At my
request, Dr. Bahnsen sent me a photocopy of the typescript of this
article. “Modern Philoso-phy and Apologetics” appears (without the quote
marks) in parentheses in the upper right corner of the typescript’s
first page. No date is given, but it was written no earlier than 1970,
when the third edition of Lonergan’s Insight, which Bahnsen
cites, was published; and probably not later than 1972, when Lonergan’s Method in Theology was published, which Bahnsen does
not cite, but almost certainly would have had it been available to him. (See
Bahnsen’s 1973 review of Lonergan’s
Method.) I have
taken the liberty of breaking up long paragraphs.
See also a
critique of
Insight and Method in Theology
by Cornelius Van Til, one of Bahnsen's most important
intellectual influences, elsewhere on this site.
Anthony Flood
First posted September 1, 2009
Van Til reference added
February 23, 2013
The Epistemology of
Bernard Lonergan
Greg Bahnsen
If one has become
accustomed to the more or less prevailing opinion that nothing of
substantial or serious philosophic challenge can be expected to emerge
from contemporary Roman Catholicism, the writings of Bernard J. F.
Lonergan could well be the disquieting anomaly which alters that
outlook. Professor Lonergan has developed throughout his career an
epistemological viewpoint which presents the persistent significance of
medieval thought in the light of modern science, psychology, and
philosophy; Lonergan’s epistemology is definitively expressed in his
astute, though ponderous, volume Insight, A Study of Human
Understanding (Third Edition, New York: Philosophical Library, 1970;
originally 1958). Insight is the first mature philosophic
product of the reconstruction called for by Pope Leo XIII, a project
wherein old scholasticism would be re-stored and completed by current day
thought. The epistemological position set forth in Insight is of
interest and significance also because of the rami-fications Lonergan
sees it as having in other fields, especially metaphysics and
theological method.
The aim of the book is
to present a critique of various methods of thought (both in science and
in common sense) and to lead the reader through the maze of dense
argumentation to understand the nature of insight as a cognitional event
within his own rational self-consciousness; from this point Lonergan
would examine the implications of a proper view of method for
metaphysics and would point out the universe which is disclosed by the
characteristics of insight. In all this Lonergan’s hope is to
demonstrate the resilience of the Aristotelian-Thomist tradition by
purging it of its antiquated science and presenting a new philosophy of
science in its place, a philosophy from which he can extrapolate to the
world structure that is presupposed in the effective operation of the
many fields of human inquiry.
The overall development of thought
through the book, then, is from psychologism to metaphysics (and God):
from the question, What is happening when we are knowing?, to the
question, What is known when we are knowing? In good Thomist
style, Lonergan aims to proceed from an indepen-dent analysis of
rational-scientific human knowing to a demonstration of the existence of
God Himself. An exposition of Lonergan’s epistemology and its entailed
metaphysical implications should properly precede an appraisal of the
same.
Exposition
In Part I (“Insight as
Activity”) of Insight Lonergan sets out the theory of cognitional
structure which shall undergird Part II, the practice of making correct
judgments (“Insight as Knowledge”). Four levels of development are
discernable throughout parts I and II, the first level representing Part
I itself while Part II is subdivided into three further levels.
The
first step of his argument is the endeavor to grasp the key occurrences
in learning math, advancing science, developing common sense, and
forming judgments in order that we might see cognitional activity as an
activity (chapters 1-10).
Secondly, Lonergan would discuss
cognitional activity as cognitional, pointing out that
self-affirmation is objective knowledge (chapters 11-13).
From here Lonergan advances to the third level of development and presents his
general case for proportionate being; in this case self-affirmation is
the key act. The case for proportionate being is used by Lonergan to
establish a general dialectical theorem, which in turn will make
possible a metaphysics of proportionate being and consequent ethics
(chapters 14-18).
Thus far the first three steps of Lonergan’s argument
have sought to present autonomous thought as the lower story for the
climactic fourth step of development wherein human knowledge of
transcendent being (that is, the possibility of intelligibly grasping
and reasonably affirming a being which lies outside of man’s experience)
is proved by the fact that such intelligent grasp and reasonable
affirmation occur. This logic of natural theology is plainly expressed
Lonergan himself:
It was to give concrete expression to the sincerity of Catholic thought
in affirming the essential independence of other fields that our first
eighteen chapters were written solely in the light of human intelligence
and reasonableness and without any presuppo-sition of God’s existence,
without any appeal to the authority of the Church, and without any
explicit deference to the genius of St. Thomas Aquinas. At the same
time, our first eighteen chapters were followed by a nineteenth and
twentieth that revealed the inevitability with which the affirmation of
God and the search of intellect for faith arise out of a sincere
acceptance of scientific presuppositions and precepts (p. 744).
Keeping this broad
outline of the argument in mind as well as the goal toward which
Lonergan is moving, we can engage in a more detailed analysis of the
various levels in the development of Lonergan’s case. It should be
clear from the overview of Insight presented just now that step
one (i.e., Part I or chapters 1-10) is of seminal importance for the
entire treatise.
The first task that Lonergan sets before himself in
that section is to clarify the nature of insight; this he does in
chapters 1-5. In chapter 1 Lonergan discusses the insights which are
sought by the knower. This chapter is crucial in Lonergan’s program to
demonstrate the possibility of having a philosophy which is
methodological, critical and comprehensive (cf. p. xii); the chapter
lays the groundwork for a study of human understanding, its philosophic
implications, and the cure for flights from understanding. If Lonergan
succeeds in showing the power of his method (p. 488), he will
accomplished his goal of finding “a common ground on which men of
intelligence might meet” (p. xiii).
The crucial issue in his argument
is an experimental issue from which everything else follows; that issue
will be the decisive achievement of rational self-consciousness taking
possession of itself as such (p. xviii) and thereby gaining the ability
to discriminate between existential concerns and purely intellectual
activity (p. xix). Thus the question, as Lonergan sees it, pertains to
the precise nature of knowledge and the relations between its two
diverse forms, rational and empirical (p. xvii). His purpose in
answering this question is to provide a discriminate of cognitive acts,
effecting a personal appropriation of the concrete, dynamic structure
immanent and recurrently operative in cognitional activities (p. xvii);
this self-appropriation cannot take place in a single leap but must be
painstakingly developed (p. xxiii).
