Dated December, 1973. Text taken from
Eric Sigward’s CD of The Collected
Works of Cornelius Van Til and checked
against a copy of typescript I bought from Westminster Seminary’s book store in
the late 1980s. Misspellings and typos corrected.
See also elsewhere on this
site two critical studies of Lonergan by one of Van Til's students,
Gregory L. Bahnsen,
The Epistemology of Bernard Lonergan
and Review
of Bernard Lonergan, Method in
Theology [1973].
Anthony Flood
February 23, 2013
Bernard J. F. Lonergan, S.J.
Cornelius Van Til
Among recent Roman Catholic thinkers Bernard J. F. Lonergan, S.J.
occupies a prominent place.
[Bernard] J. F. Lonergan
was born in Bucking-ham, Quebec, on December 17, 1904. Among the
institutions of learning he attended was the Uni-versity of London. What
a joy it was to Lonergan to be able to read
Cardinal J. H. Newman there.
New-man’s work An Essay of a Grammer [sic] of Assent
[An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent], says
F. E. Crowe, S.J. “had a profound
influence on Loner-gan’s developing epistemology.” (Collection Pa-pers
[i.e., Collection] by Bernard Lonergan, S. J. edited by F. E.
Crowe, S.J, Herder and Herder, 1967, p. IX)
When
in 1940 Lonergan began his teaching career, i.e. [sic] Roman
Catholic theology was turning into “new ways.” The “revolution in
theology was to be as world-shaking,” says Crowe, “as the war had been
in international politics.” “The gathering of professors at the
Gregorian in the thirties,” Crowe adds, “represented the fine flowering
of the old ‘classical’ culture and from them Lonergan imbibed much that
was best in the patrimony they had inherited and built up and handed
down, but the future belonged to other men: new ways of thinking, new
attitudes to fellow-Christians, new programs in theology were taking
over.” To those new trends Lonergan was to make his contribution as his
ideas slowly matured.” (Ibid., p. XI)
“In
his intellectual pilgrimage Lonergan travelled from Newman to Augustine
to Plato, then he imbibed Marechal ‘by osmosis’ from a fellow scholastic
at the Gregorian; and in his doctorate work he came to a personal
confrontation with St. Thomas and Aristotle that would lead him far from
the established schools and be a powerful fertilizing influence for
further evolution and new creative thinking. For St. Thomas, even the
genuine St. Thomas, was now obviously not enough.”
A
glance at Lonergan’s main writings during his first twenty-five years of
teaching indicate this general trend of his thinking. Lonergan wrote
his doctoral dissertation on “the concept of
gratia
operans
in St. Thomas.” He thus began his work as writer on philosophy and
theology by “reaching up to the mind of a genius.” (Ibid., p.
XII)
1. Insight
Omitting other writings we pass on at once to Lonergan’s work entitled
Insight, a Study of Human Understanding. Insight is, says Crowe,
“a Thomist book—in its fundamental metaphysics and epis-temology” but it
is in fact “a profound rethinking of cognitional theory on the basis of
seven centuries of mathematics, physics, chemistry, biology, depth
psychology, the social and human sciences and modern philosophy. The
net result was a transformation of the transcendental method as
developed by Marechal in correction and comple-ment of Kant: a critical
appropriation of human cognitional structure as a basis for a methodical
science and philosophy.” (Ibid., pp. XII-XIII)
“But, despite all its wealth and fertility,” Crowe continues, “Insight
was really only preliminary and preparatory, it had not yet come to the
heart of the matter in regard to goals and objectives.” Insight
“dealt mainly with the subject, and the subject was irrevocably
orientated to an
intentio entis intendens.”
Lonergan’s “lectures in graduate courses . . . have moved since
Insight through the implementation of methods founded on that book,
to the question of the meaning that constitutes human institutions and,
because meaning develops in history, of the new historical consciousness
of man.” (Ibid., p. XIII)
Thanking Crowe for his help in getting under way we take a look into
Insight for ourselves.
The
first five chapters of the book are devoted to the question, “What is
meant by Insight?” Man cannot begin his effort to understand
himself and his world in an uncritical way. Why did I not, asks
Lonergan, simply begin “from the simple and obvious notion of the thing?
The answer is that man is involved in a dialectical tension, and he can
be made aware of the fact only after he has grasped what is meant and
what is not meant by inquiry, insight and conception as opposed to
sensible data and schematic images. Accordingly our first task was to
clarify the nature of insight and to it we devoted our first five
chapters.” (Ibid., p. 267)
Let
us then, argues Lonergan, each for himself ask the question: “Am I a
knower?” (Ibid., p. 328) But any one who asks the question “Am I
a knower” is rationally conscious. For the question is a question for
rational reflection, a question to be met with a “Yes” or “No”; and
asking the question does not mean repeating the words but entering the
dynamic state in which dissatisfaction with mere theory manifests itself
in a demand for fact, for what is so. Further, the question is not any
question. If I ask it I know what it means. What do I mean by “I”?
The answer is difficult to formulate, but strangely, in some obscure
fashion, I know very well what it means without formulation, and by that
obscure yet familiar awareness, I find fault with various formulations
of what is meant by “I” . . . .
Still further, when I ask myself what I mean when I say “I” I ask
whether in answering the question I am, at the same time, affirming the
unconditioned. “As each has to ask these questions of himself, so too
he has to answer them for himself. But the fact of the asking and the
possibility of the answering are themselves the sufficient reason for
the affirmative answer.” (Ibid., p. 328)
What
has been said is but a very small sample of Lonergan’s analysis of the
subject of all human thought and action. Unable to follow Lonergan in
the detailed descriptions of the subject in Insight we turn at
once to his little book entitled The Subject. In this booklet we
have the “Acquinas [sic: Aquinas] Lecture 1968.”
1. Emphasis on the Subject in Recent Philosophy
Lonergan is in agreement with the modern philosophical “emphasis on the
subject.” (Ibid., p. 2) Roman Catholics may well rejoice in it.
Were they not often embarrassed by the syllogism: “What God has revealed
is true. God has revealed the mysteries of the faith. Therefore, the
mysteries of the faith are true”? This syllogism “implied that the
mysteries of the faith were demonstrable conclusions” which they are
not. Some Catholic theologians of the past “seem to have thought of
truth as so objective as to get along without minds.” These theologians
“little understood the need to respect the dynamics of the advance
toward truth.” (Ibid., p. 5)
This
overstress on objectivity may be traced back to Aristotle’s notion of
science as “propounded in the Posterior Analytics, and
proximately in the rationalist notion of pure reason.” (Idem.)
