For background, see
Murray Rothbard Main Page.
Anthony Flood
Posted July 1, 2008
Murray Rothbard: An Introduction to His Thought
Anthony Flood
“All of my work has revolved around
the central question of human liberty.”1
Reason may be man’s most distinctive attribute, but his liberty, his
essential freedom (as distinct from his effective freedom) is his
noblest. For it is by his exercise of liberty that man decides either
to be faithful to his rational nature or to evade its demands. Man is
by nature a knower, but how he expresses that nature depends on how he
exercises his liberty.
Murray
Newton Rothbard denied that liberty was man’s highest end and that it
may excuse license. He did believe, however, that man must protect
liberty above all else in his political life, the realm of legitimate
interpersonal violence. There is of course much more to life than
politics. There is, for instance, religion, philosophy, and art, not to
mention the love of family and friends. To enjoy them, however,
requires liberty. It is therefore incoherent to constrict liberty in
the name of art, religion, philosophy, or love. An attack on liberty is
an attack on the great goods that presuppose it.
The guiding thread of Rothbard’s life is the understanding and defense
of liberty. The life of understanding and defending liberty was for him
a life worth living. For his fidelity to that life he paid a price,
which even those who judge his life to have been a happy one must admit.
What follows is the story of that happiness and that price.
There is certainly no more enjoyable way to assess the pros and cons of
libertarianism than to examine Rothbard’s case. No one wrote more
clearly on such a range of subjects than he did. As he said of his
revered mentor, Ludwig von Mises, “it is rare that people have to puzzle
over what Mises ‘really meant,’” whereas what another famous economist “really
meant about very many things is virtually a cottage industry for
doctoral students.”2 I defy any moderately educated reader
to flip through any of Murray’s volumes on economics, history, or
philosophy, stop at any random page, alight on any random line and,
making allowances for technical terminology, sincerely claim not to
understand what Rothbard wrote. This boon to an expositor is
immeasurable, for the reader can at once move to the question, “Is
Rothbard correct?” without asking, “What on earth is he talking about?”
Rothbard will not impress readers who confuse verbosity with profundity.
The rest of us, however, are in for a treat whenever we dig into an old
book review or movie critique of his, a ten-line letter to the editor,
or a forty-page reply to an academic critic. My purpose here,
therefore, is not to “explain” Murray, which would be an exercise in
attempting to illuminate the bright by the dim. Rather it is to order
as many of Murray’s explanations as possible between covers not too
far apart. The principle of ordering his thought from philosophical
foundations through ethics to politics is a judgment I have made,
namely, that Murray was primarily a lover of liberty. That is, his
love of liberty ordered his study of everything else, including
economics to which he made his greatest scientific contributions.
He believed there was an interdisciplinary “science of liberty.”3
His specialized contribution to it lay in his mastery of economics.
No doubt he loved economics and delighted in imparting his insights
into its many mansions, from marginal utility to the dynamics of the
business cycle. He loved economics as he loved no other field, however
many others he was learned in. It was his love of liberty, however,
that not only made him the economist he was, but also limited his career
as an economist. His contributions to economics, as great and many as
they were, subserved the goal of a achieving a world of diminished and
controlled interpersonal violence and increased prosperity. Other books
will judge his theory of monopoly price apart from his philosophy of
natural rights. Here, however, we will try to see Murray steady and see
him whole.
Murray’s lifelong fight to expand
everyone’s “horizontal” liberty was an exercise of “vertical” liberty on
his part. Without those who exercise the latter for the sake of the
former, the former will steadily decrease in scope. There have to be
those who do not simply enjoy their own liberty, but who also fight and
sacrifice for it. The narrative of Murray’s noble fight is currently a
work-in-progress. His system can and should be studied now, however.
Understanding the system will, I hope, generate interest in the story.
For Murray expressed his love of liberty primarily by thinking hard
about it and writing down almost all that he thought in forcefully clear
prose. We can enter into his world now only by reading what he wrote.
What follows is my attempt to guide you through such a reading.
I.
