From Thomistic Papers II, Leonard A. Kennedy, C.S.B. and Jack C.
Marler, eds., The Center for Thomistic Studies, The University of St.
Thomas, Houston, TX, 1985, 133-158.
Aquinas and Philosophical Pluralism
Joseph Owens, C. Ss. R.
I
The
philosophical thinking of St. Thomas Aquinas has been interpreted in
many different ways. Read Capreolus, Cajetan, Suarez, John of St.
Thomas, in former days, and Maritain, Gilson, Fabro, Donceel—to mention
only a few—in our own epoch, and you will find that no two of them
understand Aquinas exactly alike. Why is this? Is it a peculiar
requirement of the thought of Aquinas itself? Or is it inherent in the
very nature of philosophy to be radically pluralistic, in a way that
makes each person’s thought differ in some way from that of everyone
else, even when inter-preting the same texts? Asked in its broadest
compass, the question is whether it is of the nature of philosophy to be
as individualistic in each person as fingerprints or physiognomy.
There
can be no doubt about the fact of the variety in interpretation of
Aquinas. At times the interpretations are contradictorily opposed.
Perhaps the most notorious instance, as signalized by Etienne Gilson at
a Marquette Aquinas Lecture in 1947 (see infra, n. 12), is on the
question whether or not the distinction between a created thing and its
being is real. The philosophical explanation of the fact, however, is
still a problem. Ultimately, the issue of doctrinal truth in pluralism
has to be settled by epistemological considerations. But epistemologies
differ just as do philosophies, and share their DNA characteristics.
The only philosophical discipline that allows every philosophy to stand
thematically in its own right is the history of philosophy. Its goal is
historical truth in correctly reporting and describing the various
philosophies and their actual relations towards one another. To it,
therefore, appeal is to be made for a philosophical answer to the
question of philosophical pluralism. As a discipline traditionally
included in philosophical programs, it should without hesitation be
expected to provide the desired philosophical solution to the present
problem.
II
Yet,
despite its place in college curricula, the stand that history of
philosophy is not itself a philosophical procedure may still be
encountered. That view seems to arise from a too facile assimilation of
philosophy to other disciplines. But there is a difference. Writing
the history of music, for example, does not produce a special kind of
music. Nor is the history of military campaigns a particular type of
war. The theme of the history of biology is not another and
specifically distinct aspect of cells and their growth, an aspect that
would give rise to further biological knowledge. In the history of
those disciplines you are not making melodies, you are not planning
strategy, you are not doing new biology. Yet can the same be said of
the history of philosophy? Can you allege that in it you are not truly
doing philosophy, that you are not producing new philosophy of a
special kind?
Think
carefully. History of philosophy studies the emergence of the different
philosophical conceptions from their seeds and roots. It investigates
in chronological sequence the interrelations of these concepts and their
variations and nuances as they develop. It focuses on the course of
their dynamic and ongoing life in what is accepted as a single
philosophical oikoumenê or inhabited world—oikou-menê, it
seems, was the nearest the Greeks could come to the phrase “the global
village,” as made current by the late Marshall McLuhan. Have you not
there the specifying object of a genuinely philoso-phical science? Is it
not as thoroughly philosophical a subject matter as the objects of
logic, metaphysics, ethics, and the other recognized philosophical
studies? Does it not give rise, therefore, to a truly philosophical
enterprise, which is one distinct branch of philosophy alongside the
others? Does it not function in exactly the same order of procedure as
they? So, even though writing the history of obstetrics does not mean
bringing a child into the world, is not the genetic study of philosophy
the producing of a new philosophy of its own charac-teristic type, or at
least—if you so wish it—acting as midwife for its birth?
These
queries demand a satisfactory answer before appeal may legitimately be
made to the history of philosophy for solutions that are genuinely
philosophical in nature. The professional historian is fully able to
discuss whether or not Thales really fell into the well while gazing at
the stars, whether Socrates was given a rough time by Xanthippe, whether
the Peripatetics actually walked up and down when discussing their
themes,1 whether people could set their clocks by Kant’s
afternoon walk, whether Russell became persuaded that Wittgenstein was a
genius on reading only the first sentence of his essay,2 and
whether he put him through the search under all the desks for the
non-existent rhinoceros.3 Those topics come under the
purview of the professional historian, or, as it may be, of the
philologist. But whether Aristotle’s four causes actually emerged from Presocratic speculations, whether the Aristotelian universal is an
outgrowth of the Platonic Idea and how the one is related to the other,
whether Descartes’ distinction of mind and bodily machine is parallel
with medieval notions of soul and matter, whether intentionality is a
continuous concept from the Latin Avicenna through Brentano into Husserl
and contemporary pheno-menology—do not these objects specify in a
decidedly philosophical dimension? Are they not inalienably issues for
philosophical decision? Can philosophy be asked to renounce its
sovereignty in their regard?