To conclude, our aim
regards:
(1) not the fact of knowledge, but a
discrimination between two facts of knowledge,
(2)
not the details of the known but the
structure of knowing,
(3)
not the knowing as an object
characterized by catalogues of abstract properties but the appropriation
of one’s own intellectual and rational self-consciousness,
(4)
not a sudden leap to appropriation
but a slow and painstaking development, and
(5) not a development indicated by
appealing either to the logic of the as yet unknown goal or to a
presupposed and as yet unexplained ontologically structured metaphysics,
but a development that can begin in any sufficiently cultured
consciousness, that expands in virtue of dynamic tendencies of that
consciousness itself, and that heads through an understanding of all
understanding to a basic understanding of all that can be understood (p.
xxviii).
The recurrent structure Lonergan here speaks of is identified with the
process of knowing itself, in contrast to the extensive area of the
known (p. xviii); this structure is always the same (p. xxvi), and thus
it is the essence of knowledge and that which unifies empiricism,
rationalism, and common sense. Knowing (this one and the same recurrent
structure) is understanding (p. xxix). To say that Lonergan is seeking
to get to the heart of these essential epistemological questions is
identical with saying that his aim is to reveal the nature of insight
and to indicate its basic role in human understanding (p. 269).
Therefore, it is quite
evident why chapter 1 of Lonergan’s book, wherein he discusses insight
as sought by the knower, is the central nail on which his whole position
hangs. Lonergan expresses himself most simply when he declares
that “An insight is no more than an act of’ understanding” (p. 45). It
is different from sensation (p. 5), being a function of the inner
conditions of one’s mind and enters its habitual texture (pp. 3, 4).
Insight is not methodological but creative in character (p. 4),
depending upon one’s natural endowments, alertness, and habitual
orientation, as well as an accurate presentation of definite problems
(p. 5). Lonergan sees it as the key to practicality (p. xiv), the
sudden release of inquiry-tension which pivots between the concrete and
abstract (p. 6).
It is helpful in grasping Lonergan’s notion of insight
to understand the genesis of insight. Prior to insight altogether, and
presupposing experiences and images, there is found in man an
unrestricted, driving desire to understand which constitutes the
primordial “why?” (p. 9). Man awakens to intelligence, having this
driving desire to understand; with the coming of a clue the imagination
process is triggered and leads to the insightful achievement of an
answer to the question posed (an answer in the form of a patterned set
of concepts—p. 10). An insight provides the pivot between images and
concepts in one’s thinking; it is the act of catching on to a
connection, an act which is facilitated by images and which results in
concepts (pp. 8-10). As such insight is a “preconceptual event” (p. 59)
which occurs as a leap of constructive intelligence (pp. 64f.), a
“lightening flash of illumination” (p. 201). An insight unifies,
organizes and draws into intelligible relations the various particulars
which are known. Hence Lonergan views it as “the supervening act of
understanding,” the act of organizing intelligence, a constituent of
human knowledge which apprehends relations and meaning by a process of
unification and organization (pp. ix-xi); this psychological aspect of
human intelligence, this insight, is the a priori synthetic after which
philosophers have sought, and it is that which Lonergan believes can
take him to a verifiable metaphysic.
He points out that the reader of a
detective story can be given all the clues and still fail to spot the
criminal; the solution is only reached when the apprehended clues are
intelligently organized as a distinct activity. This activity is what
he labels “insight.” Having explained his central notion, Lonergan
turns to geometrical definitions as examples of the product of insight;
from these he goes on to explain the emergence of higher viewpoints and
redefinitions which result from a complex shift in the whole structure
of insights (p. 13) and vast extension of the initial deductive
expansion (p. 15). The emergence of such a higher viewpoint consists in
an insight which arises upon the operations performed according to old
rules and yet expressed in the formulation of new rules.
At this point Lonergan’s discussion twists to the unusual type of insight which grasps
that the only understanding to be had of certain data is that there is
nothing to be understood, there is no point or solution; Lonergan calls
this an “inverse insight” which, in the context of a positive empirical
object, denies the expected intelligibility (p. 19). In the process of
abstraction which acts of insight call for there is an unavoidable
“empirical residue” which possesses no immanent intelligibility of its
own (pp. 30, 31). The higher intelligibility of a fully developed
science leaves certain positive (empirical) data which is particular and
incidental (thus irrelevant) unexplained; however, by going beyond the
sensible field, the enrichment of abstraction allows one to grasp that
which is essential, significant, and important (rather than
individual). Lonergan generalizes and says that in all data there is
this empirical residue, the notion of “oversight”; this is a flight from
understanding which results from an incomplete development of
intelligence and reasonableness (p. xi). It can unconsciously produce
a scotoma or blind spot on the understanding; the production of an
aberration of understanding is designated “scotosis” (p. 191), the cure
for which is found in insight (p. 201).
In recapitulation,
Lonergan views an insight as the prevailing and defining form of the
human cognitional process. An insight is the mental act of apprehending
intelligibilities logically distinct from, though psychologically
conveyed by, sense data and images; because these intelligibilities bear
witness to entities which are unimaginable, knowing cannot be identified
with the process of mere looking. Instead, knowing goes beyond the
empirical presentations to grasp intelligible meanings and to
reflectively judge their truth-status; as we shall soon see, the
rational self-consciousness affirms a proposition in view of its
sufficient reason, thereby rendering the condi-tioned “virtually
unconditioned” by linking it up with its called for conditions—a linkage
which is effected by structures immanent and operative within the
cognitional process. In the background of that cognitional process
characterized by insights is a pure, detached, disinterested desire to
understand or know, a desire which gives rise to inquiry and wonder (cf.
p. 74). This desire is seen by Lonergan as central to human nature (pp.
