From
Human Action, Yale
University Press, pp. 582-586. I post this because it refutes a
common charge made by philosophical critics of unhampered markets to whom I
otherwise owe much. (See, for example, my prefatory comments to Bernard Lonergan’s
“Bias, Liberation, and Cosmopolis”
elsewhere on this site.) The whole text of Human Action is
available online at
Mises.org.
The
Errors of Anti-market “Disproportionality” Doctrines
Ludwig von Mises
Guided by the Marxian
slogan “anarchy of production,” the present-day nonmonetary cycle
doctrines explain the cyclical fluctuations of trade in terms of a
tendency, allegedly inherent in the capitalist economy, to develop
disproportionality in the size of investments made in various branches of
industry. Yet even these disproportionality doctrines do not contest the
fact that every businessman is eager to avoid such mistakes, which must
bring him serious financial losses. The essence of the activities of
entrepreneurs and capitalists is precisely not to embark upon projects
which they consider unprofitable. If one assumes that there prevails a
tendency for businessmen to fail in these endeavors, one implies that all
businessmen are short-sighted. They are too dull to avoid certain
pitfalls, and thus blunder again and again in their conduct of affairs.
The whole of society has to foot the bill for the shortcomings of the
thick-headed speculators, promoters, and entrepreneurs.
Now it is obvious that
men are fallible, and businessmen are certainly not free from this human
weakness. But one should not forget that on the market a process of
selection is in continual operation. There prevails an unceasing tendency
to weed out the less efficient entrepreneurs, that is, those who fail in
their endeavors to anticipate correctly the future demands of the
consumers. If one group of entrepreneurs produces commodities in excess
of the demand of the consumers and consequently cannot sell these goods at
remunerative prices and suffers losses, other groups who produce those
things for which the public scrambles make all the greater profits. Some
sectors of business are distressed while others thrive. No general
depression of trade can emerge.
But the proponents of
the doctrines we have to deal with argue differently. They assume that
not only the whole entrepreneurial class but all of the people are struck
with blindness. As the entrepreneurial class is not a closed social order
to which access is denied to outsiders, as every enterprising man is
virtually in a position to challenge those who already belong to the class
of entrepreneurs, as the history or capitalism provides innumerable
examples of penniless newcomers who brilliantly succeeded in embarking
upon the production of those goods which according to their own judgment
were fitted to satisfy the most urgent needs of consumers, the assumption
that all entrepreneurs regularly fall prey to certain errors tacitly
implies that all practical men lack intelligence. It implies that nobody
who is engaged in business and nobody who considers engaging in business
if some opportunity is offered to him by the shortcomings of those already
engaged in it, is shrewd enough to understand the real state of the
market. But on the other hand the theorists, who are not themselves
active in the conduct of affairs and merely philosophize about other
people’s actions, consider themselves smart enough to discover the
fallacies leading astray those doing business. These omniscient
professors are never deluded by the errors which cloud the judgment of
everyone else. They know precisely what is wrong with private enterprise.
Their claims to be invested with dictatorial powers to control business
are therefore fully justified.
The most amazing thing
about these doctrines is that they furthermore imply that businessmen, in
their littleness of mind, obstinately cling to their erroneous procedures
in spite of the fact that the scholars have long since unmasked their
faults. Although every textbook explodes them, the businessmen cannot help
repeating them. There is manifestly no means to prevent the recurrence of
economic depression other than to entrust—in accordance with Plato’s
utopian ideas—supreme power to the philosophers.
Let us examine briefly
the two most popular varieties of these disproportionality doctrines.
There is first the
durable goods doctrine. These goods retain their serviceableness for some
time. As long as their life period lasts, the buyer who has acquired a
piece abstains from replacing it by the purchase of a new one. Thus, once
all people have made their purchases, the demand for new products
dwindles. Business becomes bad. A revival is possible only when, after
the lapse of some time, the old houses, cars, refrigerators, and the like
are worn out, and their owners must buy new ones.
However, businessmen
are as a rule more provident than this doctrine assumes. They are intent
upon adjusting the size of their production to the anticipated size of
consumers’ demand. The bakers take account of the fact that every day a
housewife needs a new loaf of bread, and the manufacturers of coffins take
into account the fact that the total annual sale of coffins cannot exceed
the number of people deceased during this period. The machine industry
reckons with the average “life” of its products no less than do the
tailors, the shoemakers, the manufacturers of motorcars, radio sets, and
refrigerators, and the construction firms. There are, to be sure, always
promoters who in a mood of deceptive optimism are prone to overexpand
their enterprises. In the pursuit of such projects they snatch away
factors of production from other plants of the same industry and from
other branches of industry. Thus their overexpansion results in a
relative restriction of output in other fields. One branch goes on
expanding while others shrink until the unprofitability of the former and
the profitability of the latter rearranges conditions. Both the preceding
boom and the following slump concern only a part of business.
The second variety of
these disproportionality doctrines is known as the acceleration principle.