It is
indeed the issues of this kind rather than the non-philosophical events
in the course of a person’s life that constitute the essential object of
the history of philosophy. Philosophical notions, not day-to-day
happenings, are quite obviously its subject matter. Peripherally it may
need to track down dates of birth and death, the philosopher’s medical
history, his educational opportunities, his geographical and social
environment, and other such details. But the function of those items is
to provide the material setting in which the philosophical thinking
pursued its going course. Are they not comparable to what the details
of a cultural matrix do for ethics, or what the world as known through
the modern natural and life sciences does for the philosophy of nature?
They are not the object that gives history of philosophy its essential
specification. Rather, the issues that specify the history of
philosophy lie outside the competence of any non-philosophical inquiry.
They have to be handled by a philosopher and in a philosophical way.
That means doing philosophy.
Further, there is something even more discon-certing for the contrary
view. Not only the individual philosophical interrelations but also the
overall nature and extension of philosophy itself elude the grasp of the
non-philosophical historian. You can know what music is, what biology
is, what mathe-matics is, without being involved professionally in any of
these disciplines. But can anyone know in a corresponding way what
philosophy is? Try to tell any person outside the discipline what it
is. Do you not find the task a bit difficult? It is easy enough to say ostensively that philosophy is what is done at philosophical
conventions, what is found in philosophical journals and books, what is
taught in university listings under the heading “philosophy.” But, when
it comes to showing what it is that is taught in those courses or
written in those books, no easy indication of the subject matter is
found to match the way in which you can so readily answer that botany
investigates plants and entomology studies bugs. The subject matter of
philosophy escapes offhand characterization.
Nor can
you really do much better if you consult an expert. He will give you a
neatly worded reply. But try to confirm his answer through another
expert, by way of a second opinion. You are told “No, that is all
wrong. Philosophy is something entirely differ-ent.” Ask a devotee of
traditional philosophy. He may give you Cicero’s celebrated answer that
philosophy is the knowledge of things divine and human, and of their
causes.4 But an old-time idealist will say to you “No, not
at all. Philosophy does not give primacy to the concrete. It is a
study of ideas, the building of a system of thought.” A phenomen-ologist
will answer that philosophy is an altogether special method of approach
through vivid appearances and their foundation in human subjec-tivity.
An analyst will claim that it is none of these, but rather the solution
of puzzles caused by misuse of language. There will likewise be all
sorts of variations within each of these broad classifications, as well
as intermediate or hybrid answers. In a word, if you are sufficiently
discerning, you will find that no two genuine thinkers give you exactly
the same reply. Moreover, if you yourself have worked a full lifetime
in philosophy you may well succeed in answering to your own
satisfaction, in perfectly clear and convincing terms, the question
about what philosophy is. But, unfortunately, you will find that nobody
else quite agrees with you.
By all
these tests, then, the illusiveness of philosophy seems inherent in its
very nature. Is any non-philosophical procedure able to deal with so
volatile a subject? There is, in recent phrasing, no “single developing
whole”5 to confront the historian of philosophy. The subject
matter does not lie before his gaze to be treated in ordinary historical
fashion, any more than the subject matter of other branches of
philosophy is amenable to the methods of mathematics, or of the natural
or life or social sciences. Both the subject matter as a whole, and the
differences between the links among the many-faceted notions involved,
require approach in a manner that matches their nature as philosophy,
even though material details such as the dating of manuscripts and the
points of chronological succession call for use of the established
techniques of the historian. The essential objects can be brought into
vision only through the focus of a philosophical microscope. They
require investigation by philoso-phy itself.
III
This,
then, is the factual situation. How is it to be explained? Philosophy,
whatever you may conceive it to be, will inevitably include itself among
the objects with which it deals. Other disciplines are not essentially
interested in themselves as objects. They are aware that they are
sciences or branches of knowledge, but they have no concern for probing
what knowledge is or how they themselves come under it. Each,
correctly, goes about its own work without asking what cognition in
general is or how it itself fits into the overall schema of knowledge.
None of them brings under its object the noetic considerations it
concomitantly involves. But philosophy is in this respect reflexive
upon itself. It undertakes the explanation of its own noetic nature in
one of its branches that today is usually labeled epistemology.
Further, the same inherent propensity to reflexion upon itself leads
philosophy to investigate its own genesis in its own characteristic way,
that is, philosophically. Its history comes in consequence under its
subject matter. Philosophy finds itself capable, yet entirely in its
own way, of giving an explanation of its development. This sets up a
special, but authentic, branch of philosophy.