On this basis there is again “no need for concern with the subject.” (Ibid.,
p. 6)
Again the traditional “metaphysical account of the soul” was “totally
objective.” “The study of the subject is quite different for it is the
study of oneself inasmuch as one is conscious. It prescinds from the
soul, its essence, its potencies, its habits, for none of these are
given in consciousness.” (Ibid., p. 7) It attends to operations
and to their center and source which is the self. It discerns the
different levels of consciousness, the conscious-ness of the dream, of
the waking subject, of the intelligently inquiring subject, of the
rationally reflecting subject, of the responsibly deliberating subject.
It examines the different operations on the several levels and their
relations to one another.” (Ibid., p. 8)
A. The Truncated Subject
Besides neglecting the subject men have often truncated it. When they
did so they were not able to appreciate the complexity of the totality
of the operations of consciousness because of the disease of
conceptualism.
The
result was an “anti-historical immobilism,” an “excessive
abstractness.” (Ibid., p. 10) Men thought of being as an
abstraction while in reality it is concrete. “It intends everything
about everything.” (Ibid., p. 11) “The notion of being, then, is
essentially dynamic, proleptic, an anticipation of the entirety, the
concreteness, the totality, that we ever intend and since our knowledge
is finite never reach.
The
neglected subject, then leads to the truncated subject, the subject that
does not know himself and so unduly impoverishes his account of human
knowledge.” (Ibid., p. 12)
(1) The Merely Immanent Subject
What
remains is the “merely immanent sub-ject.” (Ibid., p. 17) The
merely immanent subject knows no thinking but picture-thinking. But
“visual images are incapable of representing or suggesting the normative
exigencies of intelligence and reasonableness and, much less, their
power to effect the intentional self-transcendence of the subject.” (Ibid.,
p. 16)
B. The Existential Subject
What
we need is the “existential subject.” (Ibid., p. 19) To
understand the nature of the “existential subject” we must see that “we
are subjects, as it were, by degrees. At a lowest level, when
unconscious in dreamless sleep or in a coma, we are merely potentially
subjects. Next, we have a minimal degree of consciousness and
subjectivity when we are the helpless subjects of our dreams. Thirdly,
we become experiential subjects when we awake, when we become the
subjects of lucid perception, imaginative projects, emotional and
conative impulses, and bodily action. Fourthly, the intelligent subject
sublates the experiential, i.e., it retains, preserves, goes beyond,
completes it, when we inquire about our experience, investigate, grow in
understanding, express our inventions and discoveries. Fifthly, the
rational subject sublates the intelligent and experiential subject, when
we question our own understanding, check our formulations and
expressions, ask whether we have got things right, marshal the evidence
pro and con, judge this to be so and that not to be so.
Sixthly, finally, rational consciousness is sublated by rational
self-con-sciousness, when we deliberate, evaluate, decide, act. Then
there emerges human consciousness at its fullest. Then the existential
subject exists and his character, his personal essence, is at stake.” (Ibid.,
pp. 20-21)
Thus, says Lonergan, “I have been affirming the primacy of the
existential.” (Ibid., p. 27) This is not a question of
pragmatism. To think of man as an existential subject is to think of
him as basically “concerned with himself or herself as becoming good or
evil . . . .” (Ibid., p. 29)
C. Is the World Good?
This
leads to the question “whether the world is good.” “This question can
be answered affirma-tively, if and only if one acknowledges God’s
exis-tence, his omnipotence and his goodness.” (Ibid., p. 31)
And
this leads us in turn to the comprehensive questions of cognitional
theory, epistemology and metaphysics. We can find answers to the
ques-tions involved in those subjects only if we start from the
existential subject as described.
D. The Conditions of Critical Inquiry
We
have now taken proper note of the nature of the subject in its relation
to objectivity. As a result we are now in a position to understand what
is “meant by inquiry, insight and conception as opposed to sensible data
and schematic images.” (Insight., p. 267) We are now prepared to
ask the question Is it so? But this is a question “not of intelligent
inquiry but of critical reflection.” (Ibid., p. 270)
(1) Defects of Kant’s Transcendental Deduction
Lonergan says that he has performed something similar to what Kant
performed in developing his notion of the transcendental deduction. But
he is quick to point out in what way his deduction brings different
results from those of Kant. (Ibid., p. 339)
Kant
inquired into the
a
priori
conditions of the possibility of experience in the sense of knowing an
object. “We have distinguished two issues; there is the problem of
objectivity, and from this we have carefully prescinded not only in the
present section but also in all earlier sections; there also is the
prior problem of determining just what activities are involved in
knowing, and to this problem we have so far confined our efforts. Hence
we asked, not for the conditions of knowing an object, but for the
conditions of the possible occurrence of a judgment of fact. We have
asked for the conditions of an absolute and rational ‘Yes’ or ‘No’
viewed simply as an act.” (Idem)
A
second difference springs from his immediate interest in the difference
between the thing for us and the thing in itself. In
contrast to Kant we should think of that difference as the difference
between description and explanation, between the kind of cognitional
activities that fix contents by indicating what they resemble and, on
the other hand, the kind that fix contents by assigning their
experientially validated relations. A thing is a concrete
unity-identity-whole grasped in data as individual. Describe it, and it
is a thing for us. Explain it and it is a thing itself. Is it real? Is
it objective? Is it anything more than the immanent determination of
the cognitional act? These are all quite reasonable questions. But as
yet we answer neither ‘Yes’ or ‘No.’ For the moment our answer is
simply that objectivity is a highly complex issue and that we shall
handle it satisfactorily only if we begin by determining what precisely
cognitional process is.” (Ibid., p. 339)
In
the third place, says Lonergan, Kant was immediately interested in the
question of universal and necessary judgements. Kant was immediately
interested in these because he was out to transcend the experiential
atomism of Hume. “But in our analysis they play a minor role. A
universal and necessary judgment may be merely the affirmation of an
analytic proposition, and such analytic propositions may be mere
abstract possibilities without relevance to the central context of
judgments that we name knowledge. Our emphasis falls on the judgment of
fact that itself is an increment of knowledge and, as well, contributes
to the transition from the analytic proposition to the analytic
principle, that is, to the universal and necessary judgment whose terms
and relations are existential in the sense that they occur in judgments
of fact.” (Ibid., p. 340)
A
fourth difference between Kant and himself, says Lonergan, pertains to
Kant’s schematism of the categories. There is for Kant a proper use of
the category, Real, if there occurs a filling of the empty form of Time.
There is a proper use of the category, Substance, if there is a
permanence of the Real in Time. However, Kant’s schematism is not
regarded as one of his happiest inventions. What he was trying to get
hold of was, perhaps, the reflective process of checking, of verifying,
of bringing the merely conceived and the merely given into unity. In
fact, that process is far more complicated and far more versatile than
Kantian analysis would lead one to suspect. Verifying supposes a vast
array of hypothetical propositions that state what would be experienced
under precisely defined conditions. Verifying consists in having those
experiences, all of them, and none but them, under the defined
conditions.