Thomistic Foundations
Although Rothbard was not a professional philoso-pher, the interest he
took in the philosophical under-pinnings of his economic and political
thought was of professional depth. Throughout his writings on the
methodology of social sciences, we find him referencing works of
technical philosophy. His purpose is not to engage philosophers at the
professional level, but to specify the ultimate foundation on which his
approach to the science of liberty rests. While praxeology, the science
of human action informed all of his writings in the social sciences, it
is not the ultimate science. Why should one rationally affirm the
axioms of praxeology? That is a question for philosophy, and we will
begin our showing of how Rothbard answered it with the following
precept:
. . . [I]f a man cannot affirm a proposition without employing its
negation, he is not only caught in an inextricable self-contradiction;
he is conceding to the negation the status of an axiom.4
This is Rothbard’s justification for attributing to a proposition the
status of foundations. The precept presupposes a certain epistemology,
that it, a theory of the cognitive relationship of the human mind to
itself and to the rest of reality. The precept implicitly disvalues
self-contradiction and while valuing axioms as the foundations of one’s
scientific investigations. An axiom is a proposition that one must take
to be true as soon as one understands what it means, even though one
cannot prove its truth, for one cannot do without it whenever one is
thinking, including the thinking we call proving. The search for
axioms, however, itself presupposes the necessity of avoiding
contradiction. The value of doing so is intrinsically unarguable, for
all argumentation presupposes it.
. . . [S]ome propositions need only to be stated to become at once
evident to the self, and the action axiom is just such a proposition.
[The Action Axiom asserts “that men act, i.e., that they have
some ends, and use some means to try to attain them.”]
Whether we consider the Action Axiom “a priori” or “empirical” depends
on our ultimate philosophical position. Professor [Ludwig von] Mises,
in the neo-Kantian tradition, considers this axiom a law of thought
and therefore a categorial truth a priori to all experience.
My own epistemological position rests on Aristotle and St. Thomas
rather than Kant, and hence I would . . . . consider the axiom a law
of reality rather than a law of thought, and hence “empirical”
rather than “a priori.” But it should be obvious that this type of
“empiricism” is so out of step with modern empiricism that I may just
as well continue to call it a priori for present purposes. For
(1) it is a law of reality that is not conceivably falsifiable, and yet
is empirically meaningful and true; (2) it rests on universal inner
experience, and not simply on external experience, i.e., its
evidence is reflective rather than physical; and (3) it is
clearly a priori to complex historical events.5
This passage is key for two reasons. First, Rothbard identifies as
axiomatic the undeniability of human action. Recall that if the
affirmation of a proposition “employs” its negation, the latter is an
axiom. Although it is trivially true that the affirmation of human
action negates its denial, to note that the human denial of human action
is itself an instance of human action is no trivial matter, for it
yields an axiom. Second, Rothbard allies himself with the Aristotelian-Thomistic
line in epistemology, and therefore whatever we know about how he
appropriated the latter we can safely impute to his thought. Safety is
assured if we follow his own footnotes. They lead us to, among other
sources, Father Copleston’s Aquinas. There we find a passage
that bears on Rothbard’s claim that all of economics can be deduced from
the self-evident truth that if human beings exist then, necessarily,
they act:
. . . Aquinas did not believe that the philosopher can deduce an
informative philosophical system from certain innate ideas of
principles. For he did not admit any innate ideas or principles. He
did, however, admit self-evident propositions which in some sense give
information about reality. He believed, in other words, that there are
propositions which are necessary and yet at the same time give
information about reality; and he called them principia per se nota
(self-evident principles).6
Rothbard also believe that were such things as self-evident
propositions, and he built “an informative philosophical system,”
namely, the entire edifice of economics, on this one: human beings have
purposes and, motivated by the desire to achieve them, act in order to
do so.7 We will explore that architecture soon enough. At
the moment, however, we are focusing on what Rothbard believed about the
human mind’s power to know. He pointed his readers to Father
Copleston’s little book on Aquinas, from which we have just quoted.
There we find an exposition of the Angelic Doctor’s distinction between
two types of self-evident principles.
In the first type, the predicate simply repeats the subject, e.g., A =
A. The second, which is of far greater scientific interest, asserts a
necessary connection between the subject and the predicate. The
assertion of the proposition is not an assertion of bare identity, but
of attribution: this predicate necessarily belongs to the subject. We
could not think of the subject without attributing this property to it:
. . . Aquinas looked on the principle of efficient causality . . .