So
understood, history of philosophy will superficially acknowledge the
lines drawn in ordinary histories among “schools” or trends of thought.
Platonists, Aristotelians, Neoplatonists, Thomists, Scotists,
Cartesians, Hegelians, Realists, Positivists, Phenomenologists,
Linguistic Analysts, and so on, will parade across its stage. But in
its own more profound study the history of philosophy will find
difficulty in discovering any single original thinker who fits exactly
under anyone of these categories, even the founder of the so-called
“school” himself. On severe scrutiny philosophies turn out to be as
individual as fingerprints. No two are entirely alike. They are at
best grouped by “family resemblances”—an expression used to describe the
groupings of medieval philosophies well before Wittgenstein brought it
into current notice.6 Aristotle (Metaph.,
2.3.994b32-995a3) had remarked how a person’s ethos, that is, the
way the person has been brought up, influences his strictly theoretical
as well as his moral thinking. The habituation developed by
predecessors puts a subsequent philosopher in their debt
(2.1.993b11-14). But in every individual thinker habituation and
ethos will mean personal differences. These will influence his
thought radically, if he is philosophizing in any genuine fashion. The
influence is perhaps more noticeable in oral discussion with living
philosophers, since in their written works they tend to revise carefully
before publishing and accommodate their final draft as best they can to
the common understanding of their readers.
Bluntly, if you examine critically those whom you encounter in
philosophy, I doubt if you will ever find any two who think exactly
alike. If you do, there may be ground for wondering whether at least
one of them is not reciting by rote. So, there is reason to recoil when
someone insists “I do not care who said it; I am interested only in what
the truth of the matter is; who said it is immaterial to me.” On the
contrary, it will often make considerable if not all the difference.
For example, one finds the same word “universal” used by Aristotle, by
Aquinas, by Scotus, and by modern logicians, and the term “existence” in
Aquinas, in Suarez, in Marcel, and in Heidegger. In these instances it
makes a world of difference who is doing the talking. History of
philosophy alerts you to this and shows how to trace the differences.
In that thoroughgoing type of reflexion upon itself in its genetic
development is it not pursuing as genuinely a philosophical
investigation as is found in its reflection upon its own static nature
through epistemology? If epistemology is to be accepted as an authentic
branch of philosophy, why does history not have a like claim?
IV
From
all this one may realize how essential the history of philosophy is for
understanding the very nature of philosophy itself, as well as for
tolerance and genuine friendship inside the philosophic global village.
History of philosophy shows how the differ-ent thinkers start their
philosophizing differently, and are affected throughout by their
starting points. In broad lines, each begins somewhere in one of three
readily indicated areas. These areas are things, thought, and language,
with “thought” taken broadly enough to include mind and subjectivity.
The ancients and medieval—not excepting Plato or Augustine7—began
with things. Lack of historical understanding may anachronistically
lead to viewing them through modern epistemological eyeglasses,
classifying them abruptly as “naive realists.” But a philosophically
historical acquaintance with their highly sophisticated explanations of
knowledge soon shows how naive it is to label them “naive.” The
twentieth century notion of realism, insofar as it is trying to prove
that something existent in itself is the correlate of human ideas and
sense data, does not even touch their procedure. Correspondingly,
philo-sophies that start in the realm of thought are not, in their own
orbit, open to Dr. Johnson’s refutation by “striking his foot with
mighty force against a large stone.”8 Nor can the Oxford
philosophy of Urmson’s Philosophical Analysis be set aside by
Russell’s devastating quip that it is concerned “only with the different
ways in which silly people can say silly things.”9
No.
Things, thought, and speech are obvious to everybody. All three offer
within themselves an indefinite number of starting points from which
one’s philosophy may begin. But, once accepted, the starting points
remain sovereign. They cannot be refuted by the principles or
conclusions of any other philosophy. Yet the possibilities for
communication and dialogue lie wide open. Talk and thought are about
things. Things are described in concepts and language. Speech and
thought are themselves things. The content in all three is common. It
gives ample ground for exchange of philosophical wisdom.
But
what is common—as Aristotle and Aquinas have so trenchantly insisted—has
no being insofar as it is common.10 It has real existence
only in individuals. Philosophies live and breathe and struggle solely
in their individual instances. If the history of philosophy is sending
out a correct mes-sage, it is that their effort should not be
concentrated on refuting one another. Rather, it should be to
understand other philosophies. The philosophies benefit
reciprocally by the communication. There is no merging, there is no
melding, but there is philosophical ecumenism. From the viewpoint of
the history of philosophy, all the different philosophies partake of the
ongoing life in the one variegated philosophical world.