331, 474). In Lonergan’s estimation, this driving desire to understand
will climax in metaphysical theology, indeed the singular goal of
Thomistic philosophy and theology. However, he recognizes that the
polymorphism of consciousness and the dialectic of various philosophies
reveal that this driving desire can be channeled into different
(aberrational) streams from that of Roman Catholicism.
In chapter 2 of
Insight Lonergan introduces the heuristic structures which inform
the knower’s search for insight, showing that the methodological origin
and production of insight lies in a heuristic structure (p. 44). For
instance, symbolism is a heuristic technique (cf. p. 18). However, the
insights discussed in chapter 2 are taken by Lonergan from the field of
empirical science; having contrasted the scientific developments of
understanding with those of mathematics (such as discussed in the
preceding chapter), he probes into the origin of those clues that
facilitate the initial insight. He maintains that in the act of
inquiring human intelligence already anticipates the act of
understanding after which it is striving. The content which is
anticipated has properties which serve as the heuristic clues that lead
into insight situations. Lonergan isolates two separate groups of
heuristic structures: the classical (the abstract and systematic which
is the convergence point for concrete particulars) and the statistical
(the boundary norm of systematic abstraction from which the concrete
cannot consistently and pervasively diverge).
In chapters 3-5 Lonergan
uses a deepened study of math and science to consolidate his position
with respect to insight, classical and statistical heuristic structures.
Statistical laws, according to Lonergan, deal with particular events
and frequencies thereof (p. 53), while classical laws (formed by the
abstraction from similarities in data) state either the relation of
things (i.e., the concrete unity-identity-whole grasped in data as
individual, cf. p. 339) to our senses (thus a descriptive conjugate, the
thing being a thing-for-us) or to one another (thus explanatory
conjugates, the thing being a thing-itself) (p. 79). However, all
heuristic structures are of themselves empty and anticipate a filling.
The anticipation of this filling process itself is used by Lonergan to
demonstrate the canons of empirical method (e.g., selection, operations,
relevance, parsimony, and complete explanation). Due to the presence of
inverse insights Lonergan sees the inevitability of statistical residues
in our scientific explanations.
In chapter four Lonergan
attempts to deal with the complementarity of classical and statistical
investigations, having recognized the duality involved in the
intelligibility he takes to be immanent in positive data and the
domination of the concrete by the abstract and systematic. He sees a complementarity between them as types of knowing: in their heuristic
anticipations (i.e., either of the systematic or the non-systematic),
procedures, formulations, methods of abstraction, verification, and data
explained. Beyond the fact that classical and statistical methods
complement each other as cognitional activities, Lonergan believes that
the results of both can be combined into a single world view (which
incidentally contrasts with those of teleology, determinism, evolution,
and indeterminism all alike), a world view which is determined precisely
by this simultaneous affirmation of both classical and statistical
investigations. Lonergan asserts: “. . . heuristic structures and
canons of method constitute an a priori. They settle in advance
the general determinations, not merely of the activities of knowing, but
also of the content to be known” (pp. 104f.).
In chapter 5 Lonergan
shows us the result of his bringing classical and statistical methods
together; it is his notion of “emergent probability”: the successive
realization in accord with successive schedules of probability of a
conditioned series of schemes of recurrence (pp. 125f.). It is the
immanent intelligibility which is aimed at by empirical method and which
exhibits the inner design of the world process (p. 128). Emergent
probability is the successive realization of the possibilities of
concrete situations in accords with their probabilities (p. 171), the
world of scientific expectation. According to Lonergan’s philosophy of
science, space is the ordered totality of concrete extensions, and time
(just as simply) is the ordered totality of concrete durations (p. 143).
The concrete intelligibility of both is found in their function of
grounding situations and successive realizations in accord with
probabilities (respec-tively—p. 172). Thus Lonergan’s view of emergent
probability is founded upon his view of concrete space and concrete
time. One can best understand it by thinking of concrete extensions and
durations (i.e., space and time) as the matter of which emergent
probability is the intelligible form—being immanent in the matter
(cf. p. 172). Cosmology has come within the range of empirical science
alone!
In chapters 6 and 7
Lonergan turns to the activities of intelligent common sense, and then
in chapter 8 he brings common sense together with his previous
discussion of science. Chapter 6 sets out the pure theory of common
sense, and chapter 7 discusses its dialectical involvements. As an
intellectual development, common sense is seen by Lonergan as a
spontaneous inquiry, accumu-lation of related insights (i.e., the process
of leaning) and collaboration advanced by commu-nication (p. 175). It is
characteristic of common sense to remain incomplete as a specialization
of intelligence, waiting for one key insight into a situation at hand
(pp. 175, 177). The concerns of common sense are concrete and
particular, have no use for technical language, and are concerned with
things for us (pp. 176-178); therefore, Lonergan sharply
distinguishes common sense from theoretical science (pp. 178f.). He
maintains that the development of practical common sense entails a
change in its subject, and as well a change in its object: the making and
doing which common sense aims at involve a transformation of man and his
environment (p. 207).
In chapter 6 Lonergan had discussed the various
patterns of experience known in common sense (e.g., the biological, the
aesthetic, the intellectual, the dramatic), and this led him into a
survey of the individual’s problems as connected with dramatic bias (the
oversights caused by psychological undercurrents and which is fostered
by repression and inhibition, characterized by a failure of smooth
performance—pp. 191-196); the counterpart to this discussion in chapter
7 is Lonergan’s analysis of intersubjectivity and the tension plus
dialectic of social order (pp. 211-218), flowing from which is his
detailing of individual bias (stopping of man’s intellectual development
at the egoistic level, cf. pp. 219f.), group bias (the self-serving
reluctance of society to move toward the changes dictated by
intelligence, cf. p. 223), and general bias (the universal lag of
intelligence occasioned by a generalized empirical method (parallel to
the empirical method as it relates to sense data) which, as applied to
the data of consciousness, consists in determining patterns of
intelligible relations that unite the data explanatorily.