A
fifth difference between Kant and himself, says Lonergan, lies in the
fact that though Kant did postulate an “original synthetic unity of
apper-ception as the
a
priori
condition of the ‘I think’ accompanying all cogitional acts” he has no
room for a consciousness of the generative principles of the categories
. . . .” (Ibid., p. 341) As a consequence we must say that “if
the Kantian proscribes consideration of inquiry and reflection, he lays
himself open to the charge of obscuran-tism. If he admits such
consideration, if he praises intelligent curiosity and the critical
spirit, then he is on his way to acknowledge the generative principles
both of the categories Kant knew and of the categories Kant did not
know.” (Idem)
The
significance of what Lonergan says about Kant can scarcely be
overestimated. His criticism of Kant may well be summed up in what he
says in the following sentences. “But the basis of the Kantian attack
was that the unconditioned is not a constitutive component of judgment.”
(Ibid., p. 173) And Lonergan’s own effort as over against that of
Kant is expressed in the following words: “A complete rehabilitation of
human rational consciousness will show that the unconditioned is a
constitutive component of judgment.” (Ibid., p. 373; in the
original, 340 is erroneously given as the page number, and the quotation
is garbled.—A.F.)
Kant’s view, argues Lonergan, led to the destruction of the possibility
of predication. Kant’s view ended with a final dualism between fact and
interpretation, between knowledge and being. The only way to overcome
that dualism is to begin with the notion that predication is involved in
the very first fact that one observes.
We
must therefore maintain that the virtually unconditioned is involved in
the entire activity of the human consciousness. We shall hear more of
this point ere long.
2. Cognitional Process Involves Being as the Immanent Dynamic
Orientation of the Cognitional Process
We
proceed then to point out, says Lonergan, that “our analysis of the
cognitional process involves the notion of being and that the
spontaneously operative notion of being has to be placed in the pure
desire to know.” (Ibid., p. 353) “Not only does the notion of
being extend beyond the known but also it is prior to the final
component of knowing when being is actually known.” (Ibid., p.
353)
We
conclude then, says Lonergan, that the notion of insight as we have
developed it involves and is involved in the notion of being as
virtually unconditioned. We have herewith reached what Kant was unable
to reach, namely, “absolute objectivity.” “The ground of absolute
objectivity is the virtually unconditioned that is grasped by reflective
understanding and posited in judgment.” (Ibid., p. 377)
3. The Virtually Unconditioned And The Formally Unconditioned
But
Lonergan does not stop at this point. Beyond the “virtually
unconditioned there is the formally unconditioned. The formally
uncondi-tioned, which has no conditions at all, stands out-side the
interlocked field of conditioning and con-ditioned; it is intrinsically
absolute. The virtually unconditioned stands within that field, it has
conditions, it is itself among the conditions of other instances of the
conditioned, still its conditions are fulfilled; it is a
de
facto
absolute.
4. Metaphysics and the Pure Desire to Know
Lonergan continues his exposition of absolute objectivity as follows:
“Again, it is the absolute objectivity that is formulated in the logical
principles of identity and contradiction. The principle of identity is
the immutable and definitive validity of the true. The principle of
contradiction is the exclusiveness of that validity. It is, and what is
opposed to it, is not.” (Ibid., p. 378)
We
have seen, then, that according to Lonergan, the notion of being
underlies, penetrates, transforms, and unifies all other departments of
knowledge. This is, says Lonergan, precisely what must be said of
metaphysics, “for its principles are neither terms nor propositions,
neither concepts nor judgments, but the detached and disinterested drive
of the pure desire to know and its unfolding in the empirical,
intellectual, and rational consciousness of the self-affirming subject.”
(Ibid., p. 390)
In
metaphysics then, abstract deduction must be shunned. We must have
“concrete deduction.” But concrete deduction stands in need of a prior
inquiry. And “this prior inquiry was not conducted with sufficient
generality by Kant, nor with sufficient discrimination by Scotus.
Finally, its possibility was implied by Aquinas, but the varieties of
Thomistic interpretations are as much in need of a prior inquiry as
anything else.” (Ibid., p. 403)
5. Being Is Open and Closed
It
is this “prior inquiry” in which Lonergan has been engaged for many
years. The result of that prior inquiry is the notion of Insight
in its active development in Being. If we were to take the
Parmenidean notion of conceptual understanding and its implied notion of
all reality as one block of static being, we should therewith kill the
idea of dynamic self-affirmation. Of course, we cannot flee from
Parmenides to Heraclitus and his
panta
rei.
Intelligent self-affirmation is discernible growth in our
“understanding” of being, with absolute understanding, i.e., knowing
everything about everything as its goal. Reality must be “closed” but
not in the Parmenidean sense of the term, and reality must be “open” but
not in the Heraclitean sense of the term.
St.
Thomas was deeply conscious of this. Accordingly he employed the notion
of the analogy of being as that which would do justice to man’s
[experience], both the experience of permanence and of change.
6. We Now Have the Answer to Solipsism and Scepticism
St.
Thomas followed the lead of Aristotle but he modified the thinking of
Aristotle so as to make it consonant with his Christian theology.
Lonergan now seeks to show that St. Thomas’ synthesis of Aristotelian
philosophy and Christian theology is the answer to the subjectivism,
relativism and scepticism of modern thought but that this synthesis must
be expressed by means of a more activistic principle than was done by
Thomas himself. We must today lay greater emphasis on the openness of
reality than was done by earlier thinkers. Putting more stress on the
openness of the universe than was formerly done enables us to show
modern science, modern process philosophy and modern process theology
that we are in basic agreement with them on the principle of contingency
which underlies their efforts but that we, not they, can account for the
fact of development toward the goal of perfect knowledge as one with
being. Kant did not have, while we do have an
a
priori
principle of “sufficient generality” so as to be able to account for
newness of experience. As we can answer the rationalism and
indeterminism of a Hume. We can give an intelligible account of the
increment of knowledge toward a “totality of correct judgments.” (Ibid.,
p. 363)
All
depends on conceiving of being “heuristically as the objective of the
detached and disinterested desire to know and, more precisely, as
whatever is to be known by intelligent grasp and reasonable affirmation.
This heuristic notion has been found to underlie all our knowing, to
penetrate all conceptual contents, to go beyond them, and provide a core
for all meaning.” (Ibid., p. 444)
Lonergan uses the notions of potentiality and actuality much in the way
that St. Thomas did and even as Aristotle did.