There
you have what is, or what should be, the benefit of the history of
philosophy when it is pursued as a philosophical study. It explains how
philosophy is essentially able to be pluralistic. In this way it shows
in historical perspective what the nature of philosophy is. May I
repeat, it shows in historical perspective what the nature of philosophy
is. It makes manifest the indefinitely varying character of philosophy
as something highly individual from start to finish in each individual
thinker, while at the same time all philosophies share in a common
intellectual life. Acceptance of anyone else’s principles or
conclusions is not required by this philosophical ecumenism. Nor, by
the same token, need it give rise to the least doubt about the truth of
one’s own thinking, when one’s principles are correct. The question of
doctrinal truth is not one that is settled by the history of philosophy.
Historical truth, rather, is describing the genesis of the philosophy as
it actually took place. The reward of history of philosophy is
accordingly the understanding of the dynamics of global philosophical
activity and the correct gauging of the force to be accorded each
instance of philosophical reasoning in the light of accumulated
experience. Respect for the other person’s thinking is inculcated.
Ecumenism, not assimilation, is the result.
Two
objections at once arise against this conception of the nature of
philosophy.
The
first objection is that it seems to make philosophy thoroughly
relativistic. Each philosopher would appear to be a law unto himself.
There can be no standard outside himself to which he must conform. How
is this charge to be faced?
The
charge can hardly be brought to bear upon Aristotle or Aquinas. For
each of them there is a standard to which a philosophy has to conform.
The standard is for Aristotle the world of sensible substances, each a
substance standing in its own right. As substances in themselves,
sensible things are independent of human cognition. Epistemolo-gically
they are prior to one’s perception of knowledge of them. They are not
adjuncts or products of human cognition. They are known directly, with
awareness of one’s own cognition only concomitant to them and dependent
upon them. In Aristotle’s phraseology: “But evidently knowledge and
perception and opinion and understanding have always something else as
their object, and themselves only by the way” (Metaph.,
12.9.1074b35-36; Oxford trans.). The form that makes each of the things
be in the real world by actuating the matter is the same form that is
received by the percipient or knower and thereby causes the cognitive
agent to be, in the actuality of cognition, the thing itself. In this
way the sensible thing is attained in prior fashion. It is known
directly. One does not first have to know concepts or sensations or
ideas in order to know things. Sensible things, therefore, are with
Aristotle radically inde-pendent of human awareness of them. It is by
them that human cognition is to be judged. Epistem-ologically prior in
this way to human cognition, they are independent of every human
perception of them. Accordingly they are a common standard by which all
human cognition is to be judged. In that perspective they are an
absolute norm by which all human cognition, regardless of the
individual, has to render an account. Not individual sensations, as
with Locke or Hume, but the sensible things themselves, provide the
absolute basis to which all human cognition is relative.
With
Aquinas the norm is the sensible thing exis-tent in itself. Judgments
concerning the things have to conform to the way things are, if they are
to be true. Quite as in Aristotle, there is found in the sensible world
the firm basis for common and absolute truth.
Correspondingly, for a linguistic philosophy there is the common
language shared by all who use it. A common use of words is present by
which meaning can be checked. There is of course a certain amount of
relativity in linguistic use, but at least a flexible norm is offered by
which statements can be judged.
Much
more difficult is the situation with idealistic philosophies. Human
ideas are not external immediately in the way language and sensible
things are. How can they be shown to be common to all thinkers? This
is a problem that each idealism has to answer for itself. A recent
issue of the Monist (July, 1984) was devoted to the theme “Is
Relativism Defensible?” and gave a number of thinkers the opportunity to
justify their outlooks on the problem. But in spite of the best efforts
the problem seems to remain. This was strikingly expressed at the
conclusion of Quine’s article in that issue: “Still we can treat of the
world and its objects only within some scientific idiom, this or
another: there are others, but absolutism. all?”11
The
other objection is that the historical explanation of the nature of
philosophy provides no means for determining doctrinal truth. That is
correct. The truth determined by the history of philosophy is whether
such and such a philosopher held the doctrines attributed to him and how
the doctrines were related to his predecessors and to the contemporary
background. The competence of history of philosophy does not extend any
further. When the question is about which of the many philosophies is
doctrinally true the answer is to be sought in epistemology.
Epistemology examines the nature of human cognition and shows which
procedures are correct and which are erroneous. But in doing
epistemology one is already within a definite philosophy. The answers
will accordingly be different in keeping with the different starting
points. With Aquinas the starting points are sensible things existent
in themselves. Judged in that framework, philosophical procedures that
start from common natures or ideas or sensations or language will be
wrong, and the truth they contain will be based upon what these starting
points reflect from existent sensible things. In that perspective the
doctrinal truth present in them will be recognized and appreciated. But
those philosophies themselves will keep their conclusions within their
own perspectives, and will make different judgments on many particular
issues, as well as on the general nature of philosophy. Hence
philosophical disagreement and plurality. They will have enough in
common for mutual understanding and dialogue. But as long as they build
on their own foundations they will differ radically. Their
epistemologies are part of themselves.