A temporary rise in the demand for a certain commodity results in
increased production of the commodity concerned. If demand later drops
again, the investments made for this expansion of production appear as
malinvestments. This becomes especially pernicious in the field of
durable producers’ goods. If the demand for the consumers’ good a
increases by 10 per cent, business increases the equipment p
required for its production by 10 per cent. The resulting rise in the
demand for p is the more momentous in proportion to the previous
demand for p, the longer the duration of serviceableness of a piece
of p is and the smaller consequently the previous demand for the
replacement of worn-out pieces of p was. If the life of a piece of
p is 10 years, the annual demand for p for replacement was
10 per cent of the stock of p previously employed by the industry.
The rise of 10 per cent in the demand for a doubles therefore the
demand for p and results in a 100 per cent expansion in the
equipment r needed for the production of p. If then the
demand for a stops increasing, 50 per cent of the production
capacity of r remains idle. If the annual increase in the demand
for a drops from 10 per cent to 5 per cent, 25 per cent of the
production capacity of r cannot be used.
The fundamental error of this doctrine is that it considers
entrepreneurial activities as a blindly automatic response to the
momentary state of demand. Whenever demand increases and renders a branch of business more
profitable, production facilities are supposed instantly to expand in
proportion. This view is untenable. Entrepreneurs often err. They pay
heavily for their errors. But whoever acted in the way the acceleration
principle describes would not be an entrepreneur, but a soulless
automaton. Yet the real entrepreneur is a speculator, a man eager
to utilize his opinion about the future structure of the market for
business operations promising profits. This specific anticipative
understanding of the conditions of the uncertain future defies any rules
and systematization. It can be neither taught nor learned. If it were
different, everybody could embark upon entrepreneurship with the same
prospect of success. What distinguishes the successful entrepreneur and
promoter from other people is precisely the fact that he does not let
himself be guided by what was and is, but arranges his affairs on the
ground of his opinion about the future. He sees the past and the present
as other people do; but he judges the future in a different way. In his
actions he is directed by an opinion about the future which deviates from
those held by the crowd. The impulse of his actions is that he appraises
the factors of production and the future prices of the commodities which
can be produced out of them in a different way from other people. If the
present structure of prices renders very profitable the business of those
who are today selling the articles concerned, their production will expand
only to the extent that entrepreneurs believe that the favorable market
constellation will last long enough to make new investments pay. If
entrepreneurs do not expect this, even very high profits of the
enterprises already operation will not bring about an expansion. It is
exactly this reluctance of the capitalists and entrepreneurs to invest in
lines which they consider unprofitable that is violently criticized by
people who do not comprehend the operation of the market economy.
Technocratically minded engineers complain that the supremacy of the
profit motive prevents consumers from being amply supplied with all those
goods with which technological knowledge could provide them. Demagogues
cry out against the greed of capitalists intent upon preserving scarcity.
A satisfactory
explanation of business fluctuations must not be built upon the fact that
individual firms or groups of firms misjudge the future state of the
market and therefore make bad investments. The objective of the trade
cycle is the general upswing of business activities, the propensity
to expand production in all branches of industry, and the following
general depression. These phenomena cannot be brought about by the
fact that increased profits in some branches of business result in their
expansion and a corresponding overproportional investment in the
industries manufacturing the equipment needed for such an expansion.
It is a very well known
fact that the more the boom progresses, the harder it becomes to buy
machines and other equipment. The plants producing these things are
overloaded with orders. Their customers must wait a long time until the
machines ordered are delivered. This clearly shows that the producers’
goods industries are not so quick in the expansion of their own production
facilities as the acceleration principle assumes.
But even if, for the
sake of argument, we were ready to admit that capitalists and
entrepreneurs behave in the way the disproportionality doctrines describe,
it remains inexplicable how they could go on in the absence of credit
expansion. The striving after such additional investments raises the
prices of the complementary factors of production and the rate of interest
on the loan market. These effects would curb the expansionist tendencies
very soon if there were no credit expansion.
The supporters of the
disproportionality doctrines refer to certain occurrences in the field of
farming as a confirmation of their assertion concerning the inherent lack
of provision on the part of private business. However, it is
impermissible to demonstrate characteristic features of free competitive
enterprise as operation in the market economy by pointing to conditions in
the sphere of medium-size and small farming. In many countries this
sphere is institutionally removed from the supremacy of the market and the
consumers. Government interference is eager to protect the farmer against
the vicissitudes of the market. These farmers do not operate in a free
market; they are privileged and pampered by various devices. The orbit of
their production activities is a reservation, as it were, in which
technological backwardness, narrow-minded obstinacy, and entrepreneurial
inefficiency are artificially preserved at the expense of the
nonagricultural strata of the people. If they blunder in their conduct of
affairs, the government forces the consumers, the taxpayers, and the
mortgagees to foot the bill.
It is true that there
is such a thing as the corn-hog cycle and analogous happenings in
the production of other farm products. But the recurrence of such cycles
is due to the fact that the penalties which the market applies against
inefficient and clumsy entrepreneurs do not affect a great part of the
farmers. These farmers are not answerable for their actions because they
are the pet children of governments and politicians. If it were not so,
they would long since have gone bankrupt and their former farms would be
operated by more intelligent people.