From International Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 17, 1977,
59-93. Father Moleski’s master's thesis was on Isaye, his Ph.D.
dissertation on Newman’s “illative sense” and Polanyi’s “tacit
knowledge.” I encourage visits to Moleski’s
site.
Re-reading a 2007 e-mail exchange with Bill Vallicella reminded me that
it was he who alerted me to Moleski's paper after having read my
“Ayn Rand's Use of Retortion.”
After two years I am more inclined to think that retortion is as logically
powerful as it is rhetorically delightful. David Ray Griffin, for
example, following a precept of Whitehead’s, argues that
we inevitably presuppose
a number of
“hardcore commonsense
beliefs” in our practice, beliefs that we would implicitly reaffirm in
any attempt to deny them. Retortion also informs the metaphysics of
Bernard
Lonergan
(see his notion of the reversible “counter-position,” e.g., Insight,
Ch. XIV, section I) and the
argumentation ethics
of Hans-Hermann Hoppe as well as the distinctive but complementary
effort of
Frank van Dun.
In short, retortion is a point of connection among several philosophical traditions explored on this site.
After noting this post,
Vallicella's generated a com-plementary one of his own,
“Retortion
and the Existence of Truth.”
I thank him for making it
complimentary to this site as well.
Anthony Flood
July 27, 2009
Retortion: The Method and Metaphysics of Gaston Isaye
Martin X. Moleski, S.J.
Introduction
The purpose of this article is to present in synthesis the main lines of
philosophical thought of Gaston Isaye, a Belgian Jesuit professor of
philosophy at the Facultés Universitaires de Namur, now retired after a
lifetime of teaching. Although the keenness and originality of his
philosophical insights have long been appreciated by generations of
students and by the readers of his numerous articles, he has never
written a book nor have his articles ever been collected for convenient
reference, hence his thought is little known outside a small circle of
professionals, and almost not at all outside of Europe. Yet his main
contribution to philosophy is one that should be of special interest to
contemporary thinkers: it is the systematic use of the method known as
“retortion” for establishing and vindicating the fundamental set of
positions constituting the core of the various philosophical
disciplines, such as metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of God,
philosophy of man, and philosophy of science. The problem of how to
establish and argue the basic assumptions of a philosophical position or
system without circularity or infinite regress has proved to be one of
peculiar difficulty and yet central importance in philosophical
discussion today, highly sensitive as it is to questions of methodology.
The unique solution to this impasse worked out by Isaye seems to us,
therefore, worthy of serious attention by a wider circle of readers.
This article will discuss Isaye’s work from two main points of view:
first, the nature of his method and its historical context; secondly,
the conclusions to which he has come through the application of the
method in the various areas of philosophy, grouped under Metaphysics and
Epistemology.1
I. The Methodology of Gaston Isaye
Retortion and Transcendental Thomism
Isaye is a disciple of another Jesuit philosopher, Joseph Maréchal
(1878-1944). In the decade of the 1920’s, Maréchal published four
volumes of a planned six-volume study entitled Le Point de Depart de
ta Métaphysique. In the course of this discussion of the
starting-point of metaphysics, Maréchal works out the integration of
Kant’s transcendental critique of knowledge and the metaphysics of St.
Thomas Aquinas. From the standpoint of Thomism he shows why the denial
of metaphysics is self-defeating, and from the standpoint of Kant’s own
critique he shows that the affirmation of metaphysics is an inescapable
necessity of thought.2 Those who have followed Maréchal in
this synthesis of two great philosophies have been called
“Transcendental Thomists.” Although not all the philosophers who might
be grouped under this title would endorse it fully, the term does help
to identify a significant style of thought within the last fifty years
or so.3
Since Isaye’s method derives from Aristotle, Aquinas, Kant, and Marechal,
it seems fair to identify him as a Transcendental Thomist. Isaye begins
by observing that it is impossible to avoid the question of the
justification of knowledge. If reason is not self-critical, it is no
better than dogmatism, supersti-tion, or idle speculation.4
However, it is clear from the disagreements of philosophers that the
right criteria of knowledge are not given to us as Cartesian ideas. Isaye
suggests that in order to answer the critical question we should try to
adopt a hyper-critical position. By “hypercritical” he means the most
skeptical position we can imagine. Starting with the most extreme
criticism of thought as an experiment will lead us to some definite
conclusions about knowledge.
Suppose that the best way to test basic assumptions is to follow the
maxim, “Take nothing for granted—accept only what is proven to be
certain.” If this were the authentic criterion of knowledge, we would
have to conclude that we can know nothing: if nothing is to be taken for
granted, we cannot take for granted that this is the criterion of
knowledge, nor can we take for granted that we know how to apply it even
if it is. We may not appeal to any sense experience, intuition,
induction or deduction—all of these are placed in doubt by the
hypercritical assumption.5 If this is the authentic
criterion, we must all become skeptics and deny that there is any
knowledge, or we must become dogmatists and say that no explanation can
be given for our knowledge.
It is at this point that Isaye introduces the method of argument called
“retortion.”6 It seems clear that we cannot offer a formal
proof of the first principles of human thought. Either we will beg the
question or become committed to an infinite regression of justifying
arguments. On the other hand, if anyone tries to adopt the
hypercritical position in order to deny that we have any knowledge,
Isaye answers them with a retort: if what the skeptic says were true,
then he never could know that we are wrong; if it were true that there
is no knowledge, no one could ever say they knew that we can know
nothing. In the very act of denying knowledge, the skeptic makes a
knowledge claim. Retortion is the process of pointing out such an
inconsistency between a claim and the act of making the claim.
The experiment in hypercriticism yields two important results. We learn
first that it is impossible to deny that, at the very least, we know
something. If anyone tries to deny that we have some kind of
understanding of the way things are, he involves himself in a conflict
between his claim (“We don’t know any truth”) and his action (claiming
to know our ignorance of the truth). To have a valid objection, the
skeptic must admit that he understands the position he is criticizing,
that he knows what he wants to say, and that his position is closer to
the truth than the one he criticizes—otherwise we may charge him with
missing the point or with not knowing what he is talking about. If he
persists in advancing his opinion, he simply undercuts his position more
and more by making more and more claims to different kinds of knowledge.7
The second important result of this experiment is that we have developed
a method by which the “conditions of the possibility of thought”8
can be identified and defended against attack. If there are universal
necessities of thought, they must be present somehow in the formation of
any particular thought or expression of thought. We may claim to have
found such a necessity if its denial involves us in contradiction
between the denial and the act of making the denial. If the denial of a
principle in question does not lead to this kind of contradiction,
then—no matter what else the statement might be—it is clearly not a
first principle of thought, for it has not entered into the makeup of
the denial.