These
observations apply equally in the philosophy of religion. In the wake
of Hume, Kant, and Hegel, the philosophy of religion has become a
recognized discipline, and the literature on it is extensive. Its
subject matter is generally located in religious experience, which
offers an indefinite number of starting points. Hence pluralism in it
has to be acknowledged. But the pluralism here as elsewhere is fully
compatible with adherence to the truth of one set of starting points,
and in their light the appreciation of whatever truth may be contained
in other starting points and the conclusions drawn from them. Even
though for Aquinas neither history of philosophy nor epistemology nor
philosophy of religion can be set up as though they were separate
studies, his philosophical principles are capable of dealing
satisfactorily with the fields they cover. In particular, his doctrine
of knowledge through affectivity is readily adaptable to development in
the philosophy of religion.
V
How,
then, does all this apply to the charge that commentators on Aquinas’s
doctrine of existence live in different philosophical worlds? In
general, it shows how to relate Aquinas to the other parties in the
global village of philosophy. Acknowledged to be a great philosophical
thinker, Aquinas can be expected to have his own highly individual
starting points and to develop his own characteristic philosophy upon
the basis they offer. Distinctly individual, his thought will remain
true to its own starting points while remaining open to the widest
dialogue with other philosophies. No agreement need be expected. But
mutual benefit will result. Nor need there be any weakening of
adherence to his tenets on the ground that others cannot be brought to
accept them. Philosophical ecumenism, not assimilation, is to be sought
for and recognized. One must frankly acknowledge that the variegated
starting points of different philosophies do not allow the same terms to
be understood by all in the same way. The history of philosophy,
however, when pursued philosophically, shows where the differences lie
and how the pluralism is to be kept under control in dialogue.
Continued alertness to the care required in philosophical discussion is
the result.
These
are the general observations. In regard to the particular controversial
instance mentioned at the beginning of this paper, the considerations
from the history of philosophy can easily be seen to have very relevant
application. They vitally affect the discussions on the problem of the
distinction between essence and existence in Aquinas.12
Those of us who were introduced to philosophy through the Scholastic
textbooks of the twenties and thirties, will remember how large this
question loomed up on the horizon. Nonetheless even a student was left
with the vague impression that the books did not have any too clear a
notion of the subject they were dealing with. At least they did not
succeed in getting a convincing notion across to the reader. Knowledge
of the history of the problem shows why. The disputants were talking
about different objects, without knowing it, even when using the same
words. Suarez had been showing—and irrefutably—that essential being
coincided with existential being. Texts of St. Thomas were used by his
opponents against that stand. Yet the texts of Aquinas had nothing
against the real identity of existential being with essential being.
They were in no way concerned with that problem. They bore only upon
the distinction of that being, whether called essential or existential,
from the thing it made exist.
To
realize what was at issue here, is not the pluralistic approach from the
history of philosophy indispensable? Aristotle had stated in his
Metaphysics that “one man and being a man and a man
are the same” (4.2.1003b26-27; Apostle trans. Cf. 10.2.1054a16-19).
Though in fact the expressions are formulated differently, it would
make no difference if one accepted a single expression for them
(1003b25-26). Rather, Aristotle considered that it would be more
advantageous for this purpose at the moment if they were taken as the
same notion. In that setting could the problem of the distinction
between essence and existence have any meaning for the Stagirite, or in
general for the Greeks? However, that way of presenting it main-tained
lasting sway. The problem faced was whether the objects of two
concepts, that of essence and that of existence, were the same or
different. The notion that being entirely escaped the original
conceptual-ization of a finite thing did not arise. It was a question of
looking at a thing, and seeing that it was something and that it
existed. Both aspects were regarded as immediate objects of
conceptualization, on quite the same level. The possibility that each
might have a radically different cognitional origin did not make itsel f
felt. This attitude was too deeply entrenched to permit easy removal.
Later
in Islamic and Christian Aristotelianism, however, the revealed doctrine
of creation had come to make the difference between a creature and its
being an acute question. Against the Aristotelian background the
problem still was generally ap-proached as though both the thing and its
being were originally known through conceptualization. Essence and
existence were regarded as the immediate objects of concepts when a
finite thing confronted the human mind. From this viewpoint there was
parity in their origin. The problem was whether the objects of these
concepts were really different from each other, or else only
conceptually different, or different in some other way that did not
involve real distinction.