Involved in these notions is the internal self-sufficiency of human
self-affirmation. Lonergan does not need, indeed has no place for, the
biblical notion of man as a creature of God and as a sinner before his
creator as the reformers set it forth in their writings. For Lonergan,
as for Thomas, man is to be described as basically interpretable in
terms of the analogy of being of St. Thomas. According to Lonergan, as
according to Thomas, there is no “natural man” who is spiritually dead
in sin, who is a covenant-breaker along with Adam (Rom 8:15). On the
Roman Catholic view man’s defects are, as Herman Bavinck says,
metaphysical, not ethical. Lonergan, as well as Thomas, continues to
operate with the notion of the scale of being rather than with the
notions of sin and grace. Man is, to begin with, near to non-being.
Parmenides would say that man as a temporal being is wholly non-being.
But Aristotle has shown that temporal diversity is inherent in being.
To have a unified interpretation of being change must be conceived of
an original aspect of it. Yet there must be a primacy of the
supra-temporal. Potentiality must, in a sense, precede actuality but in
a deeper sense actuality must precede potentiality. Says Lonergan, “I
have been indicating a parallel between incomplete knowing headed toward
fuller knowing and an incomplete universe heading towards fuller being
and now I propose to employ the name, finally, to denote the objective
member of the parallel.” (Ibid., pp. 445-445)
“Basically, then, finality is the dynamic aspect of the real. To affirm
finality is to disagree with the Eleatic negation of change.” (Ibid.,
p. 446)
7. The Notion of God
Near
the end of his work Lonergan takes up “the notion of God.” “If God is a
being, he is to be known by intelligent grasp and reasonable
affirmation. Accordingly two questions arise, what is God and whether
God is. But already we have been led to the conclusion that the idea of
being would be the content of an unrestricted act of understanding that
primarily understood itself and consequently grasped every other
intelligibility. Now, as will appear, our concept of an unrestricted act
of understanding has a number of implications which, when they are
worked out, it becomes manifest that it is one and the same thing to
understand what being is and to understand what God is.” (Ibid.,
pp. 657-658)
Lonergan than proceeds to formulate the notion of God; and, after that
asks “whether this notion refers to existent reality.” We need not
follow Lonergan in the details of his exposition of the notion of God.
The first point he makes is that “if there is an unrestricted act of
understanding, there is by identity a primary intelligible. For the
unrestricted act understands itself.” (Ibid., p. 658)
Secondly the primary intelligible is “also the primary truth,” “primary
being,” “unrestricted act,” “primary good,” “perfect loving,”
“self-explanatory,” “unconditional.” (Ibid., pp. 658-659)
The
“primary being either is necessary or impossible. For it cannot be
contingent, since the contingent is not self-explanatory. Hence, if it
exists, it exists of necessity and without any conditions, and, if it
does not exist, then it is impossible, for there is no condition from
which it could result. But whether it exists or not, is a question that
does not pertain to the idea of being or to the notion of God.” (Ibid.,
p. 659)
Formulating his notion still further Lonergan says that “there is only
one primary being. For
entia
non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem,
and there is no necessity for more than one.” Further, “primary being is
simple.” As a conse-quence “secondary intelligibles are conditioned.” (Ibid.,
p. 660) Again “the primary being is the omnipotent efficient cause,”
and “the omniscient exemplary cause.” Again “the primary being is free”
and “without any increment or change in its reality.” (Ibid., p.
661)
Still further it follows from what has been said about the notion of God
that he “would be the creator,” “the conserver,” (Ibid., p. 663)
“the first agent of every event, every development, every emergent,”
“the ultimate final cause of any universe, the ground of its value, and
the ultimate objective of all finalistic striving.” From this “there
follows a transformation of metaphysics as we have conceived it. For the
metaphysics of proportionate being becomes a subordinate part of a more
general metaphysics that envisages the transcendent idea of being.”
There follows too “a transformation of the ethics based on restricted
metaphysics. For that ethics was concerned with the consistency of
knowing and doing within the individual’s rational self-consciousness.
But now it is clear that true knowledge not only is true but also is an
apprehension of the divinely ordained order of the universe, and that
doing consistent with knowing not merely is consistent with knowing but
also is man’s cooperation with God in the realization of the order of
the universe. Inversely, error becomes a deviation not only from truth
but also from God, and wrong-doing takes on the character of sin against
God.”
A. The Nature of Sin and Evil
Something further must here be said “about evil and sin.” “By basic sin
I shall mean the failure of free will to choose a morally obligatory
course of action or its failure to reject a morally reprehensible course
of action.” “Next, by moral evils I shall mean the consequences of
basic sin.” “Finally by physical evils I shall mean all the shortcomings
of a world-order that consists, in so far as we understand it, in a
generalized emergent probability. For in such an order the unordered
manifold is prior to the formal good of higher unities and higher
orders; the undeveloped is prior to the developed; there are false
starts, breakdowns, failures, advance is at the price of risk; security
is mated with sterility; and the life of man is guided by an
intelligence that has to develop and a willingness that has to be
acquired.”
(1) “Basic Sin” As “The Irrational”
At
this point Lonergan goes more deeply into the nature of “basic sin.”
What is basic sin? It is the irrational. Why does it occur? If there
were a reason for its occurrence it would not be sin. There may be
excuses, there may be extenuating circumstances; but there cannot be a
reason, basic sin consists, not in yielding to reasons and
reasonableness, but in failing to yield to them; it consists not in
inadvertent failure but in advertence and in acknowledgment of
obligation that, none the less, is not followed by reasonable response.
Now
if basic sin is simply irrational, if understanding it consists in
grasping that it has no intelligibility, then clearly it cannot be in
intelligible dependence on anything else. But what cannot be in
intelligible dependence on anything else, cannot have a cause, for cause
is correlative with effect, and an effect is what is in intelligible
dependence on something else. Nor does this conclusion contradict our
earlier affirmation that every event is caused by God. For basic sin is
not an event; it is not something that positively occurs; on the
contrary, it consists in a failure of occurrence, in the absence in the
will of a reasonable response to an obligatory motive.
Finally “God is personal.” Though we began from the highly impersonal
question, What is being?, though we have been working out the
implications of an unrestricted act of understanding in itself in its
relations to the universe, though we have been speaking of an object of
thought, which if it exists, will be known as an object of affirmation
in the objective domain of being, still the notion at which we have
arrived is the notion of a personal being. As man, so God is a rational
self-consciousness, for man was made in the image and likeness of God.
But what man is through unrestricted desire and limited attainment, God
is as unrestricted act. But an unrestricted act of rational
self-consciousness, however objectively and impersonally it has been
conceived, clearly satisfies all that is meant by the subject, the
person, the other with an intelligence and a reasonableness and a
willing that is his own.
Moreover, as the idea of being is the notion of a personal God so too it
implies a personalist view of the order of the universe.” (Ibid.,
pp. 667-669)
In
all this Lonergan has been dealing with the “notion of God.” From this
notion of God we turn to the question whether such a God exists.