Retortion is essentially a process of recognizing inconsistency in a
philosophical position. It results in the judgment that no person could
adopt such a position without becoming involved in a kind of
self-contradiction. This places it in the genre of ad hominem
arguments, although “the Homo in question is every Homo,
every human being.”9 An argument which is subject to
retortion is rejected because no one can adopt it consistently, not
simply because the argument is inconsistent with a particular person’s
beliefs. Since it is implicitly concerned with all men, retortion can
lead us to a universally valid statement about the nature of man and the
nature of being.10
Maréchal makes an important observation on the logical status of the
argument:
Let us admit it, however: the logical contradiction, which we invoke
here as a sanction against any rejection of the absolute exigencies of
the affirmation, is not directly a formal contradiction between
conceptual terms (a contradiction in terms), but a contra-diction between
that which is implicit and explicit in a judgment. Besides, a
merely logical contradiction “in the terms,” indepen-dently of any more
or less concealed positing, affirming or presupposing, would be unable
to yield us (possible or actual) reality on the rebound. He who tries
to demonstrate the ab-solute necessity of being merely and exclu-sively by
analyzing concepts—even through a logical analysis of the idea of
nothingness—would commit the typical error of the ontological argument
or of the Cartesian rationalistic postulate.11
Isaye insists on the fact that this kind of self-contradiction does not
just leave us poised and undecided about which position the skeptic is
in. When anyone does something which they themselves have said to be
impossible, it is clear that their theory is wrong. Whoever denies a
first principle of thought will concede that same principle by their
action of making and communicating a judgment.12 The
ramifications of this will become clear when we examine specific cases
of retortion in the second part of this article.
Isaye claims that through retortion we can come to affirm necessary
truths about our relationship to transcendental realities (being, truth,
and goodness). Retortion does this by showing us that there is an inner
structure to our life which underpins all thought:
The first truths cannot be established by argument: the starting point
of such an argument would have to be some truths which would be anterior
to the first truths, which would be a contradiction in terms. Outside
of argument we have only a single way of knowledge available to us:
intuition. The first truths will be intuitive or they will not be
known; in the latter case, we will never know anything.13
It is important to note that Isaye is not saying that these intuitions
are self-justifying through some kind of psychological impact. Instead,
we realize that there is simply no way to do without them since every
possible denial involves us in a position subject to retortion. Nor is
he saying that this intuition provides us with an infallible
illumination or with wholly formed concepts. He speaks rather of a deep
experience of our inner orientation toward the truth which is difficult
to articulate but which is nevertheless the real root of all of our
striving to know and to speak. Retortion makes us aware of the fact
that our intellect is always poised toward the truth by its very nature.
It is our undeniable nature as human knowers which ultimately justifies
our claim to know that we can know.
What Isaye calls intuition is very closely related to what Joseph
Donceel, a long-time friend of Isaye and practicer of the method of
retortion, calls “necessary affirmation”:
For Transcendental Thomism affirmation is the keystone of metaphysics,
and therefore of all human thought and activity. Maréchal called it
“Man’s substitute for intellectual intuition.” We have no intuition of
our basic certitudes. We do not see that or why they are true. We do
not see that or why some of our knowledge is absolutely certain, that or
why every event has a cause, that or why the Illimited Being exists.
But we cannot not affirm it.14
It is clear that the kind of intuition which Maréchal and Donceel wish
to deny is not the kind of intuition to which Isaye refers. Retortion
shows us that we cannot deny the basic structure of human life;
therefore, we must affirm our natural dispositions toward knowing which
are present to us intuitively, i.e., which are constitutive of the very
fabric of our intellectual life.
In short, retortion works because it is a fact of our human nature that
we are knowers and that being is in some way intelligible to us. We do
not possess this fact; it possesses us and forms the ground of every act
of the person. We do not see this first fact, but we come to recognize
by retortion that we see all things only through its activity within us.
Retortion in Other Philosophies
Retortion is not the private property of Transcendental Thomists. It is
an argument which dates back to Aristotle’s defense of his principle of
identity and non-contradiction which he presents in the fourth book of
his Metaphysics. It has been used, consciously or unconsciously,
by generations of philosophers who have struggled to articulate truths
which are too close to us to be clear and distinct. Norris Clarke notes
that this method can be recognized in the work of Wittgenstein,
Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and other existential phenomeno-logists as well
as in the work of Maréchal, Rahner, Coreth, Lonergan, Donceel, and other
Transcendental Thomists.15 Joseph M. Boyle, Jr.—who uses the
argument himself—reports that it has been used to “refute skepticism,
behaviorism, pragmatism, intuitionism, and the coherence theory,” as
well as “to defend versions of idealism and utilitarianism.”16
Before considering the details of Isaye’s thought, let us look at
some of these other uses of retortion. This will help us to recognize
the importance of his philosophy to other contemporary, non-Thomist
schools of thought.
Retortion is a significant part of the history of analytic and
linguistic philosophy, although philoso-phers in this tradition have
never called it by this name. They have explored “performative
contradic-tions” (which are the necessary condition of making a sound retortion), “denial of a form of life” (which is similar to the reason
Isaye gives for the ground of self-contradiction), “charging categorial
nonsense,” or “committing self-referential inconsistency.” G. E. Moore
used a kind of retortion in 1925, one year before the publication of
Maréchal’s Fifth Cahier, as a way of establishing the claims of
common sense against the critique of the more skeptical empiricists:
In other words, the proposition that some propositions belonging to each
of these classes are true is a proposition which has the peculiarity
that, if any philosopher has ever denied it, it follows from the fact
that he has denied it, that he must have been wrong in denying it.
The strange thing is that philosophers should have been able to hold
sincerely, as part of their philosophical creed, propositions
incon-sistent with what they themselves knew to be true; and yet, so far
as I can make out, this has really happened.17
Wittgenstein picked up this style of approach from Moore, and it
apparently became the starting-point for his reflections, On
Certainty, which were pub-lished posthumously,18 as well
as for many of the points made in his Philosophical Investigations,
particularly in his attacks on the Cartesian starting-point, the
solitary thinker.19 H. H. Price uses the argument very
deftly to point out four ways in which we come to practical and useful
knowledge; his defense of memory claims is a good illustration of his
technique:
Whenever we claim to remember something, it is conceivable that we might
be misremem-bering. In that case, how can we know anything about the
past at all?
Now there is something wrong with this argument. It cannot ever be
stated unless we assume that some of our claims to memory are correct,
that sometimes when we claim to remember we are really remembering and
not mis-remembering. How do we know that memory claims are ever made at
all? Because we remember making them ourselves and remember hearing
others speak as if they were making them. And how do we know that some
of these memory claims were incorrect? Because we are able, somehow, to
find out what the facts about the past actually were, we ourselves must
rely on memory at some point or other.20
The most outstanding example of retortion’s efficacy in establishing a
solid foundation for philosophy cannot be attributed to anyone man.
When the Logical Positivists began to claim that the Verification
Principle was the standard of all true knowledge, they were shortly
confronted with the retort that the Principle could not meet its own
standard: “hence, the highly embarrassing conse-quence that the
verification principle was itself meaningless.”21
None of these philosophers uses retortion in exactly the same way that
Isaye does. Probably all of them would be uneasy at the lengths to
which the argument as used by Isaye can lead us. Nevertheless, it is
important to recognize that the form of the argument is very much the
same: “If what you said were true, you could not have said what you did;
you did, in fact, say what you said; therefore, what you said is false.”
The major of this syllogism is given by an insight (or intuition in the
sense in which Isaye uses the word) into the nature of language, human
nature, and reality. This insight cannot be denied because every denial
simply re-afflrms its importance (e.g., we can only deny memory claims
by using our memory; therefore, we cannot discredit memory universally).
The method of Gaston Isaye, then, is highly relevant to Thomists and
non-Thomists alike.