Such
generalized method deals with a multiple of conscious subjects and their
milieu as well, and this brings in the instrumentality of the dialectic
(a pure form with general implications which enables a general form of a
critical attitude, applicable to any concrete unfurling of linkerd but
opposed principles that are modified cumulatively by the unfolding: cf.
p. 244). Lonergan has now reached the point where he can, in chapter 8,
draw the necessary distinction between things and bodies—only the former
are intelligible unities to be grasped within the intellectual pattern
of experience, the latter being as significant for animals as they are
for common sense. A body is the “already out there now real” (p. 251),
but a thing is an intelligible unity which need not be bodily at all (p.
268); the failure to reach this critical position accounts for the
endless chain of philosophic positions according to Lonergan, and he
thinks that only a dialectical analysis which is based on this critical
position will allow one to go on to a “philosophy of philosophies.”
Things are concrete, intelligible unities. As such, all are alike.
Still they are of different kinds, not merely when described in terms
of their relations to us, but still more so when explained in terms of
their relations to one another. For there is a succession of higher
viewpoints; each is expressed in its own system of correlations and
implicitly defined conjugates; and each successive system makes
systematic what otherwise would be merely coincidental on the preceding
view-point . . . Moreover, emergent probability is extended to realize
cumulatively, in accord with successive schedules of probabilities, a
conditioned series not only of schemes of recurrence but also of things
(p. 268).
We can now summarize
Lonergan’s view of science and common sense. According to him they are
separate and incomplete cognitional proces-ses. While common sense
investigates things in relation to us, science investigates things in
relation to each other. The objective of science is complete
explanation which can be verified in descriptions of direct experience
having formalized scientific method, Lonergan explicates its structure
and points out the kind of world which it presupposes—thereby showing
the application of an a priori within knowledge and experience, and
proposing that one’s method legislates the types of answers which he
will deem admissible.
There are three basic
methods in science, each having its own peculiar heuristic structure.
The classical method assumes that similars are to be similarly
understood, and these similarities are amenable to mathematical
expression; its objective is to ascertain the unspecified correlation
which must be specified. The statistical method is used to detect
probabilities since the coincidental aggregates or particular
individuals do not neatly conform to the expectations of classical
method. The genetic method discovers intelligible patterns, allowing
for the subsumption of the histories or significantly dissimilar
individuals under common genetic principles. Lonergan sees the
advantage or investigating methods (instead of synthesizing facts
and laws) as being the elimination of any need or constant revision
contingent upon new scientific discoveries; the methods will persist in
that they determine beforehand which data and principles may count as
scientific advances.
Turning then to common
sense, Lonergan sees this understanding of things as related to us as
dominated by practical concerns which can in the long run obstruct the
pure, detached, unrestricted desire to know. Certain biases can lead to
scotosis (the unconscious closing off of an insight) which become
evident in psychological breakdowns, soci-etal disruptions, and world
crises. Nevertheless, it must be remembered that common sense does
validly yield insight into concrete situations; it is just that the
shortcomings of common sense must deprive it of any central position in
the solution to philosophical problems.
Now as to the relation holding
between science and common sense, Lonergan sees them as complementary.
This thesis is tested against the issue of thinghood, for therein
science and commons sense would appear to conflict: science seeing
things as wavicles which are verified by sense data yet ontologically
distinct for them, while common sense simply takes things to be
concrete, publically accessible. The reconciliation between these
positions is found (through a critical use of dialectic) in the higher
viewpoint of metaphysics which draws proper and necessary distinctions.
Lonergan says that the scientist is in error by supposing that
intelligible objects, since things must be related to each other, must
be imaginable objects existing out there; on the other hand, common
sense mistakes everyday appear-ances for the intrinsic natures of things
them-selves. Lonergan overcomes the standoff here by integrating the
insights of both science and common sense in the intellectual pattern of
experience which takes the “knowable” to be the “real.” Thus science
and common sense are equally forms of knowledge which can come up
against and understand reality.
In chapters 9-10
Lonergan comes to the point; chapters 1-8 are given as a communication
of the necessary prior insights which lead into the last two chapters of
Part I, the area of critical judgment. In terms of the cognitional
structure which Lonergan discusses in chapter 9 as the final outcome of
his previous analyses, chapters 6-7 set forth the “level of
presentations”: that is, the empirical raw materials for intelligence
which are ineffable by themselves; chapters 1-5 set forth the “level of
intelligence” (which follows the level of presentations in the
cognitional process): that is, the acts of inquiry, understanding, and
formula-tion. In chapters 9-10 Lonergan comes to the point of asking
whether the preceding discussion is so, is representative of the actual
state of affairs; this question is handled through his analysis of the
cognitional process as such and of reflective judgment.
Chapter 9 deals with the
notion of judgment and the overall cognitional structure. The content
of a judgment is a proposition (p. 271) and involves a personal
commitment (p. 272); being the answer to a question for reflection (p.
272), a judgment (in terms of Lonergan’s scheme, to be discussed
presently) is the final and total increment in the cognitional process
(p. 276). This process moves on three successive levels. First there
is the level of presentations, the level of empiricism and common sense
wherein the raw materials for intelligence are supplied; this level
cannot yield understanding of itself. This level is presupposed by, and
complements, the second level in the cognitional process, which is the
level of intelli-gence; here the acts of inquiry, understanding and
formulation take place (e.g., what? why? how often?). Then because we
conceive in order to judge, every question on the level of intelligence
leads invariably on to questions for reflection. This is the third
level of the cognitional process; this level calls for a further kind of
insight and judgment which relate to the notions of truth or falsity,
certitude or probability (though not here in the sense of frequency).
Thus each level of the cognitional process is distinguished by the
addition of a new dimension in man’s thinking; the attitude of an
inquiring mind which effects the transition from one level to the next
does so by means of questions.
Overall the cognitional process is a
cumulative affair (cf. p. 275) wherein the human mind goes about its
proper business of, not contemplation, but adding increments to its
habitual knowledge. Lonergan’s idea of a cognitional structure is
actually quite a bit simpler than it might sound. What he is
essentially setting forth is this pattern: the knower is confronted with
certain empirical situations (i.e., presentations) which raise ques-tions
of intelligence in his mind; having formulated an initial answer by
means of an insight, he then asks whether his formulation is true or
whether he can have certitude about it; upon reflection of these
questions on the rational level he finally makes a judgment (answers
“yes” or “no”). Lonergan schematizes his analysis of the cognitional
process in the following way (each Roman numeral represents an advanced
level, and on each level the progression moves from left to right and
moves onto the next level by means of questions):
I. Data. Perceptual
Images. Free Images. Utterances.
