From
On the Use of
Philosophy: Three Essays by Jacques Maritain, Princeton University
Press, 1961, 24-29.
Can
Philosophers Cooperate?
Jacques Maritain
Some years ago I was asked whether in my opi-nion
philosophers can cooperate. I felt rather embar-rassed by this
question, for on the one hand if philosophy is not a search for truth it
is nothing, and truth admits of no compromise; on the other hand if
philosophers, that is, lovers of wisdom, cannot coop-erate, how will any
human cooperation be possible? The fact that philosophical
discussions seem to con-sist of deaf men's quarrels is not reassuring
for civilization.
My answer is that philosophers do not
cooperate, as a rule, because human nature is as weak in them as in any
other poor devil of a rational animal, but that they can
cooperate; and that cooperation bet-ween philosophers can only be a
conquest of the intellect over itself and the very universe of thought
it has created—a
difficult conquest indeed, achieved by intellectual rigor and justice on
the basis of irreducible and inevitably lasting antagonisms.
A distinction, moreover, seems to me
to be relevant in this connection. The question can be considered
either from the point of view of doctrinal exchanges between
systems or from the point of view of the mutual grasp which
various philosophical systems can have of each other, each being taken
as a whole.
From the first point of view, or the
point of view of doctrinal exchanges, each system can avail itself of
the others for its own sake by dismembering them, and by feeding on and
assimilating what it can take from them. That is cooperation
indeed, but in quite a peculiar sense—as
a lion cooperates with a lamb.
Yet from the second point of view,
and in the perspective of the judgment which each system passes on the
other, contemplating it as a whole, and as an object situated in an
external sphere, and trying to do it justice, a mutual understanding is
possible which cannot indeed do away with basic antagonisms, but which
may create a kind of real though imperfect cooperation, to the extent
that each system succeeds (1) in recognizing for the other, in a certain
sense, a right to exist; and (2) in availing itself of the other, no
longer by material intussusception and by borrowing or digesting
parts of the other, but by bringing, thanks to the other, its own
specific life and principles to a higher degree of achievement and
extension.
It is on this genuine kind of
cooperation that I would like to insist for a moment.
If we were able to realize that most
often our mutually opposed affirmations do not bear on the same parts or
aspects of the real and that they are of greater value than our mutual
negations, then we should come nearer the first prerequisite of a
genuinely philosophical understanding: that is, we should become better
able to transcend and conquer our own system of signs and conceptual
language, and to take on for a moment, in a provisional and tentative
manner, the thought and approach of the other so as to come back, with
this intelligible booty, to our own philosophical conceptualization and
to our own system of reference.
Then, we are no longer concerned with
analyzing or sorting the set of assertions peculiar to various
systems in spreading them out, so to speak, on a single surface or level
in order to examine what conciliation or exchange of ideas they may
mutually allow in their inner structure. But we are concerned with
taking into account a third dimension, in order to examine the manner in
which each system, con-sidered as a specific whole, can, according to
its own frame of reference, do justice to the other in taking a view of
it and seeking to penetrate it as an object situated on the outside—in
another sphere of thought.
From this standpoint, two
considerations would appear all-important: the one is the consideration
of the central intuition which lies at the core of each great
philosophical doctrine; the other is the consideration of the place
which each system could, according to its own frame of reference,
grant the other system as the legitimate place the latter is cut out to
occupy in the universe of thought.
Actually, each great philosophical
doctrine lives on a central intuition which can be wrongly
concep-tualized and translated into a system of assertions seriously
deficient or erroneous as such, but which, insofar as it is intellectual
intuition, truly gets hold of some aspect of the real. Consequently,
each great philosophical doctrine, once it has been grasped in its
central intuition and then re-interpreted in the frame of reference of
another doctrine (in a manner that it would surely not accept), should
be granted from the point of view of this other doctrine some place
considered as legitimately occupied, be it in some imaginary universe.
If we try to do justice to the
philosophical sys-tems against which we take our most determined stand,
we shall seek to discover both that intuition which they involve and
that place we must grant them from our own point of view. Then we shall
benefit from them, not by borrowing from them or exchanging with them
certain particular views and ideas, but by seeing, thanks to them, more
pro-foundly into our own doctrine, by enriching it from within and
extending its principles to new fields of inquiry which have been
brought more forcefully to our attention, but which we shall make all
the more vitally and powerfully informed by these principles.
Thus there is not toleration
between systems—a
system cannot tolerate another system, because systems are
abstract sets of ideas and have only intellectual existence, where the
will to tolerate or not to tolerate has no part—but
there can be justice, intellectual justice, between philosophical
systems.
Between philosophers there can be
tolerance and more than tolerance; there can be a kind of cooperation
and fellowship, founded on intellectual justice and the philosophical
duty of understanding another's thought in a genuine and fair manner.
Nay more, there is no intellectual justice without the assistance of
intellectual charity. If we do not love the thought and intellect
of another as intellect and thought, how shall we take pains to discover
what truths are conveyed by it while it seems to us defective or
misguided, and at the same time to free these truths from the errors
which prey upon them and to re-instate them in an entirely true
systematization? Thus we love truth more than we do our
fellow-philosophers, but we love and respect both.