“Our
knowledge of being,” says Lonergan, “is by intelligent grasp and
reasonable affirmation. By asking what being is, we have been led to
grasp and conceive what God is. Since it has been shown that being is
the core of all meaning, it follows that our grasp and conception of the
notion of God is the most meaningful of all possible objects of our
thought.”
But,
“Is God, then merely an object of thought? Or is God real? Is he an
object of reasonable affirmation? Does he exist?” (Ibid., p. 669)
8. The Existence of God
But,
though we must thus discuss the notion of what God is before we
ask the question whether God exists, we must not follow the
ontological argument for the existence of God. “All forms of the
ontological argument are fallacious, for they argue from the conception
of God to his existence. But our conceptions yield no more than analytic
propositions. And, as has been seen, one can effect the transition from
the analytic proposition to the analytic principle only inasmuch as the
terms and relations of the proposition occur in concrete judgments of
fact. Hence, while there is no difficulty in so conceiving God that the
denial of his existence would be a contradiction in terms, still that
conception yields no more than an analytic proposition, and the
proposition in question can become an analytic principle only if we can
affirm in a concrete judgment of fact that God does exist.” (Ibid.,
p. 670)
“The
existence of God, then, is known as the conclusion to an argument and,
while such arguments are many, all of them, I believe, are included in
the following general form. If the real is completely intelligible, God
exists. But the real is completely intelligible: Therefore, God exists.
. . .” Being is completely intelligible because “being is the objective
of the detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know, this desire
consists in intelligent inquiry and critical reflection; it results in
partial knowledge inasmuch as intelligent inquiry yields understanding
and critical reflection grasps understanding to be correct; but it
reaches its objective, which is being, only when every intelligent
question has been given an intelligent answer and that answer has been
found to be correct. Being, then, is intelligible, for it is what is to
be known by correct understanding; and it is completely intelligible,
for being is known completely only when all intelligent questions are
answered correctly.” (Ibid., p. 673)
But
we must go even further. Now that we have proved the existence of God,
we must ask “what God is or has been doing about the fact of evil.” (Ibid.,
p. 687)
God
is “the first agent of every event and emergence and development . . .
.” What then about the fact of evil. The solution for the fact of evil
is love. Apart from the surd of sin, the universe is in love with God;
and good will is the opposite of the irrationality of sin; accordingly,
the man of good will is in love with God.
Again, the actual order of the universe is a good and value chosen by
God for the manifestation of the perfection of God. Again, the order of
the universe includes all the good that all persons in the universe are
or enjoy or possess.
But
to will the good of a person; and so to will the order of the universe
because of one’s love of God is to love all persons in the universe
because of one’s love of God.” (Ibid., p. 699)
“There remains the problem of identifying the solution that exists. For
if possible solutions are many, the existent solution is one,
universally accessible and permanent, continuous with the actual order
of the universe, and realized through human acts of acknowledgment and
consent that occur in accordance with the probabilities. . . .” (Ibid.,
p. 729)
Each
man must identify the solution for himself. “None the less, there is
available the critique of erroneous beliefs that has been outlined,” and
none of us need to “labour alone in the purification of his own mind,
for the realization of the solution and its development in each of us is
principally the work of God, who illuminates our intellects to
understand what we had not understood and grasp as unconditioned what we
had reputed error, who breaks the bonds of our habitual unwillingness to
be utterly genuine in intelligent inquiry and critical reflection by
inspiring the hope that reinforces the detached, disinterested,
unrestricted desire to know and by infusing charity, the love, the
bestows on intelligence the fullness of life.” (Ibid., p. 730)
With
this sentence Lonergan’s great work concludes. In an epilogue he says
the “long-suffering reader” might think himself entitled to a summary.
Well, he does give something to help us catch the drift of the
argument. Says Lonergan: “If I have written as a humanist, as one
dominated by the desire not only to understand but also, through
understanding to reach a grasp of the main lines of all there is to be
understood, still the very shape of things as they are has compelled me
to end with a question at once too basic and too detailed to admit a
brief answer. The self-appropriation of one’s own intellectual and
rational self-consciousness begins as cognitional theory, expands into a
metaphysics and ethics, mounts to a conception and an affirmation of
God, only to be confronted with a problem of evil that demands the
transformation of self-reliant intelligence into an
intellectus quaerens fidem.
Only at the term of that search for faith, for the new and higher
collaboration of minds that has God as its author and its guide, could
the desired summary and completion be undertaken; and then, I believe,
it would prove to be, not some brief appendage to the present work, but
the inception of a far larger one.” (Ibid., p. 731)
The
“inner logic” of my work, says Lonergan, “is a process.” Let us,
finally, look at that process “in its ulterior significance.” Let us
ask, “whether it has any contributions to offer to the higher
collaboration which it has envisaged and to which it leads. To this
question the remaining paragraphs of this Epilogue will be devoted and,
as the reader already has surmised, they will be written, not from the
moving viewpoint whose exigencies, I trust, I have been observing
honestly and sincerely, but from the terminal viewpoint of a believer, a
Catholic, and, as it happens, a professor of dogmatic theology.” (Ibid.,
p. 732)
“In
conclusion,” says Lonergan, “I would add that I believe this work to
contribute to the programme,
vetera
novis augere et perficere,
initiated by the encyclical,
Aeterni
Patris,
of His Holiness, Pope Leo XIII.”
Lonergan has, he says, aided us in the understanding of the medieval
mind. He has made “an advance in depth that is proportionate to the
broadening influence of historical research” as it pertains to St.
Thomas. He has taken the “Opera
Omnia”
of St. Thomas and has followed “through successive works the variations
and developments of his views.” In this manner it was possible,
Lonergan argues, to appreciate the fact that the “intellect of Aquinas .
. . reached a position of dynamic equilibrium without ever ceasing to
drive towards a fuller and more nuanced synthesis, without ever halting,
complacently in some finished mental edifice, as though his mind had
become dull, or his brain exhausted, or his judgment had lapsed into the
error of those that forget man to be potency in the realm of being.” (Ibid.,
pp. 747-748)
This
long and penetrating study, Lonergan says, has enabled him to see
[that?] what “the
vetera
really were” [was?] only a skeleton of the multi-faceted argument of his
great book. Lonergan is one of the most outstanding Roman Catholic
philosophers of our day. His aim in all his writing is to show that
when the Roman Catholic life-and-world view is put in modern dress it
will appear to rational men as the most reasonable philosophy of life to
be found anywhere.
Does
modern philosophy, beginning with Kant, insist that the human self must,
before all else, interpret itself in terms of itself; Lonergan does more
so. The whole of his Aquinas lecture on The Subject is devoted
to making this point. The interiority of his subject is
evidence of it. Does modern philosophy, beginning with Kant, as over
against Greek philosophy, make time or pure contingency ultimate in
human experience; Lonergan does more so. In terms of doing more so he
can and does incorporate into his modern Thomism aspects of all the
methods and movements of modern temporalism from that of Heidegger’s
Sein und Zeit
to that of Sartre’s Being and Becoming. If modern philosophy,
beginning with Kant, seek to do better justice to the claims of human
reason as legislative of what can and what cannot be than even
Parmenides did, Lonergan does more so. Lonergan argues, in effect that
one cannot do justice to the legislative rights of “reason” unless one
thinks of them as correlative to the idea of purely contingent
factuality.