“everything which begins to exist begins to exist through the agency of
an already existent extrinsic thing” . . . as a self-evident principle
of this second type. . . . [A]nalysis of the nature of a thing which
begins to be reveals its relationship to a productive agent which we
call “cause.” He would not admit that the principle of efficient
causality could ever be refuted, but he certainly thought that it gives
information about the nature of being which begins to exist.8
Similarly, Rothbard contends that we “could not conceive of human beings
who do not act purposefully, who have no ends in view that they desire
and attempt to attain.”9 “Purposeful behavior” is not,
however, arrived at by “unpacking” the concept of “human being,” but
rather by applying reason to the observation of human beings, oneself in
the first place, to ascertain their nature.
When he said that we couldn’t conceive of human beings who didn’t act,
Rothbard was asserting a necessary connection between the subject,
“human being,” and the property, “capacity to act to achieve ends.” A
property is not accidentally but necessarily related to the
nature of which it is a property: for a thing to cease to have a certain
property would mean for it to cease to have a certain nature. It would
therefore no longer be that thing.
Rothbard was also implicitly asserting that the human mind could do this
sort of thing, and that unless it could, science would be impossible.
Yet the notion of empirical study yielding necessary connections may
strike some readers as a confusing mixture of rationalism and
empiricism. Since Rothbard’s science of liberty depends on getting this
right, it is worthwhile to pursue it to the end. We may find that it is
the contemporary reader, not Aquinas or Rothbard, who is confused.
Rothbard’s affinity to Thomistic Aristotelianism does not stop at
epistemology, nor could it, as the following passage attests:
The world, in fact, consists of a myriad number of observable things,
or entities. This is surely an observable fact. Since the
world does not consist of one harmonious thing or entity alone, it
follows that each one of these different things possesses differing
attributes, otherwise they would all be the same thing. But if A, B, C,
etc., have different attributes, it follows immediately that they have
different natures. It also follows that when these various
things meet and interact, a specifically delimitable and definable
result will occur. In short, specific, delimitable causes will
have specific, delimitable effects. The observable behavior of
each of these entities is the law of their natures, and this law
includes what happens as a result of the interactions. The complex
that we may build up of these laws may be termed the structure of
natural law.10
Elsewhere he wrote:
The reason we say things are determined is that every existing thing
must have a specific existence. Having a specific
existence, it must have certain definite, definable, delimitable
attributes, i.e., everything must have a specific nature. Every
being, then, can act or behave only in accord with their [sic]
specific natures, and any two beings can interact only in accord with
their respective natures. Therefore, the actions of every being are
caused by, determined by, its nature.11
Notes
Undeveloped Thoughts
Liberty
was Murray Rothbard’s supreme value. It oriented his scientific
pursuits. Even the love of truth presupposes the liberty to seek it.
First come value commitments, then the search for a philosophical
framework to understand them. But it always came back to a basic
insight: it is wrong to “push people around.”
Liberty is a presupposition of any moral
system. The unanswered question in his writings: How ought
liberty be exercised? Toward what summum bonum ought we exercise
liberty? Is this silence a defect, or a strength? Nothing stops one
from defending a concrete interpretation of the human good.
Rothbard appreciated this value before he grounded it theoretically. The
proof of this is that his appreciation survived at least one change of
justification strategy. Rothbard converted to the principle of liberty
before he offered any justification for it. His theoretical edifice is
therefore properly erected on its foundation, even if value if often
treated after metaphysics and epistemology.
Man’s essential liberty, the freedom that pertains to man’s essence, is
allied with his pure desire to know. Desire is oriented toward its
satisfaction. Knowledge of being is a value for the desire to know. To
pursue that value however requires liberty. Operationally,
metaphysically, liberty comes first. A philosophical system that
devalues liberty undermines itself.
Rothbard’s main battles were not with philosophical determinists, i.e.,
deniers of man’s essential freedom, but rather with those who would
restrict man’s effective freedom.
One might view his economics as a practical vindication of liberty. That
is, if effective freedom is maximized, things get better for everyone.
His studies in history train the eye on the struggle for extending the
realm of man’s effective freedom. His system moves from the individual
to the social through the concept of property. His insight into the
real reference of this notion is secured by an awareness of the chaos
that follows its abandonment. If there is no real moral property, then
there is only physical possession.
Rothbard Main Page