With
Aquinas, on the other hand, the problem presented itself in radically
different fashion. In the starting point of his metaphysical thinking
the being of a thing was originally grasped not through
concep-tualization but through judgment. You knew what a man or a
phoenix is through conceptualization, but that the man or phoenix
existed you knew only through a different type of intellection that was
expressed in a proposition or sentence. You saw that the man in front
of you existed in the real world. You did not see the same for the
phoenix. But in the concept of neither man nor phoenix was existence
contained. Even in the concept of God, who included all conceivable
perfection, existence was not contained. For its inclusion, one needed
first to know that God exists. The Anselmian argument had to be
rejected. Only when the existence seen in sensible things was traced to
its source in subsistent existence, God, its primary efficient and
exemplar cause, was the nature of existence reached, and the possibility
of drawing conclusions about it from its nature established. Only then
did you have the basis for inferring apodictically that the existence of
a creature is really different from the creature itself. The conclusion
had to burst forth in splendor from the truth sublime that Aquinas saw
in God’s revelation of himself to Moses as I am who am (Exodus
1.14). Everything else had to receive being as actuality really
distinct from itself. In its status as a nature, that is, as something
on the “essence” side of the “essence-existence” couplet, being was
infinite. In this status it could not form any part of a finite nature.
Where present in any real thing other than God it had to be really
distinct from the finite nature it was actuating. It was not just
conceptually distinct, as an object attained by judgment is conceptually
distinct from an object attained through conceptual-ization. Immediate reflexion showed that it was distinct in that conceptual way. But the
difficult metaphysical reasoning finally showed that the distinction was
much greater than one that remained in the conceptual order. It is a
real distinction.
This
metaphysical reasoning, however, was possible only from Aquinas’
absolutely novel starting point of an existence grasped originally, not
as a nature through conceptualization, but as an actuality known through
judgment. This tenet that existence is originally known through
judgment, as contrasted with conceptualization, had no recognizable
ancestry. It was a new departure, the starting point of a radically new
metaphysics, distinctively charac-teristic of Aquinas. Aristotle (De
an., 3.6.430a26-b6) had clearly distinguished knowledge of simple
objects from knowledge of composites. But he had not placed existence
as the object of the synthe-sizing type of knowledge. Aquinas did so
place it. A close study of the history of philosophy is required to
make that clear. This study will show why Aquinas’s route to the real
distinction between a thing and its being has to proceed first to the
existence of God, the infinite ocean of being, and only afterwards
reason through that infinite nature of being to the real distinction in
all else.
So much
for the particular instance. Returning to pluralism in general, and
summing up briefly, the basic reason why people disagree is brought out
clearly enough by a close study of the history of philosophy. The basic
reason is that people are built differently. That conclusion may not
seem very startling. It is quite what common sense might suggest
without any philosophical investigation.13 People are built
in different fashions, physically and physiologically. The
physiological disposition of an elderly person may give rise to a notion
of proper temperature that prompts him or her to turn up the thermostat
to a degree that nobody else in the house can stand. More pertinently,
the habits and mentality in which a person is brought up are regularly
expected to influence his or her views on a wide variety of topics.
There is also the fact of backlash against one’s environment, prompted
by dissatisfaction with and revolt against the attitudes in which one
has been trained. These are recognizable facts. But to understand
them, and to appreciate their dynamics in the pluralism of human
thinking, the study of the history of philosophy has a dominant role.
That
study shows graphically how a wide, indefinitely wide, variety of
starting points are open to human thought. These may be taken from any
of three broad areas, things, thought itself, or language. The starting
points will shape the whole course of the individual’s thought, if he is
consistent. If he is inconsistent, it will cause internal trouble. But
where the thinking is consistent it need not involve any ill-will or
hardheadedness or stupidity when confronted with different ways of
thinking in other persons. Because each thinks according to his
starting points, what is crystal clear to one will be opaque or
downright wrong to others.
A
serious study of the history of philosophy, therefore, grounds respect
for the views and opinions of others, no matter how much they diverge
from one’s own. It shows the possibility of working towards mutual
understanding and tolerance, and reveals the way in which gradual change
in habitu-ation can take place. Application of logical analysis to Greek
and mediaeval texts, for example, has had noticeable influence in the
last couple of decades in bringing many of its adherents to a deep
appreciation of the earlier philosophies in their own right, as opposed
to the attitude that there never had been any real philosophy before the
advent of modern logic. Ecumenism and cooperation in philosophy is
accordingly possible, and devoutly to be wished. In Aristotle human
virtue lies between divine excellence and utter brutishness, and anyone
human virtue involves all the others. In this perspective the ordinary
human is neither virtuous nor vicious. Indeed, the ordinary human for
Aristotle does not fit neatly into either the restrained or the
unrestrained types that come between the virtuous and the vicious.