Retortion and Self-Referential Inconsistency
Two philosophers who recently have made extensive use of this argument
are Germain Grisez and his student, Joseph M. Boyle, Jr. Grisez
directed Boyle’s doctoral dissertation, “The Argument from
Self-Referential Consistency: The Current Discus-sion,”22 and
Grisez has recently published two books which depend heavily on this
argument.23 For the most part, their interpretation of the
structure and value of the argument is remarkably consonant with Isaye’s.
However, there seem to be two areas of significant difference between
the two positions.
In more than a dozen different places in his doctoral dissertation,
Boyle insists that retortion (what he would call self-refutation or the
argument from self-refutation) cannot be used to ground a positive
statement about reality because its nature is simply to warrant the
denial of a self-referentially inconsistent position; e.g., he says:
Both [Urban and Weiss] seek to use this argument to establish general
affirmative statements. It cannot do this. It can only falsify general
statements, as well, of course, as any other self-referential
statements. The argument terminates either in a singular statement or a
negative generalization. In other words, this argument cannot be used
to establish a system of affirmative general philosophical theses.24
This marks a major difference between Boyle and Isaye in terms of their
understanding of how the argument works and what we can learn through
it. Boyle argues that the argument “is based not on an insight into
what knowledge or being positively is, but only on the performative
inconsistency of the position under attack,”25 and therefore
“does not give any understanding of the subject matter.”26 Isaye,
as was pointed out above, contends that we do come to possess explicitly
what is only implicit in all acts of judgment, and thus are justified in
making general statements. The condition of the possibility of making a
sound retortion is that we know something—every negation involves a
complex affirmation of our relationship to each other and to all being.
Retortion shows the impossibility of denying necessary affirmations;
therefore, indirectly, it leads us to assent to them. On Isaye’s
account, it is virtually impossible that an adequate understanding of
retortion should fail to spell out the general outlines of a sound
metaphysical position.27
Isaye contends that there are universal principles which govern all of
human thought and which we can come to recognize explicitly through
retortion. These principles are constitutive of human nature, a kind of
a priori orientation in virtue of which all judgments are made. Grisez
does not recognize such universal principles as constitutive of all our
judgments; instead, he discusses “rationality norms”:
Since rationality norms are not laws of thought, one can choose to
violate them . . . .
“Be reasonable” is
very like a moral demand, if it is not precisely a moral demand.
Rationality norms are very like a code of ethics for asking questions,
arguing, judging. Some-one who violates them cannot be convicted of
self-contradiction for violating them, because rationality norms direct
all and only the moves which admit of choice, and one who is face to
face with an inconsistency no longer has a choice.28
Grisez speaks of the rationality norms as being shaped by experience.29
Isaye would answer that the first principles of thought are the
condition of all human experience, even though it is perfectly clear
that their recognition and articulation require a historical
development. Isaye does not deny that there is an element of freedom in
the pursuit of knowledge—in fact, he uses this insight to ground his
discussion of the human soul—but he would want to hold that there are
indeed laws of thought which can only be violated on pain of
contradiction between word and deed. If there are not these laws of
thought, then one has no grounds for making a moral demand on
others—everyone is free to think whatever he pleases. That there are
such laws of thought in no way diminishes the responsibility of the
knower to choose what is right. We can confront a person with an
inconsistency through retortion precisely because there are universal
principles of thought, but it is up to that person then to choose
whether to resolve the inconsistency or not.30
Despite Boyle’s reservations about how far one can go with the argument
from self-refutation, he recognizes that it has an important role to
play:
To sum up, it is
possible to do metaphysics with self-referential arguments as a basic
strategy. It is hard to guess what such a metaphysics would look like
since no one has as yet worked it out, at least with this strategy
explicitly stated and operating.31
Gaston Isaye has worked out such a metaphysics “with this
strategy explicitly stated and operating.” The purpose of the second
part of this article is to grasp the rich and complex outlines of his
life’s work in philosophy.
II. Metaphysics and Epistemology
Isaye’s methodology leads us to a metaphysics which is based upon
profound self-knowledge. Retortion forces us to become conscious of our
inner activity and the conditions of the possibility of all human
action. The metaphysics which Isaye articulates is grounded in an
undeniable experience of a metaphysical reality: oneself.32
No one can deny the importance of the self, for if they do, they are in
fact contrasting their self-understanding with mine, and in that act
they concede the point in question.33 Although Isaye’s
metaphysics is thoroughly subjec-tive in the sense that it is grounded
upon an appreciation of the nature of the knowing subject, it is at the
same time thoroughly objective in the sense that it attains to a grasp
of what is true for all men and what is accessible to the understanding
of all men. Isaye’s metaphysics verifies a definition which Karl Rahner
proposes:
. . . there exists one branch of knowledge which assigns their objects
to the various sciences, determines the structure of this object, as
presupposed by each science, provides the formal principles of knowledge
deriving from this structure and shows how the existence and diversity
of the sciences follows necessarily from the very fact that they are the
activity of man. . . . Hence the statement: every problem of the
philosophy of science is a problem of the one first science,
metaphy-sics.34
We might add that every problem of the philosophy of philosophy (metaphilosophy)
is also a problem of metaphysics, since it is only a metaphysical
solution which can answer the question of how philosophy is critically
justified.
The
Principle of Objectivity
That which guarantees that our subjectivity is the ground of all
objectivity is the principle of objectivity. No one formula is
sufficient to exhaust the full import of this principle. Isaye uses
several to draw out the different aspects and implications of this
notion. His first approximation is: “There are some true judg-ments.”35
No one can deny this consistently. If they are right in saying, “There
are no true judgments,” then there is one true judgment, and they are
proven to be wrong by their own act of judgment. It is impossible for
the skeptic to revise his position by saying, “There is no true judgment
except this one,” for if this is the only true judgment, absolutely no
reason can be given as to why it is true. Every possible judgment which
might possibly be advanced in support of the thesis must be rejected on
the basis of the thesis. Moreover, the admission of even one true
judgment is sufficient for Isaye to ground several others. If we know
even one truth, then we may claim that our subjective experience stands
revealed as being conformed to what is objectively the case.36
The skeptic is claiming that he, the subject, knows what objectively is
the case.
The first principle of thought, then, is that there is truth and that
this truth consists in the conformity of the subject to the object of
all thought. Judgment is the operation by which we recognize and
articulate relationship between the subject and the object of thought.
The principle of objectivity may then be restated as follows: Every
judgment as judgment, regardless of its content, affirms that the
subject who makes the judgment understands the object of the judgment,37
and is conformed to that object. The object of judgment, considered
precisely as object apart from any particular determinations, can only
be some being. This consideration leads to the most universal statement
of the principle: being is intelligible; all that is, is affirmable. If
anyone says that not all being is intelligible, he is subject to the
retort that he has just claimed to understand all being. It is
important here to emphasize the fact that Isaye is saying that it is the
nature of all being to be understandable and it is the nature of the
intellect to understand all being; but he in no way is claiming that in
fact all being is actually understood by the human intellect. The
aptitude of the mind to affirm all being is a potentiality which strives
toward its realization throughout the course of our lives.