II. Questions for
Intelligence. Insights. Formulations.
III. Questions for
Reflection. Reflection. Judgment.
Thus, the knower moves from empirical conscious-ness onto intelligent
consciousness, and finally onto rational consciousness; in all this he
is impelled forward by the driving desire to under-stand. The last thing
which we need to add to this exposition is the tenet that this
triple-level cognit-ional process operates in two different modes. The
direct mode begins with the data of sense (i.e., empirical science) and
proceeds through the three steps; the results of anyone level in the
cognitional process in the direct mode can supply data of consciousness
(the experienced work of inquiry, insight, and formulation, etc.) which
become the starting point for the introspective mode of the cognitional
process (which completes the transi-tion from level to level). Hereby Lonergan ac-counts for all kinds of thinking and presents know-ing as a
dynamic structure (facilitated by insight).
The only thing that
remains now is for Lonergan to explain in chapter 10 his notion of
reflective understanding. He takes it to be an insight which meets
questions for reflection and which leads on to judgments (thus is
formally parallel to the acts of direct or introspective understanding
discussed just previously). In grasping unity, or system, or ideal
frequency, a reflective understanding also grasps the sufficiency of the
evidence for a prospective judgment (p. 279). When certain evidence is
taken to be sufficient, the prospective judgment is seen as virtually
unconditioned. Thus the reflective understanding transforms a
prospective judgment from a conditioned status to that of being
virtually unconditioned; this it does by seeing what the conditions of
that prospective judgment are and noting their fulfillment (p. 280). A
reflective insight grasps this pattern and by a rational compulsion the
judgment follows; hence Lonergan maintains that the judgment is implicit
in the cognitional process even before the judgment actually
comes about (p. 281). Lonergan next goes into an extended examination
of the various types of judgments that knowers make, and he summarizes
his discussion in chapter 10 thusly:
Prospective judgments are propositions
(1) that are the content of an act of conceiving, thinking, defining,
considering, or supposing,
(2) that are subjected to the question for reflection, to the critical
attitude of intelligence, and
(3) that thereby are constituted as the conditioned.
There is sufficient evidence for a prospective judgment when it may be
grasped by reflective understanding as virtually unconditioned. Hence
sufficient evidence involves
(1) a link of the conditioned to its conditions, and
(2) the fulfilment of the conditions.
These two elements are supplied in different manners in different cases.
In formal inference the
link is provided by the hypothetical premise, If the antecedent, then
the consequent. The fulfilment is the minor premise.
In judgment on the
correctness of insights, the link is that the insight is correct if
there are no further, pertinent questions, and the fulfilments lies in
the self-correcting process of learning reaching its limit in
familiarity and mastery.
In judgments of fact the
link is the correct insight or set of insights and the fulfilment lies
in present and/or remembered data.
In generalizations the
link is the cognitional law that similars are similarly understood and
the fulfilment lies in such similarity that further, pertinent questions
no more arise in the general case than in the correctly understood
particular case.
In probable judgments
the link is that insights are correct when there are no further
pertinent questions and the fulfil-ment is some approximation of the
self-cor-recting process of learning to its limit of familiarity and
mastery.
In analytic propositions
the link lies in rules of meaning that generate propositions out of
partial terms of meaning and the fulfilment is supplied by the meanings
or definitions of the terms (pp. 315f.).
This then completes a broad outline of Lonergan’s basic epistemological
position. Through chapters 1-10 he has laid out a psychologism which
centers in the event of insight, relates the various methods of knowing,
and expands into a general cognitional structure. This is cognitional
activity as activity in Insight.
These first ten chapters
represent the first step in Lonergan’s overall argument in Insight;
they are followed by three subsequent steps in chapters 11-20. Therein
Lonergan develops his view of the self-affirmation of the concrete
subject (knower) as a transcendental condition implicit in cognitional
acts, his method and content of metaphysics, his view of proportionate
being, the implications all this has for ethics, and then finally his
view of transcendent knowledge (general and special). It is quite clear
that Lonergan sees his cognitional theory as exercising a fundamental
influence in metaphysics, ethics and theology (cf. p. 389). However, in
consideration of time, space, and the specific scope of this paper (the
epistemology of Lonergan), only an abbreviated exposition of these
secondary developments would be appropriate. Moreover, if the
epistemology previously expunded turns out to be faulty, the foundation
underlying the later metaphysics and theology will be dissolved and
thereby leave any extended consideration of these aspects of Lonergan’s
thinking useless.
Based on his analysis of
heuristic structure and the place it has in cognition as an activity
aiming at truth and oriented toward objects, Lonergan renders the
unusual definition being as whatever is known and remains to be known
(p. 350). Being may be known either by experience, intelligent grasp,
or reasonable affirmation; and because these three ways all disclose
distinct aspects of reality, being should be viewed as proportionate.
Metaphysics, then, becomes the integral heuristic structure of
proportionate being (p. 431).
Combining his cognitional structure with
a Thomist ontology, Lonergan identifies potency with experience, form
with intelligence, and act with affirmation. At the level of common
sense and science things have simple potency, form, and act; at the
higher standpoint of metaphysics, though, the thing has a central
potency, central form, and central act. The views of thinghood in
science and common sense parallel Aristotle’s substantial form, while in
metaphysics all contradictions are resolved by an integrating principle
of viewpoint-unification (the intrinsic intelligibility of being and the
central form of reality being perceived in metaphysical thinking).
Because knowing is more than just taking a look at the world, and due
to man’s unnrestricted desire to understand completely, levels of
further questions take him on to the realm of the transcendent (pp.