Rather, ordinary persons come in between even those two inner types,
and alternate variously between them in everyday conduct. So in the
philosophical panorama it would be too much to expect anyone on earth to
be entirely consistent throughout a long lifetime. His habituation can
change gradually through new experience and the open-mindedness with
which it is met. The change can be for better or worse. One may not be
giving in too much to Greek moral optimism in trusting that with the
promotion of serious thinking the good will gradually prevail. In this
vein, I think, full approbation may be given to Aristotle’s appeal to
start from what confronts oneself and work towards what is universally
acceptable: “. . . just as in conduct our task is to start from what is
good for each and make what is without qualification good good for each,
so it is our task to start from what is more knowable to oneself and
make what is knowable by nature knowable to oneself” (Metaph.,
7,3,1029b5-8; Oxford trans.).
In any
case, a study like the foregoing should help to locate Aquinas in
philosophy’s global village. It brings into the open glare of public
comparison the outstanding merit of his philosophical thinking. It
safeguards fully the apodictic character of his de-monstrations of God’s
existence, the indestructibility of the human soul, and the primary role
played by contemplation in human destiny. These are surely the
metaphysical underpinnings of a Christian culture. In Aquinas they find
unrivalled expression. But if we are to appreciate his thought we have
to approach it through the understanding that emerges from the history
of philosophy. By the same token, the radical disagreements among his
commentators can be assessed, and any scandal or discouragement they
might otherwise occasion can be obviated.
Aquinas
himself was sensitive to the radically different character of the
sources in philosophy. He noted, for instance, how Augustine in
following Plato was on a different path from that of Aristotle.14
But, within his own use of sources, what may be regarded as a more
intimate type of pluralism is at work. In their light the same notions
come to be viewed from different vantage points. Peter of Bergamo could
observe routinely, as he listed Aquinas’s tenets one after another in
the Tabula aurea (e.g., s. v v. creatio and esse),
“he seems to say the opposite” of what had been asserted in immediately
preceding texts. Peter’s own introductory comment was that the
contradictions were in appearance only, and not in fact.15
Such a pair of opposites, for example, may be seen in the assertions
that being is an accident and is not an accident. In the present
century attempts have been made to explain some alleged inconsis-tencies
by change of opinion with the course of time, for instance on the one
hand that there is no reason on the part of the creature against its
becoming an instrument in creation, and on the other that creative power
is not communicable to a creature in instru-mental fashion.16
Etienne Gilson remarked in a letter of August 1, 1959: “Thomas has said
everything, and its contrary, at least twice, but in words only—his
own meaning is one, stabilisque manens.” One’s reading of the
Thomistic texts needs accordingly to be flexible. It becomes wooden at
its own peril.
To
understand this phenomenon, however, the deep background of
philosophical pluralism has to be kept in view. The pluralism in
Aquinas’s own use of his sources does not coincide precisely with the
pluralism found in those sources when they are considered just in
themselves. They had passed through Aquinas’s thinking, and they had
thereby been adapted to his own mentality. They were sources as he had
rethought them, and as revitalized in the unifying flow of a new blood
stream. There need be little wonder, then, that they functioned in a
different way, but with enough of their original pluralism seeping
through to cause trouble for an unalerted reader. They gave rise to an
internal pluralism, distinct but analogous in type, and requiring
acquaintance with the original pluralism for the correct understanding
of their thrusts.
Correspondingly, the intramural pluralism of the Thomistic commentators
is not exactly the same as the pluralism outside their orbit. These
writers work on the same texts and remain for the most part within
Scholastic tradition. The unifying influence of those factors keeps
exercising its effect. Nevertheless the pluralistic nature of
philosophical thinking remains basic in their interpretations. In spite
of varying family resemblances the differences stay profound. Common
acceptance of texts and common respect for Scholastic tradition does not
keep their work from being a pluralism of its own type. From this
viewpoint pluralism is itself plural-istic in the degrees in which it
makes itself manifest.
To the
charge that this conception of pluralism allows no room for any
“objective” standard by which philosophies may be assessed, one may
point out the difficulty inherent in the use of that term. At one stage
in its history “objective” was contrasted with “real”. It meant:
“Existing as an object of con-sciousness as distinct from having any
real existence” (O.E.D., s. v., A2a). Objective being was
contradistinguished from real being. With Aquinas, only the individual
is really existent. In general, unless one accepts Platonic Ideas or
Scotistic common natures, anything taken apart from the individual is
brought into being by human thought.