Isaye points out that this first principle that being and the
intelligible are the same is a synthetic insight because “thought and
the real are formally different.”38 We do not affirm this
fact because it is an analytic truth but because it is impossible to
deny it. Every possible denial simply returns us to the recognition
that our mind judges what is and can never under any conceivable
circumstances do other than to judge about what is.39
It is impossible to object to this principle on the grounds that some
future event may jeopardize our knowledge. If anyone makes a claim
about what may happen in the future, they are actually claiming
knowledge about the true potential of what now is the case. If they do
not base their claim about what is possible in the future on the basis
of what is really possible, they have no objection whatsoever, since
they cannot distinguish what is really possible from what is really
impossible; and if they can make that distinction for the sake of making
a sound objection, then they cannot deny that the mind is oriented
toward being, for they are claiming to know what is and what is not.40
The skeptic may not simply retreat to the inter-rogative mood and attempt
to avoid affirmation of understanding by only asking questions instead
of making objections. Every question necessarily involves the judgment
that there is something to be questioned (a being) and something
intelligible to ask about that object. If the question is about nothing
or asks nothing about something, then it is not a question at all. If
the question has any meaning with regard to some object, then the
questioner is implicitly affirming an intelligible relation between
himself and the object of the question.41
The process of retortion thus has led us to affirm the principle of
objectivity. Every act of the mind concedes an order independent of my
thought to which all of my thought is spontaneously oriented. Every
judgment, whether bearing on the sensible or the purely intelligible,
whether it is true or false, whether it is in the form of a statement,
objection, or question, necessarily involves the co-affirmation of the
subjective order and the objective order.42 Every judgment
as judgment bears on being as being; whatever is affirmable, is, and
whatever is, is affirmable.43 This is the basic fact of our
nature which makes knowledge possible and which therefore is the actual
and theoretical foundation of all know-ledge.
The
Structure of Judgment
It is not sufficient to stop with the statement that the mind is ordered
to the affirmation of what is. It is possible and necessary to spell
out how we make explicit what is given implicitly in the operation of
our nature. Isaye begins with the observation that every judgment
necessarily consists of a subject and a predicate. This is the
“principle of duality” which expresses the fact that every judgment is a
synthesis of the abstract and the concrete.44 Any denial of
this can only take the form, “This notion is false.” Such a denial
confirms the observation, for it links a concrete entity (“This notion”)
to a universal predicate (“false”). It is impossible to deny that there
are universal predicates. If each predicate had only one proper use,
then after I have been told that this observation about language is
false, I can never be accused of making any other false statements. It
is impossible to deny that there are universal subjects, for it is
possible to entertain the denial only by conceiving of a universal
subject, e.g., “All subjects are concrete.” Having shown that there can
be universal propositions, Isaye establishes that there are some
universal propositions that are true via the same retortion which
establishes the principle of objectivity. It is clear that no one can
consistently say: “No universal propositions are true.”
On the basis of these reflections, Isaye claims to have grounded an
essential aspect of deductive reason. Once you concede that there are
true propositions of the form “P is Q” or “All P’s are Ps,” you have
conceded the validity of syllogistic reasoning. Isaye sums the whole
argument up in one retortion. If someone claims that there are no valid
syllogisms, he presents the major of a syllogism; and if he claims that
this syllogism is invalid because there are no valid syllogisms, he has
undercut his whole position by using a syllogism.45
The determined skeptic might point out that this whole discussion begs
the question because it assumes the principle of identity and
non-contradiction. This was the challenge which first prompted
Aristotle to develop the method of retortion. He answers that no one
can object to this principle without using it to specify what is denied
and what is affirmed, and consequently the use of the principle is
vindicated by the critic’s own use of it. Similarly, Isaye justifies
the principle of contradiction with excluded middle: there are some
pairs of judgments such that if one is false, the other is true. Anyone
who denies this proves that there is one such pair, his denial and my
assertion. It is impossible that both should be false, because any
denial of this position is an antithesis to the thesis and exhibits the
characteristics of incompatibility.46
Given these notions, Isaye shows that medieval and modern logic are
complementary.47 He argues that any adequate metalogic must
coincide with metaphysics, for there is no other way to justify the
results of logic except through a correct understanding of the universal
concept and the exigency of the principle of identity and its
corollaries. These cannot be justified by any higher principles or
concepts; hence, the only way to ground logic is through some kind of
retortion.48
The
Significance of Judgment
Isaye holds that every judgment synthesizes two terms, one concrete and
one universal, and affirms this synthesis as objective. The content of
the judgment is given a posteriori, while the objectivity of the
judgment is given a priori. We are therefore dependent for our
knowledge in some measure on the action of other beings upon us, and in
some measure on the action of our mind upon data. This interaction is
governed by the principle of metaphysical causality. Although the mind
makes a contribution to knowledge by its affirmation of objectivity, it
does not create what it knows; this contribution is a condition of the
possibility of knowledge, but it in no way specifies the content of
judgment (except in the case of reflex judgments which are directed
toward knowledge of the conditions of knowledge). When we interpret an
argument or the data of the senses, we are affirming the notion that
every effect requires some kind of cause which accounts for its being
what it is. A sound argument causes assent in us. A sensible object
causes a certain impression in us. Anyone who denies this can only do
so by attempting to influence his audience through intelligible
arguments commu-nicated by intelligible signs.49
This principle of metaphysical causality is epitomized by the saying,
“As a being is, so it acts.” We do not know other beings by entering
directly into their self-consciousness; instead, we know other beings by
interpreting their actions in light of the principle that they cannot
act other than as they are. This, then, is the ground of all analogous
know-ledge.50 Since we are the kind of being which we know
most intimately, our language will always tend toward anthropomorphic
expressions whenever we talk about non-human being, whether it be less
than human or more than human. Without this anthro-pomorphic dimension
of analogous language, the propositions would make no sense to us.
“What we discover within us we apply above ourselves by extension and
below ourselves by restriction.”51 This is the way in which
the knowledge which we possess potentially about all being is actualized
and communicated. There is no doubt that it would probably be much more
satisfying to have a direct intuition into all being, but that is simply
not how things are for us. We must “by indirections find directions
out,” and in this process the guiding light consists of the principles
which make all of our judgments possible. The ultimate significance of
judgment, then, is that we are finite, dependent beings. This
recognition plays a major role in Isaye’s discussion of our knowledge of
God, which will be briefly outlined toward the end of this article.
Principle of Fallibility
If it is true that there are some true judgments, it is equally true
that there are some false judgments. No one could ever prove us wrong
in thinking that men sometimes err, for if they could do that, they
would have shown us to be in error and thus would establish our thesis
for us.52 It is precisely because we have become aware of so
many errors in thought over the last three centuries that we have become
skeptical about the possibility of knowing the truth. Rather than
leading us toward a skeptical position, this certainty of past and
potential error should point us toward a right understanding of man as a
finite knower.53 The ultimate significance of the fact of
error is that there is an element of freedom in all of man’s reasoning
which must be systematically reconciled with the necessities of thought
which are picked out by retortion.54
The first principles function within us implicitly in every judgment we
make. We do not even need to advert to them consciously in order to use
them in the formation and application of concepts. No explicit concepts
are given immediately by the structure of our knowing nature, even
though our nature reveals itself implicitly in every concept which is
articulated or affirmed. Therefore, it is possible to spell out a
concept of knowledge which misrepre-sents the relationship between
subject and object. If this were not the case, there would be no need
for retortion or for any other indirect approach to an understanding of
knowledge. One would only have to examine the concepts given by nature
and every-thing would be perfectly clear. There would then be no errors
in judgment at all, for there would be no need for any judgments.