In
other words Lonergan virtually seeks to bring Roman Catholic philosophy
up to date by combining the “nature-freedom” scheme of modern thought to
the “form-matter” scheme of Greek thought.
II. Method in Theology
All
of this is, as we have seen, apparent in the epistemology that Lonergan
has worked out in Insight. It is further apparent in his work on
Method in Theology to which we must now turn.
Lonergan informs us that his method is transcendental. From
Insight we have already learned that the cognitive process implies
as it is implied in a transcendental method.
In
his work on method we have this point made more specific than it was in
Insight.
1. The Transcendental Method
It
is of special interest to us to ascertain what a great Roman Catholic
philosopher says about his transcendental method. Yet we need
not quote him extensively on this subject. We already have the basic
epistemology and the basic metaphysic underlying and expressing this
method.
By
and large Lonergan seeks to inform us on the basic conditions that
underlie, i.e., are presup-posed in any act of knowledge on the part of
the human subject. With Kant he wants to ascertain “die
Bedingungen der Erfahrung Moglich Machen.”
Of
course what Lonergan is at the same time seeking to prove is that it is
St. Thomas rather than Kant who has shown us what these conditions are.
Not that he would call us straight back from Kant to Aristotle.
Aristotle was too strongly devoted to the Parmenidean principle that
thought as such can produce knowledge. Knowledge is, for
Aristotle, of universals only. He was therefore enamored of mathematics
as the only true science. According to Aristotle other sciences can be
called sciences “only by courtesy since, as Sir David Ross says, ‘they
are occupied with matters in which contingency plays a part.’” (Bernard
J. F. Lonergan, Method in Theology, p. 3)
Now
time; i.e. contingency, is real. It is not only real but ultimate. How
else would man’s “moral self-transcendence” have meaning? “The concrete
being of man is being in process. His existing lies in developing. His
unrestricted desire to know leads him ever towards a known unknown.”
This is man’s “indeterminately directed dynamism” and this
indeterminately directed dynamism “has its ground in potency; it is
without the settled assurance and efficacy of form . . . .” (Insight,
p. 625)
The
whole of Lonergan’s idea of “emergent probability” presupposes the
notion of pure con-tingency as correlative to logic as pure form. This
notion of emergent probability is Lonergan’s equi-valent of the Reformed
view of God’s providence as controlling whatsoever comes to pass.
Lonergan’s position is not that for man, though not for the
all-controlling God, “combinations of events possess a probability.”
His point is rather that one must talk about events as such as
one must talk of logic as such without bringing in the question
of the relation of God to man.
Accordingly for Lonergan the “world process is open. It is a succession
of probable realizations of possibilities. Hence, it does not run along
the iron rails laid down by determinists nor, on the other hand, is it a
non-intelligible morass of merely chance events. World process is
increasingly systematic. For it is the successive realization of a
conditioned series of schemes of occurrence, and the further the series
of schemes is realized, the greater the systematization to which they
are subjected.” (Insight, p. 126)
A
word must here be added about Lonergan’s view on possibilities as
underlying emergent probabilities. Man must determine what is possible
by means of the law of contradiction. To be sure one must not use this
law in the way that Parmenides used it. By using the law of
contradiction Parmenides “denied both multiplicity and motion.” Denying
“the possibility of becoming as an intermediary between being and
nothing” and thus “precluded any multiplicity of being.” (Method,
p. 91) Surely this must not be. We need the idea of contingency to
account for “becoming,” for the idea of multiplicity of beings and for
the general idea of emergent probability.
But
then these very ideas in turn need the idea of permanence and permanence
springs from no other source but thought. We need to think of the
“actual order of the universe” as an “intelligible unity.” (Insight,
p. 696)
While therefore Parmenides’ “specific achievement” (the idea that all
reality is one static block of being) “was only a mistake, still it
provided a carrier for a breakthrough. Linguistic argument had emerged
as an independent power that could dare to challenge the evidence of the
senses. The distinction between sense and intellect was established.
The way lay open for Zeno’s paradoxes, for the eloquences and the
scepticism of the Sophists, for Socrates’ demand for definition, for
Plato’s distinction between eristic and dialectic, and for the
Aristolian Organon.” (Method, pp. 91-92)
But
we must, Lonergan contends, go even beyond Aristotle. “There can be
little doubt that it was necessary for medieval thinkers to turn to some
outside source to obtain a systematic substructure. There is little
doubt that they could not do better than to turn to Aristotle. But
today it is very evident that Aristotle has been superseded.
Magnificently he represented an early stage of human development . . .
the emergence of systematic meaning. But he did not anticipate the
later emergence of a method that envisioned an ongoing succession of
systems. He did not envision the later emergence of a
Philologie
that made its aim the historical reconstruction of the constructions of
mankind. He did not formulate the later ideal of a philosophy that was
at once critical and historically-minded, that would cut the roots of
philosophic disputes, and that would ground a view that embraced the
differentiations of human consciousness and the epochs of human
history.” (Ibid., pp. 310-311)
2. History
As a
Roman Catholic philosopher Lonergan seeks to show that the
philosophia perrenis
can and must incorporate into its position every advance that any modern
view of philosophy and of science offers. The philosophy of St. Thomas
can and must, in particular, show that its position alone has room for a
truly historical consciousness.
This
appears strikingly in what Lonergan says about such men as Carl Becker’s
and R. G. Collingwood’s view of history and the historical consciousness
as set forth in his well-known work on The Idea of History. Like
other modern historians such as Carl Becker and R. G. Collingwood, says
Lonergan, “insisted on the constructive activities of the historian.
Both attacked what above I named the principle of the empty head.” (Method,
p. 204)
“There has been, then, a Copernican revolution in the study of history
inasmuch as history has become both critical and constructive. This
process is ascribed to the historical imagination and, again, to a logic
in which questions are more fundamental than answers. The two
ascriptions are far from incompatible. The historian starts from
statements he finds in his sources. The attempt to represent
imaginatively their meaning gives rise to questions that lead on to
further statements in the sources. Eventually he will have stretched a
web of imaginative construction linking together the fixed points
supplied by the statements in the sources.” (Ibid., p. 205)
Lonergan gives his evaluation of Collingwood’s approach to the
philosophy of history in the following words: “Such is the Copernican
revolution Collingwood recognized in modern history. It is a view that
cannot be assimilated on naive realist or empiricist premises. As
presented by Collingwood, unfortunately it is contained in an idealist
context. But by introducing a satisfactory theory of objectivity and of
judgment, the idealism can be removed without dropping the substance of
what Collingwood taught about the historical imagination, historical
evidence, and the logic of question and answer.” (Ibid., p. 206)
We
could scarcely find a better entrance into the “imaginative web” of
Lonergan’s delicately nuanced and infinitely extended process of
reasoning than we can from what he says here about Collingwood.