635ff). His limited capacities will mean that the range of possible
questions will always be larger than the range of possible answers for
man (p. 639). The content of the unrestricted act of understanding
would be the idea of being; as such it would have to be absolutely
transcendent (pp. 644ff.)—not just things, but the general idea of being
which lies behind things. However, Lonergan feels that to understand
being is to understand God (p. 658), for they have the same properties.
In this case the conception of God is the most meaningful concept to
man since being in the core of meaning (p. 669). To say that “God is
real” is to say that “He is the object of a reasonable affirmation,”
which amounts to saying “God exists.” Therefore, Lonergan feels that
our restricted understanding extrapolates back to an unrestricted act,
i.e., God (p. 670). His basic theistic proof then is: “If the real is
completely intelligible, God exists. But the real is completely
intelligible. Therefore, God exists” (p. 672).
The higher level of
supernatural knowledge (with its conjugate forms of faith, hope, and
love) was anticipated, then, all along in the lower con-text of
cognitional theory; from the psychologism of insight Lonergan has
mounted to a universal viewpoint. As he sees it, the inner dynamism of
inquiry has brought the knower from an autonomous science to a
universally relevant theology; indeed, grace does perfect nature after
all! On page 748 of Insight we find an assertion also given on
p. xxviii of the preface; thus as the brackets of Lonergan’s study, this
assertion shows us the significance of insight according to his theory:
“Thoroughly understand what it is to understand, and not only will you
understand the broad lines of all there is to be understood but also you
will possess a fixed base, an invariant pattern, opening upon all
further developments of understanding.”
Appraisal
The fact that Lonergan’s
epistemology is staked on the psychologism he sets forth in Insight
leaves his position in a weak and vulnerable condition from the outset;
he would have to possess privileged access to all human
psychological-intelligent processes in order to argue as he does, but he
clearly does not have such an ability “to know whether I reach all my
conclusions via the pattern of data-presentation, insight, and
reflec-tive judgment or not. He is merely arguing from the similarity of
outward acts when humans are intelligently engaged in thought to an
assumed identity of cognitional structure; at best this is an argument
from silence (seeing that nothing is known about the internal mental
acts of others), and at worst it is the fallacy of false cause
(attributing the wrong cause to the similarity of outward responses in a
variety of knowers).
Lonergan’s viewpoint
pivots on his notion of the unrestricted, driving desire to understand,
for it is this desire which initiates and sustains the cognitional
process. This drive prompts further and further questions, mounting
onward from one level to the next; it inevitably leads to God as the
unrestricted act of understanding, the absolutely unconditioned
condition of all being. So then, the driving desire of man’s mind
demands for its fulfilment the complete intelligibility of the universe,
a premise necessary for Lonergan’s theistic proof. However, it is not
at all clear why an argument which moves from the human desire for
intelligibility to the putative existence of an objective
intelligibility does not amount to simple wishful thinking.
Moreover,
by admitting that there is mystery in the natural world, Lonergan
precludes the possibili-ty of man’s driving desire for understanding
being satisfied; in this case the complete intelligibility of the world
rests ultimately on faith: Therefore, Lonergan’s autonomous proof of
God’s existence turns out to be no proof whatsoever. Indeed, even if
Lonergan’s odd God did exist, the intelligibility of the universe would
only be from a supernatural standpoint and thus irrelevant to human
science and philosophy. Again. we must question whether this supposed
driving desire to understand actually leads inevitably to the Roman
Catholic God when in terms of the manifest results of the history of
philosophy we find a motley array of systems which commonly oppose the
scholastic position.
Furthermore, one does not have to search very
long to find someone within his own community or neighborhood who does
not seem to have a very strong desire to learn or understand at all;
indeed, in terms of the revelation of God in Scripture we should
maintain that no one at all seeks to understand God: Throughout his
discussion Loner-gan has committed the customary “normalist” fallacy;
consonant with his Romanist training, Lonergan does not appear to take
the noetic effects of the fall of man into sin very seriously at all.
So much is this the case that he even attributes unethical acts to
oversights of intelligence rather than to any depraved nature and
corrupted mind-set. In terms of what the Bible describes in man, and in
terms of what we actually find in man, the driving desire to know which
men are said to have by Lonergan is far from detached and pure; it is
resistive to God and lustful throughout. That is why behavioral
aberrations are not simply caused by flights from insight (cf. p. 191)
and certainly are not cured by intellectual insights (cf. p. 201)! It
would appear that Lonergan’s psychologism actually embodies a false
psychology of man, an erroneous view of the primacy of man’s intellect,
and an inadequate view of sin.
Lonergan’s idea of
cognitional insight is also beset with difficulties. His idea of
discerning Platonic-like relations between the particulars of empirical
presentations falls short of taking account of the phenomenological
orientation of man’s knowing process. In fact, men do not encounter
isolated, brute facts of sensation (e.g., spherical red) which they put
together into intelligible unities (e.g., apple); all of man’s
experiencing is controlled by interpretations which he already possesses
and brings to the facts. The facts which man encounters, moreover, are
themselves expressions of the divine interpre-tation of the cosmos and
fit into the intelligible pattern of the divine plan; thus insight into
the relations holding between various “clues” cannot even get off the
ground if one is going to insist on an autonomous attitude from the
start. In the case of autonomous intellectual process there could be
nothing into which an insight might be had, for no presentation could
stand alone without at least an initial interpretation assigned to it;
since this is the case, an insight can never be genuinely indepen-dent of
outside considerations.
Next, we would ask if the simple insight into a
patterned coherence of elements, traits, or clues says anything at all
to us about the truthfulness of that point of view. Through any given
number of points there are an infinite number of geometric designs which
could accommodate the point locations; of themselves these points do not
determine a right or wrong pattern of explanation. So also, an insight
might draw all the disparate elements of presentation together into an
interpre-tation or formulated law, but any nominalist will be quick to
challenge the normativeness of this one insight among many. Lonergan
simply assumes that we will recognize the truth when we reach it (p.
3OO)—an assumption which begs the question throughout the gamut of the
history of philosophical dispute! If men recognize the truth when they
reach it, Lonergan has a lot of explaining to do as to why men never
reach it or why they so pervasively will refuse to recognize or
acknowledge it.