Intuition would suffice.
There is, then, this paradox: on the one hand, we are free to say
whatever we want to about knowledge because the language we use is at
the disposal of our conscious mind and will; on the other hand, we are
not free to say whatever we want about knowledge because not everything
is equally true. Although we are by nature disposed toward knowledge of
all being, it requires a freely chosen, diligent effort to bring the
whole of our life to conform to what is true. From these
considerations. Isaye moves to establish the idea that man is
essentially free. Here he develops a more roundabout retortion which
takes as its focal point the nature of dialogue rather than the
conditions of judgment, and he seeks to develop two points: all dialogue
rests on moral obligation: and moral obligation implies that man is
free.55
In every dialogue there is an obligation on the one speaking to be
sincere and on the one listening to trust the speaker. If the speaker
is not sincere, there is no need to pay any attention to him. If the
listener is overly skeptical, it is virtually impossible to communicate
with him. The responsibility of the one is therefore strictly
correlative to the responsibility of the other.56
Insincerity merits mistrust, and mistrust stifles sincerity. Anyone
who tries to deny this double obligation necessarily concedes it, for
every objection is an implicit declaration of sincerity. The more the
critic advances compelling reasons, the more he asks to be taken
seriously, and the less can he believe that he is right in thinking that
we could have a real dialogue without such appeals.57
If we were wholly determined beings, no one could ever tell us we ought
to do something. All we could do would be to follow the law of our
nature. It would be impossible to do otherwise, and consequently it
would be impossible to insist that we were required to do otherwise. No
one can say to a hungry lion, “Thou shalt not kill.” One can and should
say that to a hungry man—and if it is possible, one should also feed the
hungry man. Anyone who objects can only reiterate the point by saying,
“That’s false. You shouldn’t say that.”58
It seems clear that our freedom is finite and dependent. We do not
create; the good things which we know or choose but rather we depend
upon the experience of good things in order to choose them. We can only
choose between alternatives offered by this universe; we cannot choose
what will be the context and content of our choices. We are subject to
physical and psychological laws, and yet, within limits set out by these
laws, we are free.
The
Human Spirit
From the fact that man is a finite, free agent, Isaye comes to affirm
that man is a composite being. Since all of the domain of physico-chemical
realities is governed by the laws of nature, the phenomenon of freedom
in man points to the fact that we are spiritual beings.59 Isaye’s
demonstration of the spiritual dimension in man may be summed up in four
points:
1. The self grasps itself as being conformed to being. This is
undeniable, for anyone who objects is claiming that he knows what really
is the case.60
2. The self affirms itself in every judgment. There are no disembodied
thoughts. Every affirmation of truth is an act of some particular
person. Anyone who objects immediately shows that there is an
opposition between his thought and mine.61
3. The self is an intelligible reality. It is never given in sense
experience, but we can perceive it through its characteristic activity
of judgment. Since judgment is a fact of our experience, that which
causes judgment must also be really factual (principle of metaphysical
causality).62
4. We distinguish one kind of being from another through the activities
which are characteristic of each: ‘As a being is, so it acts.’ We can
tell that there is spirit in man as the essence of the knowing self,
esse ratione sui, which exhibits the distinguishing characteristics
of knowledge, self-affirmation, and free action.63
It is the spiritual dimension which is the root of intelligence, for it
alone escapes the determinism of matter and thus is free to reflect upon
itself. We have this spiritual dimension in common with all men, and
this is what makes authentic intersubjectivity possible. The more I
come to know my nature, the more I come to know the nature of all men.64
The principle of distinction is the body. The mélange of material
elements which make up each man’s body enter into interaction with each
other to establish a unique temperament and personality.65
We must be careful here not to fall into a kind of Cartesian dualism.
The human being is one being, not a mixture of two different beings,
one wholly spiritual and the other wholly material; rather, man’s whole
being is to be spiritualized matter. From this fact flows the
phenomenon of self-identity through process: there are many things in me
which change (you concede this if you try to change my mind on this
point), and yet there is something of me which is ever the same (even
when I change my mind, I am I). These are some indications of how the
essence of man embraces both the material and the spiritual realms.
The
Philosophy of Science
“As a being is, so it acts.” Our knowledge reflects our complex unity as
a spiritual body. Up to this point, the emphasis has been upon the
contribution of the human spirit to knowledge; now Isaye opens the
question of the relationship of metaphysics to the sciences. Some argue
that we learn from the history of thought that every philosophical
position is open to change. The progress of science has come about
through the recognition that very attractive habits of thought simply
cannot be verified and in fact need to be discarded in order to
understand the world. Euclidean geometry has been shown to be neither
the only possible geometry nor the most helpful. The distinction
between matter and energy has been overcome, and the relativity of all spatio-temporal relationships has been established. One model after
another of the atom has been suggested and discarded, and it is clear
that no model will ever reign supreme as our techniques of research
become increasingly sophisticated. Therefore, the argument goes, there
is no certain knowledge. Everything which is suggested is only
tentative and must be open to revision.66
Isaye answers this position by noting that there is a strict dichotomy
between natural science and metaphysics. Metaphysics takes as its
starting point the nature of judgment as judgment and explores the
metaphysical conditions of the possibility of knowledge. Science takes
for its starting point the content of judgments about the world and
explores the physical conditions of knowledge gained through the senses.
These are quite different points of departure; consequently, it is
impossible to deduce metaphysics from science or science from
metaphysics, and it is a serious category mistake to think that one can
substitute for the other.67
The fact that metaphysics and science are distinct does not mean that
they function apart from each other. Man is one, and knowledge is one.
The first principles of metaphysics inform every judgment, regardless
of its content, and so metaphysics may be called the “soul” of all
thought, including science. Science, in turn, is necessary for the
development of our potential for knowledge. If metaphysics were the
only legitimate form of knowledge, we simply would not know our world as
it reveals itself to us through the senses. If science were the only
legitimate form of knowledge, it would be incapable of justifying itself
and its own results, for the validity of the scientific method is never
given as a datum of the senses.68
Science is particularly in need of a justification of testimony. No
scientist has checked the results of every experiment on which his own
work depends. Each scientist begins by accepting an enormous amount of
material as others have generated it. If such a process is not grounded
by the principle of objectivity and by a metaphysical understanding of
the conditions of dialogue, then all of the achievements of science do
not rise above the level of mere opinion.69 If the evidence
of science is marshalled to make me change my opinion, it can only be
successful on condition that there is an objective order to which I
ought to conform my thinking. To affirm that there is evidence that
this is the case is to affirm the principle of objectivity and the
principle of metaphysical causality, both of which can be justified only
by metaphysics.70
There is real progress in knowledge only if we are capable of closing
off dead ends once and for all. The model of the atom may well be
revised again and again, but it will never again be portrayed like a
piece of raisin bread with the electrons stuck into it in static
positions. The truths of metaphysics are certain and unrevisable
(although their articulation may be revised—there are many ways of
formulating these truths). Anyone who denies this simply opens himself
to retortion. These metaphysical truths are the very grounds of change
in science, as was suggested above. If it were not for the fact that we
are by nature committed to the pursuit of the truth, no one could ever
give evidence that others ought to revise their positions. Since we do
have this ground to appeal to, and since sense knowledge does not
exhaust the intelligibility of the beings of sense experience, it is
clear why science is indefinitely revisable.71
Sense
Knowledge
Just as it is wrong to think of man as two separable parts, soul and
body, so it is wrong to think of intellectual knowledge as separable
from sense knowledge. We are capable of sense knowledge because the
soul forms the body and the intellect forms the senses.72
Through the material dimension of our nature we are receptive to the
activity of other beings upon us—we take on the form of the other and
become what we know.73 Through the spiritual dimension of
our nature we posit the opposition of the self and the object and thus
immediately transform sense experience into sense knowledge. The senses
do not affirm being as being. They are oriented toward being as
activity. Through the operation of the intellect within the senses, we
identify the sources of action as particular beings, depending on the
knowledge that there must be a real relation between action and being
(principle of metaphysical causality).74
In the same way, the intellect distinguishes the categories of space and
time which are implicit in sense experience; sensation of space is a
function of time and vice-versa.75
The principles of fallibility and objectivity are both operative in our
sense knowledge. Sometimes we make right judgments about sense
experience, and sometimes we don’t. But it is impossible that we should
always be wrong. Anyone who understands this assertion enough to object
to it cannot do so consistently. The only way such a critic can have
come to understand that there is a position to be refuted is by
interpreting certain sensible sounds or signs as a particular argument.