It
is by means of the modern idea of the historical or existential
consciousness as so brilliantly presented by a man like Collingwood that
Lonergan is able to satisfy both the basic demands of the mother-church
and those of modern science and philosophy.
Lonergan has worked out for us a modernized version of the medieval idea
of the scale of being. In course of time human consciousness gradually
emerges from “undifferentiated consciousness.” This human consciousness
develops step by step. There are several stages of differentiation and
specializations in this human consciousness “towards an integration.”
The undifferentiated consciousness survives in the later stages of its
development. (Ibid.,
p. 97)
Through a process of interiorization the human consciousness becomes
aware of the distinction between good and evil. This raises questions
“about the character of our universe.” (Ibid., p. 101) Behind
these questions “there is a basic unity that comes to light in the
exercise of transcendental method. We can inquire into the possibility
of fruitful inquiry. We can reflect on the nature of reflection. We
can deliberate whether our deliberating is worth while. In each case,
there arises the question of God.” (Ibid., p. 101)
Gradually we establish “general theological categories” and from them
derive special theological categories. “In this task we have a model in
the theoretical theology developed in the middle ages. But it is a
model that can be imitated only by shifting to a new key. For the
categories we want will pertain, not to a theoretical theology, But to a
methodical theology.” (Ibid., p. 288)
It
is thus that Lonergan’s existential subject and his transcendental
method provides the philosophical foundation for Roman Catholic theology
and, in particular for its doctrines.
In
our day we no longer operate “from a metaphysical psychology, but from
intentionality analysis, and, indeed, from transcendental method.” (Ibid.,
p. 288) Working by means of “intentionality analysis” and
transcendental method we discover that “the human subject was
self-transcendent intellectually by the achieve-ment of knowledge, that
he was self-transcendent morally inasmuch as he sought what was
worth-while, what was truly good, and thereby became a principle of
benevolence and beneficence, that he was self-transcendent affectively
when he fell in love, when the isolation of the individual was broken
and he spontaneously functioned not just for himself but for others as
well.”
We
proceed further on this way, says Lonergan, and come to various kinds of
love, such as “the love of mankind devoted to the pursuit of human
welfare locally or nationally or globally: and the love that was
other-worldly because it admitted no conditions or qualifications or
restrictions or reservations. It is this other-worldly love, not as
this or that act, not as a series of acts, but as a dynamic state whence
proceed the acts, that constitutes a methodical theology what in a
theoretical theology is named sanctifying grace. Again, it is this
dynamic state, manifest in inner and outer acts, that provides the base
out of which special theological categories are set up.
Traditionally, that dynamic state is manifested in three ways: the
purgative way in which one withdraws from sinning and overcomes
temptation; the illuminative way in which the serenity of joy and peace
reveal the love that hitherto had been struggling against sin and
advancing in virtue.” (Ibid., p. 289)
3. Doctrines
We
see how by his elaborate analysis of the existential subject and by his
application of the transcendental method Lonergan has prepared us for
the acceptance of the doctrines of his church.
Moreover, by means of his intentional analysis and transcendental method
Lonergan has been able to develop the idea of the ever broadening
church.
Friedrick Heiler, says Lonergan, has described seven areas “common to
such world religions as Christianity, Judaism, Islam, Zorastrian
Mazdaism, Hinduism, Buddhism, Taoism.” According to all of these “there
is a transcendent reality.” This transcendent reality is God, and this
God “is immanent in human hearts,” . . . “he is supreme beauty, truth,
righteous, goodness,” . . . “he is love, mercy, compassion,” . . . “the
way to him is repentance, self-denial, prayer” . . . “the way is love of
one’s neighbor, even of one’s enemies” . . . “the way is love of God, so
that bliss is conceived as knowledge of God, union with him, or
dissolution into him.”
Now
it is not difficult to see, says Lonergan, “how these seven common
features of the world religions are implicit in the experience of being
in love in an unrestricted manner.” (Ibid., p. 109) We must
always remember “that God is good and gives to all men sufficient grace
for salvation.” (Idem.)
Lonergan’s philosophy is consistent with the new universalism of Vatican
2. What was implicit in the teaching of Vatican 1 is made explicit in
the teaching of Vatican 2. Its point of view is well expressed by the
theologian Yves Congar, O.P. when he says: “Those who without fault on
their part, do not belong to her, can nevertheless encounter things
which are an occasion for them to express the true inwardness of their
hearts and thus they are able to receive the seed of faith and charity,
in the same way that in the gospel, a disposition of refusal or
acceptance was produced by meeting signs and parables. The great thing
is to decide whether one will seek self or give self. Those who have at
least the beginning of love for God implicitly desire to do his will;
they have an implicit and unconscious wish for baptism and the Church,
and are in some degree related to the mystical body of the Redeemer. . .
. Such an ‘implicit’ desire must normally lead to a formal meeting with
the gospel message.” “Failing that the meeting with Jesus Christ will
take place eschatologically, i.e., at the end. Many people will then
come to know for the first time that face and which they have loved
without being aware of it. At the end when people’s eyes will be opened
will they not say, ‘Fine! Everybody’s here’?” (Yves Congar, The Wide
World My Parish, tr. Donald Attwater, pp. 101-102)
Reasoning in similar fashion Lonergan says that Vatican 2 was concerned
to follow the example of Paul who wanted to be all things to all men.
The church “communicates what God has revealed both in a manner
appropriate to the various differentiations of consciousness and, above
all, in the manner appropriate to each of the almost endless brands of
common sense.” (Method, p. 329)
Turning now to the other side of the coin we observe that Lonergan’s
transcendental method is a criterion by which all are excluded from the
fold who do not operate with the principle of unrestricted love. “The
church is a redemptive process.” (Ibid., p. 364) It is a
redemptive process consonant with the philosophical view of emergent
probabilities developed in Lonergan’s writings. These writings present a
teleology of history that is consonant with Aristotle’s idea of the
analogy of being. It is a teleology of history consonant with Kant’s
primacy of the practical reason. This teleology of history excludes
extreme determinism and extreme indeterminism. It is not as though
there are certain individual men who are either extreme determinists or
extreme indeterminists and must therefore be excluded. The question is
one of “eschatology” rather than one of “history.” The church excludes
no one, but individual men exclude themselves if with such men as
Parmenides or Calvin they allow for no freedom in their systems of
thought or if with such men as Pelagius they allow for no sovereign
grace of God at all.