If Lonergan’s notion of insight appears to have the
rationalist cast about it (man’s mind is normal and able to attain to
ultimate truth in its own ability), it contrawise also has an
irrationalist cast about it. As noted above, Lonergan thinks that
insights are preconceptual events likened to a leap and to a lightening
flash; this all sounds strangely like a mystical experience, an
unpredictable, unteachable, unstructured process of irrational
achievement of rational outlook! Finally, we would ask if it is
actually true that images are necessary to having insights; must all
discoveries and scientific or philosophic formulations be arrived at
pictorially? It certainly seems that the laws of logic are discernable
without pictures, and one can have an insight into a musical score
without conjuring up an image in his mind can he not? If Lonergan
expands the idea of image to include all symbolic representations (e.g.,
logical signs, musical notes), then his point about insights leading to
formulations can readily be reduced to a trivial declaration that one
must use formulation-symbols if he is going to arrive at a formulation
of intelligence. This same general line of criticism applies to
Lonergan’s idea that insights are pre-conceptual; it certainly seems
possible (and not altogether uncommon) for people to have insights which
are occasioned by the proper and suggestive correlation of certain
concepts themselves.
With respect to
Lonergan’s views on science and common sense it would seem that he has
assumed that methods of science themselves are constant through all
changes in content; however, even the methods of science have developed
and changed over the years. The arbitrariness of Lonergan’s views is
perhaps evident in the fact that he refuses to assimilate classical and
statistical method to each other, a task which is logically conceivable
and which has been attempted before; by keeping these two methods
separate Lonergan is able to go on to his view of emergent probability,
etc., but he fails to show why these two should be accepted as diverse
and irreconcilable methods. Why should random behavior not be treated
as a conjunction of classical laws instead of as statistical law, for
instance?
Furthermore, Lonergan does not show why the emergent
probability from classical and statistical methods is not merely a
temporary inadequacy in human understanding rather than the objective
structure of the world (as he propounds). Even if the structure of
emergent probability were an accurate representation of the world
itself, it is most difficult to see how Lonergan gets from this point to
his cosmology grounded in God and comprised of necessarily dependent
beings; this movement of thought has all the signs of being dictated by
a preconceived goal rather than moved along by the natural logic of the
subject matter and discussions. Earlier we had noted the weak
tenability of Lonergan’s position because of his failure to have private
access to all cognitional activities; the same weak tenability is
evident when we realize that the only thing which is necessary for a
refutation of Lonergan’s extended case is for the heuristic structures
of existing scientific methods to change (thereby showing that they are
not final)—a possibility which is highly likely if we listen to the
renown philosopher of science, Thomas Kuhn.
Turning to Lonergan’s
views on common sense, it would appear that he is confronted with the
horns of a dilemma: either the driving desire to know may be engaged as
much by practical problems as by disinterested inquiry, or common sense
insights are of inferior truth value than scientific ones. Lonergan
cannot accept the latter view because he affords common sense the status
and ability of insight; yet the former alternative endangers the very
disinterestedness and detachment of the driving desire to understand
(fragmentation into mere practical questions would arrest intellectual
development). We must wonder, also, as to the real value of common
sense when, after seeing its downfalls and dangers, Lonergan says that
it must be refined and corrected within the dialectic of the
community—which is itself admittedly biased as well! Similar to the
case of classical and statistical method, we need to ask Why Lonergan
draws a sharp distinction between common sense and theoretical science
instead of trying to combine them into a common approach; there are
prima facie indications that common sense and science enter into all of
man’s reasoning experiences (with different emphases dependent upon the
subject matter and investigator at hand). The implication of
arbitrariness again suggests itself in Lonergan’s argument.
There are problems to be
found also in Lonergan’s notion of a cognitional structure. The idea of
a “structure of cognitional process” is a metaphor built up from
a misleading view of mental substance (which can take on
structural properties and distinctives) that can be easily confuted from
either modern philosophy or the Scriptural view of man’s soul (heart,
mind). If there is no substance inherent to mind, then the idea of a
cognitional structure is nothing more than a “way of seeing” things; it
certainly cannot be made the basis for a far-reaching metaphysical
theory! Moreover, in what sense are we to think of a cognitional process
as isomorphic to the metaphysical structure? Why should we
assume that it is so? Would a variety of cognitional structures commit
Lonergan to a variety of metaphysical situations?
Finally, because Lonergan reverts to a dialectical scheme to handle all disagreements of
philosophical outlook at the metaphysical level, he apparently has
precluded the possibility of antinomies inherent in man’s knowledge as
he tries to probe to the ultimate metaphysical truths of the world.
However, he could only make a successful go of his dialectical method,
then, if he were to demonstrate the complete intelligibility of reality;
if he does not present cogent reasons for assuming this complete
intelligibility, then his theistic p roof also falls by the way as
something less than an argument along with the credibility of his
dialectical method.
Finally we must call
into question the overall possibility and validity of Lonergan’s
argumen-tative logic. He claims to be autonomous in his discussion of
epistemology, and he claims that his epistemology entails and drives him
on to his views of metaphysics and theology. However, it is quite
apparent that one cannot draw this mislead-ing line between epistemology
and metaphysics; the epistemological and methodological stance assumed
by a philosopher is assumed for some reason and in order to best arrive
at true conclusions about the states of affairs, and these reasons as
well as the ability to compare the success of competing positions for
engendering true conclusions depend upon a modicum of metaphysical
understanding of the world already. Therefore, one’s metaphysics
informs his epistem-ology as much as his epistemology informs his
metaphysics.
The idea of a completely neutral method or epistemology is
a completely egoistic fiction of rationalism. An autonomous
epistemology is not able to theoretically ground the laws of logic which
it employs or the canons of uniformity upon which it depends; an
autonomous epistemology cannot intelligently explain the successful
interaction of synthetic facts and analytic laws in man’s thinking. Thus an autonomous epistemology amounts to either sheer arbitrariness
(and therefore should not command our serious attention) or to the
denial of a theoretically justified doctrine of knowledge (in which case
the position is self-vitiating and should be rejected on the most
elementary level of consideration). In accepting the logic of natural
theology, Lonergan implicitly undermined his whole study of epistemology
and metaphysics; in his attempt to explain the groundings of
epistemology on an autonomous basis he precluded the success of his
endeavor. And because he founds his metaphysic and theology in his
epistemology, those two outlooks must be rejected with the same
stringency that demands the rejection of his problem-laden theory of
knowledge.