Against
that background, a historian may be considered objective if he treats
each individual person or event as actually found in real existence,
without coloring the facts by framing them in his own preconceived ideas
or making them conform to his personal tastes. The historian of
philosophy never-theless can rate one philosophy as more widespread, more
influential, or more enduring than another, as for instance Hegelianism
through the influencing of both Marxism and Fascism may be given a
higher rating than Rosmini’s ontologism. To that extent the historian
of philosophy may be said to have in his own right an objective norm for
his judgments. But, for rating the different philosophies in terms of
their doctrinal truth, he has to have recourse to epistem-ology. He is
thereby placed within the mold of a particular philosophy, as formed
within a specific way of thinking. The judgments made in its light can
hardly be expected to receive approbation by all as objectively
historical. Compare, for example, Marxist with Augustinian versions of
the historical events in human cultural development. To be objective,
the historian has to view each philosophy as standing in its own right
and as not subject to the tribunal of any other way of philosophical
thinking. It may well be that no one historian of philosophy will
attain that objectivity in a perfect degree. Yet he can strive for it,
and attain it “roughly and for the most part,” as an Aristotelian
ethical procedure. The objectivity allows for experts and for amateurs.
But the
history of philosophy is only one branch of the discipline.
Epistemology is there to examine the respective philosophies from the
viewpoint of doc-trinal truth. Its objectivity, however, remains within
the philosophy of which it is a part. As developed from the
Aristotelian tradition, epistemology is able to assess satisfactorily
the internal pluralism in Aquinas himself, the intramural pluralism
among his commentators, and the utterly radical pluralism in the
panorama of world philosophies.
Notes
1
For the evidence, see Ingemar During, Aristotle in the Ancient
Biographical Tradition (Goteborg: distr. Almqvist & Wicksell,
Stockholm, 1957), 404-411.
2
See Bertrand Russell, Portraits from Memory (London: George Allen
& Unwin, 1956), 26-27; The Autobiography of Bertran Russell
(London: George Allen & Unwin, 1967), 330.
3
See Ronald W. Clark, The Life of Bertrand Russell (New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1976), 170.
4
“. . . rerum divinarum et humanarum causarumque, quibus eae res
continentur, scientia.” De off., 2.2.5.
5
Maurice Mandelbaum, “The History of Philosophy: Some Methodological
Issues,” The Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1977), 572. Cf. pp.
568-569.
6
“. . . family resemblances,” in Maurice De Wulf, Scholasticism Old
and New, trans. P. Coffee (London: Longmans, Green, & Co., 1910),
46. Cf. “family likenesses,” De Wulf, History of Medieval Philosophy,
3rd ed., trans. P. Coffey (Longmans, Green and Co., 1909), 108. “Like
the various members of a single family, each of the scholastics reveals
his own individuality”—ibid., p. 109.
7
For Plato (Prm., 132BD) the Forms were not human concepts but
existents in reality. For Augustine (Magistro, 40, 1; ed. Weigel,
p. 49.2-4) the things themselves were spread out before the human mind
in the divine illumination.
8
Boswell’s Life of Johnson,
ed. George Birbeck Hill, rev. by L. F. Powell (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1971), I, 471.
9
Bertrand Russell, My Philosophical Development (London: George
Allen & Unwin, 1959), 230.
10
Aristotle, Metaph., 7.13.1038b8-1039a3; 16.1040b25-1041a5.
Aquinas, De ente et essentia, 3.52-70 (ed. Leonine, 43, 374).
11
W. V. Quine, “Relativism and Absolutism,” The Monist, 67 (1984),
295.
12
“Here are two philosophically different worlds, for indeed beings
cannot, at one and the same time, be essences actualized by distinct
acts of existing, and essences not so actualized. but these choices
contradict one another.” E. Gilson, History of Philosophy and
Philosophical Education (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press,
1948), 33-34.
13
So Browning’s question “Now, who shall arbitrate?” makes itself felt.
Platonic or Aristotelian, Cartesian or Kantian, Hegelian or Heideggerian or phenomeno-logical, the different philosophies contradict
each other on innumerable points. Yet their authors and proponents are
all intelligent persons, highly trained by years of research and
meditation, mature in their views and widely experienced in teaching or
writing. “They are people who in ears and eyes match me; we all surmise,
they, this thing, and I, that; whom shall my soul believe?” (Rabbi
Ben Ezra, XXII, lines 127-132). One’s own reason, whether in
speculative or practical matters, has to make the decision.
14
“Augustinus autem, Platonenm secutus quantum fides catholica patiebatur,
non posuit species rerum per se subsistentes; sed loco earum posuit
rationes rerum in mente divina Aristoteles autem per aliam viam
processit.” De spir. creat., 10.ad 8; cf. ST, 1.84.5c.
15
Tabula aurea
(Rome:
Editiones Paulinae, 1960), p. x.
16
See Dagobert D. Runes, The Dictionary of Philosophy (New York:
Philosophical Library, Inc., 1942), 16b (s. v. Aquinas, Thomas).
Owens Page