to lament the philosopher’s approach to truth. See
Freidrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufman
(New York: Vintage Books, 1966).
20
See David Kelly, Evidence of the Senses
(Princeton University: Unpublished doctoral dissertation, 1978). See also
Thomas A. Russman, “Selective Perception,” Reason Papers, No. 7
(Spring 1981): 21—32.
21 It is the formalism of these philosophers, in their discussion of
their respective fields, that I am calling attention to here.
22 Among others, B. F. Skinner feels the need to do this in Science
and Human Behavior (New York: Macmillan Publishing Co., 1953), p. 429.
23
Mark Platt, Ways of Meaning (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1979), chapter 10, and Reference, Truth and Reality (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980), chapter 4.
24 Only what is extinguishable can be the beneficiary of something— a
process, thing, prospect---that might prolong its existence. Apart from
the life of some organism, nothing else is extinguishable, only
transformable, so that only life can experience what is of value to it, of
benefit to it. A somewhat more elaborate way of putting this can be found
in Ayn Rand, The Virtue of Selfishness (New York: Signer Books,
1964), p. 20ff. The point is developed fully in Douglas Den Uyl and
Douglas Rasmussen, “Nozick on the Randian Argument,” The Personalist,
59 (April 1978): 108—205. In the present discussion we wish merely to
indicate that value or goodness or benefit makes its appearance with the
emergence of the ontological domain of living things for which something
can be of value, good, of benefit, etc.
25
Robert Nozick, “On the Randian Argument,” The Personalist, 52
(Spring 1971): 282-304. But see, Den Uyl and Rasmussen, “Nozick on the
Randian Argument.”
26
Here is where an account of “logically possible” is crucial, since mere
imaginability is often accepted as showing logical possibility, so that
when some counterexample is taken to be logically possible, it is argued
that from a logical point of view a conclusion cannot be maintained. See
my “A Note on Conceivability and Logical Possibility,” Kinesis, 2
(Fall 1969): 39—42.
27 I discuss this in more detail in my A Primer on Ethics (Santa
Barbara, Calif.: Reason Press, 1982).
28 In other words, given that human beings are necessarily individuals
existing sometimes and somewhere, the general principles of morality and
politics will probably apply to them quite differently, depending on the
facts they face in their lives.
29
See Roger W. Sperry, “Changing Concepts of Consciousness and Free
Will,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, (August 1976): 9—19.
30 This position mirrors, in the metaphysical sphere, the epistemological
pluralism we find in Stephen Toulmin, The Uses of Argument
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958). We mean just that in
various contexts the criterion of knowledge will be different from what it
is in others.
31 Many philosophers argue for animal rights today. My acceptance of the
fact that it may not be ruled out that animals will have rights is not the
same as endorsing their views. (For there to be animal rights, animals
would have to be able to choose between exercising or not exercising their
rights, something that is not now in evidence.)
32 I develop this point in my The Pseudo-Science of B. F. Skinner
(New Rochelle, New York: Arlington House, 1974).
33 I say a bit more in my “A Reconsideration of Natural Rights Theory,”
American Philosophical Quarterly, 19 (January 1982): 61—72.
34 For example, see Karl Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1963).
35
For example, Larry Briskman, “Skinnerism and Pseudo-Science,”
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 2 (May 1979): 81—103. Cf., Ranford
Bambrough, Moral Skepticism and Moral Knowledge (Atlantic High,
N.J.: Humanities Press, 1979).
36 For a more developed discussion, see Douglas Den Uyl,
“Freedom and Virtue,” in T. R. Machan, ed., The Libertarian Reader
(Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1982).
37
I wish to thank the Earhart Foundation for support for some of the work
on this paper. My colleague Randall Dipert and the editor of The Review
of Metaphysics have given generous help toward the improvement of an
earlier draft, as has Marty Zupan.
Return to Tibor R. Machan
Page