Before closing our
consideration of Lonergan we can briefly sketch some specific
difficulties in his metaphysic and theology. In common with all
unscriptural thinking, Lonergan is pulled apart by the opposite poles of
rationalism and irrationalism: for instance, he tries to combine the
determinism of classical laws with the indeterminism of statistical
method, he hold to the rationalistic doctrine that man must drive toward
the limit of omniscience while simultaneously believing the
irrationalist tenet that it is impossible to know all things due to the
inevitability of mystery and distortions. In his metaphysics Lonergan
dubiously stretches the potency-form-act motif which was helpful in
analyzing common sense to apply it to the thing itself (a semi-Kantian
thing-in-itself which is outside ordinary human experience and the reach
of normal science); it is questionable whether the fact that cognitional
theory influences metaphysics logically justifies inferences from the
“structure of cognitional processes” to the constitution of ontological
structures.
And yet such argumentation dominates the viewpoint of Lonergan’s Insight. Lonergan’s infer-ence would be valid if and
only if he could show that no other cosmology or metaphysic can account
for the structures of the cognitional pro-cess, and such a universal
negative argument simply cannot be adduced (especially on Loner-gan’s
autonomous platform). Consequently, the argument of his book must be
seen as faulted. Lonergan could only see methods and cognitional
processes as the foundation for inference to cosmology and metaphysics
(rather than specific instances of them) if he were a Kantian (i.e.,
holding that the knowing subject imparts the very structures to
knowledge, experience and nature); yet Lonergan is the diametric
opposite of a Kantian since, instead of limiting his conjectures to
human experience, he goes after the things in themselves, even applying
the structure of the cognitional process to God! In the case of
Lonergan we find a most radical subjectivism, a case wherein
epistemology, cosmology, and theology all collapse into a psychologism
of the knower as subject.
It is clear that Lonergan has abandoned any
truly transcendent starting point which would ground philosophic
thinking in the word revelation of a transcendent God; Lonergan’s
position is com-pletely immanentistic (despite his intentions!). By
means of his analogy of Being Lonergan forces the knowing subject to
become God projected, and this in order to prove the existence of this
God who is man’s image! Professor Lonergan’s investigations and study
were never truly independent of theological commitment as he had
claimed; all along he was working on a scheme which of necessity
worships the creature rather than the Creator—a most definite, and
erroneous, theological commitment. There would, advancing to other
difficulties, seem to be a few contradictions in Lonergan’s view of
being which need resolution: he says being is the knowable, yet a state
of affairs (cf. pp. 348, 358); he says being is univocal, yet analogical
(cf. pp. 361f.); he maintains that being is, and is not, a genus (p.
367).
Lonergan’s thinking becomes completely obscure when he holds that
the core of meaning is the intention of being (p. 359); what sense is to
be made of that? Turning finally to Lonergan’ s own theology we observe
that, along with all the past scholastics, he thinks that he knows
that God is but not what God is (cf. p. 634). When Lonergan
identifies Being with God he begs the crucial question of his study;
why, after all, should one just assume a Thomistic notion of God? In a
strange form of argumentation Lonergan thinks that the problem of evil
(a problem which he had not taken very seriously in his first seventeen
chapters we would note) pushes us to affirm God’s existence (in the
egoistic sense that we need a grounding for explanation and
rationality); how-ever, the problem of evil is usually taken to dictate
against God’s existence, and it is not clear why Lonergan’s autonomous
theology does not suitably collapse under, that problematic. Lastly we
would indicate that Lonergan, just as his Thomistic predecessors,
constructs a proof of God as an unrestricted act of understanding and
thereby makes Him as isolated and irrelevant to the world as Aristotle’s
unmoved mover and entails that He has the same difficulty in contacting
the created world as the God of Aquinas did.
Rehabilitation
Despite all its
encumbering fallacies, arbitrari-ness, and philosophic difficulties, the
writings of Bernard Lonergan are not devoid of formally helpful
insights. If his credible points were to be taken and placed upon a
presuppositional and Scriptural foundation there might be a prospect for
Christian epistemology being advanced in some areas. Two areas where
Lonergan comes close to offering significant aid to the Christian
apologist are: his position that one’s method determines the content of
his conclusions (cf. pp. 104f.) and his more or less transcendental
proof of God’s existence (cf. p. 672). In both of these cases the
important insights would have to be taken out of the problematic and
immanentistic context of Lonergan’s Thomistic thought and replanted in a
Biblical world-view.
Lonergan might also be the formal jumping off
point for genuinely Christian philosophers to explore the significance
of that process of coming to understand which is designated “insight.”
This notion should profitably be used for comparison and contrast with
the noetic operations of the Holy Spirit in inspiration, inward
testimony and illumination of the believer, and common grace operations
whereby even the unbeliever is enabled to come to some fundamental
understanding of his world. If the notion were purged of its mystical
connotations and qualified with ethical consider-ations, insight might be
a valuable didactic cate-gory for Christian philosophy. But again, if it
were to become so it would have to be reworked within the presuppositional viewpoint of Scriptural thinking.
As noted in the
introduction to this paper Bernard Lonergan’s philosophy is an anomaly
if one is not expecting anything of serious philosophical import from
the Roman Church today. The preceding exposition hopefully demonstrated
that. However, the subsequent appraisal and rehabilita-tion suggestion
should have also made manifest that in the long run Lonergan has really
not presented anything new to us; what we have in his case is simply a
redressed form of medieval Thomism. As the Reformation vigorously
opposed such a position, so also reformed thinkers today must challenge
this persistent heresy so that we do not become like unto it and so that
its proponents will not be wise in their own conceits (Proverbs 26:4-5).
Greg L. Bahnsen page