The very attempt to deny that sense data are intelligible only serves
to confirm that fact.76
Induction
The last major element of scientific knowledge which Isaye seeks to
justify is the method of induction. He notes first that it is
impossible to justify induction by induction. Induction is not any
particular fact; rather, it is an interpretation placed upon the facts
which leads either to the statement of a law or to the predication of
some characteristic with respect to a given entity.77 We
never see the causes which act upon us or upon other beings. Instead,
we know all causes through the requirement of intelligence that every
observable effect must have its ground in the activity of some being.
The establishment of the method of induction thus becomes the decisive
refutation of empiricism.78
The only way to predict a future event is to know a present necessity.
Every law of science anticipates what will be the course of a future
event, given certain conditions, and therefore represents a grasp of the
causes which are most significantly active in the matter in hand. This
virtual possession of the future frees man from the bondage of the
present and once again reveals the action of his spirit in scientific
knowledge.79
Isaye argues that induction is a necessity of all human action, and that
action is a necessity of all human life. In order to make an
intelligent decision about how to shape our lives, we are forced to
anticipate future events on the basis of what we have experienced in the
past and the present. Anyone who acts on the basis of such anticipation
affirms the validity of inductive reason with each choice that is made
and carried out. A denial of the inductive method would have to take
the form: “No one can see ahead into the future on the basis of past
experience. No one can act on the basis of foresight.” Isaye makes two
retorts to this position. First, such a statement is formally an
induction. It states what will be possible in the future based on what
is known to be possible now. Certainly the speaker cannot have visited
the future to see whether or not his statement is correct. Second, the
formation of the sounds is a material action based on foresight. Before
the skeptic opens his mouth to speak (or before he takes any steps to
communicate his position, whatever medium he chooses), he has in mind
all that he intends to say in a single sentence. The sentence takes
intelligible shape only because his action is governed by his conviction
that he will be able to shape the signs of communication and that he
will be able to make himself understood.80
Isaye dwells on this material action in order to draw out the fact that
such action implies that there are physical laws which govern the
universe upon which all of our intentional actions depend. Suppose that
the critic denies that there are such laws: “There are no physical
laws.” Isaye asks what the probability is that these seventeen sounds
could be produced in precisely this arrangement simply by chance. There
are roughly 33 basic sounds in French, so there is only one chance in
3317 random speech events that this particular sentence will be
pronounced. The chances that one minute of speech be produced simply by
chance is one out of 33600. If the environment in which we
produce the signs of communication is not ordered by laws, it is
impossible to think that we could ever communicate with each other. If
anyone takes objection to this, they concede by their very effort to
make an objection that they have gotten the message through a material
medium and that they intend to respond in the same way. Hence, we
cannot not affirm that the universe is governed by laws which our
intentional actions can exploit.81
Inductive interpretation is the method by which we posit the explanation
of our sense experience in the structure of some other being. When I
say, “The page is white,” I am claiming that the way the object is in
itself is responsible for my sense experience. When I judge that
another object also is white, I infer the similarity of the two exterior
facts from the similarity of the two interior experiences. If it is
true that there must be a proper proportion between effects and their
cause, then this induction is justified. It is not possible to deny
this consistently, for the whole of human dialogue depends upon our
ability to judge that many different locutions are generating the same
word or the same meaning. If the critic contends that there is no
necessary relation between cause and effect, in particular between
intention of meaning and the spoken word, then I may take his objection
to mean precisely the opposite or anything else I please. If he insists
that his objection makes sense, he concedes that we can make sense out
of the data of experience by referring them to their source in another
being. We argue analogously in the case of impersonal interpretation
that there must be something and not nothing responsible for the
particular form which our sense data take.82
Given the justification of mathematics (we have omitted this analysis),
sense knowledge, and induction, it is possible to justify the unique
starting points of all of the disciplines of science. Through this
analysis of the foundation of natural science, Isaye has confirmed his
initial contention that metaphysical and scientific method must be
sharply distinguished and yet re-integrated in a completely satisfying
account of human knowledge.
Philosophy of God
Isaye’s metaphysics reaches its climax in the affirmation that we can
know that God exists. He offers several suggestions in the course of
his reflections which indicate how we can come to recognize God. Here
we will consider only the argument on which he spends the most time and
attention. The structure of the argument is simple:
If God is possible, God exists.
God is possible.
God exists.
The form is identical to Leibniz’ version of the ontological proof, but
Isaye claims that his version is not ontological because the proof of
the minor term is taken from the data of experience and not simply from
the hypothetical possibility which we are willing to concede to
virtually any concept.
Isaye establishes the major in the classical fashion. By “God” he means
an infinitely perfect being, one of whose perfections is necessary
exis-tence.83 For the sake of argument, Isaye considers all
four ways in which the two predicates “to be” and “to be possible” might
be combined to speak about God:
1. God is and God is possible.
2. God is and God is not possible.
3. God is not and God is possible.
4. God is not and God is not possible.84
We can eliminate the second arrangement immediately. If any being
exists, then ipso facto it is absurd to say that it is impossible
for it to exist. The third arrangement is eliminated by a twofold
consideration: if God does not exist, there is nothing that could cause
Him to exist, and He is therefore extrinsically impossible; if God does
not exist, the concept must be intrinsically impossible, for it would be
absurd to speak about a non-existing necessarily existing being. We may
express this recognition by saying: If God does not exist, God is not
possible. This means that we may say with certitude that if God is
possible, God exists. There is no other way for God to be possible.
The ontological fallacy is to assume without more ado that we are sure
God is possible. What Isaye does is to show that we must affirm the
possibility of God and cannot not affirm it.
Isaye draws out this necessary affirmation in a series of six points:
1. All must admit that the intellect affirms the existence of objects
and strives to conform itself to what is. Anyone who denies this
concedes it in the act of denial: they perform a real act of judgment.
2. The intellect seeks knowledge as its proper good. Every question
raised by the intellect implies that an answer is worth having. Every
judgment is a claim to be in possession of the good of the intellect.
3. The intellect is not satisfied by an infinite regression. An answer
which leads to an infinite regression is no answer at all, for the
question is never settled, only infinitely extended. No one who affirms
the validity of an argument which proceeds to infinity can ever finish
presenting his objection. If he sums up the significance of the whole
of the infinite progression, he is no longer relying on the progression
but upon a grasp of the first principles of thought, and his judgment
about the significance of his argument concedes the finality of the
intellect.
4. The formal object of the intellect is being as being. Every judgment
affirms the conformity of thought to being. In a reflexive judgment
about the nature of judgment, it is impossible to limit the notion of
being in any way: to judge that the being which corresponds to our
thought is limited is to say implicitly that we know that there is a
greater being which cannot be known. To say there is a limit concedes
knowledge of what is beyond limit. Thus the intellect must judge of
itself that it is oriented by nature toward unlimited being.
5. The intellect cannot tend simply toward the abstract idea of
unlimited being. When I am hungry, I want real food, not the idea of
food. When the intellect affirms that being as being is unlimited, it
affirms that this being actually exists independent from the concept
formed by the intellect. That alone which satisfies the intellectual
appetite is the infinite Being.
6. This proves that the infinite Being is intrinsically possible. “Desiderium
naturae non potest esse inane. Because intelligence is necessarily
a teleological function, it cannot be oriented toward two
contradictories. In effect, nothing is the contradictory of the formal
object of the intellect, being as being. Thus the intellect cannot tend
toward nothing. Thus the intellect cannot tend to become contradictory.
Thus it cannot tend to become a function which would posit a
contradictory operation. Thus it cannot tend toward an operation (finis
ultimus quo) which is contradictory. Thus it cannot tend toward
being united to an objective final end (finis ultimus qui) which
would be contradictory. Now, this final end, is the infinite Being.
Therefore, the finite Being is not contradictory.”85
The intellect cannot deny its own nature. Every judgment bears the
stamp of its affirmation of infinite Being. Any time anyone says, “This
being is finite,” they affirm the drive of the mind toward the infinite
Being. Even if their intention is to say that all of being is finite,
they implicitly concede that the mind leaps toward the infinite.86
This is a natural, not an elicited affirmation; hence it proves that
God is possible. Therefore, God exists.
Conclusion
This article presents only the most general sketch of Isaye’s
philosophical system. Many fine details and distinctions have been
glossed over in this effort to present the main lines of his thought,
and many issues to which he turned his attention have been omitted
entirely for the sake of brevity. Still, the risks of distortion run by
this kind of translation and synthesis seem worthwhile if this will help
to make his work better known.
One of the most interesting ideas which has been neglected is Isaye’s
notion that metaphysics is natural to all men—so much so that even a
young child can be shown to be using basic metaphysical principles in
his simplest questions and answers.87 This theme of the
simplicity and universality of metaphysics runs throughout the whole of Isaye’s work. If ours were an age which cared about such things, he
should be given two titles: “Master of Retortion” and “Metaphysician for
the Man in the Street.”
Notes
1 For a detailed
analysis of Isaye’s method, see The Transcendental Method by Otto
Muck. trans. William D. Seidensticker (New York: Herder and Herder,
1968), pp. 163-180.
2 Joseph Marechal,
A Maréchal Reader. ed. and trans. Joseph Donceel (New York:
Herder & Herder: 1970).
3 Joseph Donceel,
“Transcendental Thomism,” The Monist, 58 (1974), 67-85.
4 For the sake of
simplicity in making reference to the works by Isaye. I have numbered
his articles (see Bibliography at end). In this and all subsequent
references to Isaye, I give only the number of the article and the page
number(s); in this case I wish to refer the reader to 16:282,284, i.e.,
the sixteenth article, pages 282 and 284.
5 13:206; 20:7.
6 Donceel, op.cit.,
p. 81. Donceel spells the word with an s, “retorsion,” which is
identical to the French spelling and practically identical to the Latin
(retorsio). I prefer the alternative spelling given by the Oxford
English Dictionary because this calls attention to the cognate,
“retort.” The O.E.D. indicates that “retortion” was in use as early as
1610 to refer to “an answer made to an argument by converting it against
the person using it.”
7 8:68; 29:32.
8 Philosophical
Dictionary, ed. and trans. Kenneth Baker (Washington: Georgetown
Univ. Press, 197.2), p. 425.
9 Donceel, op.cit.,
p. 81. Isaye makes the point when he observes that this is an argument “ad
objicientem qua talem” (8:209, 218).
10 6:36; 13:209.
11 Maréchal,
op.cit., p. 210.
12 13:206, 208;
24.695.
13 13:209, 215-16;
24:673, 677.
14 Donceel, op.cit.,
p. 82.
15 W. Norris Clarke,
“What is Most and Least Relevant in the Metaphysics of St. Thomas
Today?” International Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1974), 415.
16 Joseph M. Boyle,
Jr., “The Argument from Self-Referential Inconsistency: The Current
Discussion” (Ph.D. dissertation, Georgetown University, 1970; available
from University Microfilms, Ann Arbor, Michigan), p. 5.
17 G. E. Moore, “A
Defense of Common Sense,” Classics of Analytic Philosophy, ed.
Robert R. Ammerman (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965), pp. 53-54.
18 Anthony Palmer,
Book Review of On Certainty by Ludwig Wittgenstein, ed. by G. E.
M. Anscombe and G. J. Von Wright, Mind, 81 (1972), 454: “What
happens in On Certainty is that Wittgenstein treats the
propositions that Moore claimed to know as examples of that agreement in
judgement needed if language is to be a means of communications. Hence
they need to be seen not as opinions about which everyone would agree,
but as agreement in form of life. If this seems to abolish logic, this
is because our conception of logic is faulty.”
19 Norman Malcolm,
“Knowledge of Other Minds,” New Readings in Philosophical Analysis,
ed. by Herbert Feigl, Wilfrid Sellars, Keith Lehrer (New York:
Appleton-Century Crofts,1972), p. 348.
20 H. H. Price,
“Belief and Evidence,” Empirical Knowledge, ed. by Roderick M.
Chisholm and Robert J. Swartz (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1973),
p. 108.
21 W. Norris Clarke,
“Analytic Philosophy and Language About God,” Christian Philosophy
and Religious Renewal, ed. by George F. McLean (Washington: Catholic
Univ. Press), p. 41.
22 Ph.D.
dissertation, Georgetown U., 1970; available from University Microfilms,
Ann Arbor, Michigan. Boyle has summarized his position in
“Self-Referential Inconsistency,” Metaphilosophy, 3 (Jan 1972),
25-42.
23 Beyond the New
Theism: A Philosophy of Religion (Notre Dame: Univ. of Notre Dame
Press, 1975); Free Choice: A Self-Referential Argument (Notre
Dame: Univ. of Notre Dame Press, 1976).
24 Boyle,
dissertation, p. 291.
25 Ibid., p.
287.
26 Ibid., pp.
292-93.
27 6:32; 8:71.
28 Grisez, Beyond
the New Theism, p. 79.
29
Ibid., p. 80.
30 6:47.
31 Boyle. op.cit., p.
311.
32 24:692-93: “The
experience of the self is a metaphysical experience. It is like the
affirmation of protons and electrons in that it is an unseen and yet
experienced reality, but it is different in that it is an experience
from within—we do not feel like electrons or protons, but we do feel
like men.”
33 13:211.
34 Karl Rahner,
Hearers of the Word, manuscript translation by Joseph Donceel, p. 2.
35 24:675.
36
13:211.
37 8:44, 20: 10.
38 Isaye’s article.
“Une Métaphysique ‘intérieure’ et ‘rigoureuse’” (#20 in the
bibliography) was translated by Daniel J. Shine and became the first
chapter of An Interior Metaphysics: The Philosophical Synthesis of
Pierre Scheuer (Weston, Mass.: Weston College Press, 1966). This
quotation is taken from page 23 of that book.
39 8:45.
40 11:354.
41 8:71; 13:218.
42 3:220.
43 6:32-33; 9:225.
44 6:46; 24:675.
45 5:3-6.
46 11 :356-59; 8:212.
47 6:35-6; 16:281;
5:30.
48 11:349.
49 3:200; 6:49-50.
50 15:21-3; 29:45,
54-55.
51 20:32-3.
52 13:218.
53 16:284.
54 2:219; 6:42.
55
[“55” was superscripted in the body of the article, but the
corresponding footnote text was omitted in error.—A.F.]
56 13:228.
57 8:60; 17:885.
58 18:36.
59 17:885.
60 20:14.
61 9:226; 10:932;
20:16.
62 10:935; 20:18.
63 20: 19.
64 13:221, 21:885.
65 10:925, 17:882,
24:683-87.
66 6:31-4.
67 16:284;
20:800-803.
68 15:6.
69 14:183-R5; 15:3.
70
6:40; 11 :362; 30:207.
71 4: 115·16; 6:45 .
72 12:176-77.
73 24:683.
74 6:46.
75 11 :359-60.
76 25:746-68.
77 3:208-112;
4:113-14.
78 6:38.
79 19:233.
80 3:208.9.
81 6:37-38.
82 19:225; 25:748-49.
83 8:91.
84 8:90-91.
85 The whole of the
eighth article, “La Finalite de l’objection kantienne,” is dedicated to
the presentation of this argument. This summary is taken from pp. 89-93.
86 8:83.
87 See article #24,
““La Métaphysique des simples,” one of the most interesting and original
of his writings.
The Major Writings of Gaston Isaye, S.J. (in chronological order)
1. “La Théorie de la mesure et l’existence d’un maximum selon
saint-Thomas.” Archives de Philosophie, 16 (1940), 136 pp.
2. “Logique, dialectique et liberté.” La Liberté: Actes du Quatriéme
Congré des Sociétes de Philosophie de Langue Française, 13-16
septembre 1949, pp. 276-81.
3. “Nécessité’ de la science, sa légitimité.” Leçons de Philosophie
des sciences expérimentales, par Auguste Gregoire, S.J. Paris:
Editions J. Vrin, 1950, pp. 196-228.
4. “Les Sagesses du savant et le dialectique.” Les Sciences et la
sagesse: Actes du Cinquiéme Congrés des Sociétés de Philosophie de
Langue Francaise, 14-17 septembre 1950, pp. 113-16.
5. “La Logique scholastique devant ses recents adversaires.”
Bijdragen. 1952, No. 3, pp. 1-30.
6. “Le Privilége de la metaphysique.” Dialectica, 6 (1952),
30-52.
7. “Antinomies de Ia science historique.” L’Homme et l’Histoire:
Actes du Sixiéme Congrés de la Société de Philosophie de Langue
Française, 1952, pp. 17-21.
8. “La Finalité de l’intelligence et l’objection kantienne.” Revue
Philosophique de Louvain, 51 (1953), 42-100.
9. “Le Principe de dualité et les degrés du savoir.” Épistémologie:
Actes du Onziéme Congrés Interna-tional de Philosophie, 20-26 aout
1953, II, 225-30.
10. “Les Robots et l’esprit.” Nouvelle Revue Théologique, 7S
(1953), 912-36.
11. “Logique scholastique et logique moderne.” Bijdragen, 1953,
No.4, pp. 349-62.
12. “Les Sciences positives et les trois sections de la cosmologie.”
Studi Filosofici intorno all’ “Esistenza”, al Mondo, al Trascendente:
Vol. 47 of Analecta Gregoriana. Rome: Pontificia Universita
Gregoriana, 1954, pp. 173-234.
13. “La Justification critique par rétorsion.” Revue Philosophique de
Louvain, 52 (1954), 205-33.
14. “La Spontanéité de la vie et la nécessité de la pensée.” Vie et
Pensée: Actes du Septié Congrés de la Société de Philosophie de Langue
Françoise, 13-16 septembre, 1954, pp. 181-85.
15. “Métaphysique réflexive et philosophie de la nature.” Revue
Internationale de Philosophie, 10 (1956), No. 36. 174-202.
16. “Le ‘Raisonnement’ de la machine et le raisonnement de l’homme.”
Actes du Premier Congrés International de Cybernétique, Namur, 1956,
pp. 281-287.
17. “La Psychologie rationnelle et les frontiéres de la cybernétique.”
Actes du Premier Congres Interna-tional de Cybernetique, Namur,
1956, pp. 879-885.
18. “Tout Dialogue est métaphysique.” Actes du Huitieme Congrés
International des Sociétés de Philosophie de Langue Française, 6-9
septembre 1956, pp. 33-36.
19. “La Physique, expression de l’homme.” L’Homme et ses Ouevres:
Actes du Neuviéme Congrés des Sociétés de Philosophie de Langue
Française, 2-5 septembre 1957, pp. 222-25.
20. “Une Métaphysique ‘intérieure’ et ‘rigoureuse’.” Nouvelle Revue
Théologique, 79 (1957), 798-813.
21. “La Cybernétique et la methode réflexive.” Actes du Deuxiéme
Congrés International de Cybernétique, 3-10 septembre 1958, pp.
850-65.
22. “Science de la nature et métaphysique réflexive.” Actes du
Douziémé Congres International de Philosophie, Venice, 1958, pp.
183-88.
23. “Bergson et Teilhard de Chardin.” Bergson et Nous: Actes du
Dixiéme Congrés International des Société de Philosophie de Langue
Française, 17-19 mai 1959, pp. 167-69.
24. “La Métaphysique des simples.” Nouvelle Revue Theologique, 82
(1960), 673-98.
25. “La Métaphysique et les sciences.” Nouvelle Revue Théologique,
83 (1961), 719, 51.
26. “La Métaphysique des simples, métaphysique naturelle.” Actes du
Onziéme Congrés des Sociétés de Philosophie de Langue Française,
Montpelier, 1961, pp. 224-7.
27. “La cybernétique et Teilhard de Chardin.” Actes du Troisiéme
Congrés International de Cybernétique, 11-15 septembre 1961, pp.
168-89.
28. “Est-il vrai que l’homme est un robot pensant?” Pamphlet no. 42 in
the series, “Est-il vrai que . . .?” Brussels: Oeuvre des Tracts, 16 pp.
29. “The Method of Teilhard de Chardin.” New Scholasticism, 41
(1967), 37-52.
30. “‘Heureux ceux qui ont une lime de pauvre:’ Dépendance et liberté
dans la priére.” Lumen Vitae, 20 (1968), 205-20.