By
and large then the mother church allows for ecumenism of the sort that
the world council of churches advocates.
Lonergan does not mention Calvin by name. It is obvious, however, that
he would have to exclude Calvin. Lonergan assumes that all philosophy
must begin with the assumption that man can identify himself
independently of the question whether he is created in the image of God.
Consonant with this all-controlling assumption is the idea that this
ultimately self-identifying man can use the laws of his thinking
properly independently of their relation to the providence of God. In
other words Lonergan assumes that the basic contention of Parmenides to
the effect that human logic is legislative for what is possible in the
world is not wrong. Parmenides was wrong only in that he did not think
of logic as a form that needed pure contingent factuality for its
correlative.
Accordingly, in consonance still with his basic assumption with respect
to man’s ability to identify himself in terms of himself, Lonergan
assumes the existence, the idea of pure contingency as the source of all
newness in the universe.
But
then this idea of contingency must not be driven to extremes in the way
that some modern process-philosophers drive it to extremes. These
process-philosophers do not seem to realize that the idea of pure
contingency, as well as pure rationality destroys intelligent rational
experience.
Lonergan’s contribution seems to lie in the way that he works out in
great detail the notion of the Kantian idea of the relation of nature
and freedom as supplemental to the traditional Thomistic-Aristotelian
notion of form and matter.
By
doing this Lonergan gives a magnificently constructed philosophical
basis to the “new theology” of some recent Roman Catholic theologians
and allows the Church assembled in Vatican 2 to develop its doctrine of
the sovereign-universal grace of God.
Lonergan has built an elaborate philosophical support for the church’s
freedom to construct its own theology. He says he is as a methodical
theologian not dictating to the church what the content of its doctrines
must be.
Of
course it is perfectly clear that the only kind of doctrine the Church
will pronounce will be in accord with the type of philosophy that
Lonergan has constructed.
There is great harmony between the new philosophy, the new theology and
the official church pronouncements of Vatican 2.
Moreover, as these three presuppose one another, they constitute
together an effort to bring medieval-philosophy, medieval theology and
the official church pronouncements of the Council of Trent up to date.
Neo-Protestantism
Involved in this effort is the new attitude on the part of Roman
Catholicism toward Protestantism.
This
new attitude toward Protestants finds a striking illustration in Hans
Küng’s great work on Justification (Rechtfertigung—Die
Lehre Karl Barths und eine Katholische Besinnung.)
Küng
argues that Barth and Catholicism must be thought of as allies in the
defense of sovereignty and universality of the grace over against
determinism of the Reformers. Barth and Catholicism have lifted the
whole question of sin and grace out of the predestinarian scheme of the
Reformers. (Rechtfertigung,
p. 58)
It is Barth’s act theology that enables him to escape what he thinks the
nemesis of the theology of the Reformers.
In
his work on The Church Küng develops the universalism of the
message of grace. “The final aim of God’s plan of salvation is not the
salvation of the gentiles, nor the salvation of the Jews, but the
salvation of all men, the salvation of the one and entire people
of God composed of Gentiles and Jews.” (The Church,
p. 147)
Again: “If we wish to insist upon the negative axiom, no salvation
outside the Church, then we must not use it to threaten or damn those
outside the Church, but interpret it as a hope and a promise for
ourselves and our community: it is true for me, we are able to say with
joy, there is no salvation outside the Church for me personally.” (Ibid.,
p. 313)
The
new Catholicism appears to be ready to embrace in its fold all men, so
long as they do not insist on holding a view of reality and knowledge
similar to that of the Reformers. The neo-orthodox position of Barth is
quite acceptable because it has rejected the idea of the atonement of
men’s sins as finished once for all on a calendar day of ordinary
history.
Lonergan’s analysis of the human self and his transcendental method
support the church’s doctrine today as St. Thomas’ modified Aristotelian
supported the church’s doctrines at Trent. The
philosophia perennis
has again shown itself to possess the totality outlook on life that
alone can give men salvation. There is no salvation outside the Church
because there is no man outside the church. To be sure there are many
men outside the church as an institution. But these are still in the
church because they are at one with the teaching of the church on the
basic doctrine of the salvation of all men by the sovereign grace of
God.
This
is strikingly apparent in the teaching of neo-orthodoxy with respect to
Christ. According to Barth God is what he is to man in Christ. Christ
is his work and his work is that of saving all men.
But
even beyond that, orthodox Calvinists are also in the church. No man
can be anywhere else than in the church. To be a man is to be in
Christ. The bitter rebellion of orthodox Protestants is the rebellion of
a child against its father. The father forgives his rebellious child
in advance of its acts of disobedience.
All
this is the essential teaching of both the mother church today and of
the neo-orthodox Protestantism today. And Lonergan’s philosophy is
calculated to support this new theology, this new Christology, this new
soteriology. Lonergan’s virtual support of this union of
neo-Roman-neo-Protestant coalition in theology is based on his
philosophy as a union of the Form-Matter scheme of Aristotle and the
freedom-nature scheme of Kant.
As a
Christian philosopher Lonergan joins with non-Christian philosophers in
a common effort at self-analysis and in a common effort of finding the
presuppositions which make human experience intelligible.
III. Communication
The
study of Lonergan’s philosophy can be very rewarding for those whose
views are informed by orthodox Protestant and more particularly,
orthodox Reformed writers on philosophy and theology. One can only
imagine something of what the nature of a dialogue between Herman
Dooye-weerd and Lonergan would be like. Dooyeweerd has worked out in
great detail a Christian, i.e., a Reformed Philosophy as Lonergan has
worked out in great detail a Christian, i.e. a Roman Catholic
philosophy. Both men speak of the transcendental method as being the
hall-mark of their thinking.
In
recent times, Dooyeweerd has stressed the transcendental as over against
the transcendent nature of his method in the interest of communication
with non-Christian and scholastic thinkers. As a matter of fact there
has been considerable dialogue between Dooyeweerd and Roman Catholic
philosophers. Moreover, at least two doctoral dissertations were
written by Roman Catholics on aspects of Dooyeweerd’s philosophy.
But
this only in passing. We must undertake a brief dialogue with Lonergan.
It
would not matter much which point of com-mon interest between us would
be taken up for dis-cussion first. Lonergan’s view, as noted, while
basically philosophical, presupposes as it is pre-supposed by Roman
Catholic theology. We shall, therefore, obtain the best results if we
offer to Lonergan for his consideration a brief statement of our own
general outlook on life, expressing our-selves, as does Lonergan,
primarily though not exclusively in philosophical terms.
We
shall briefly speak of our view of the self and of our view of the
transcendental method.
1. Calvin on the Self
Lonergan asks the question how it is that I can say I and
mean something. His answer is expressed in his philosophy of being, as
discovered in his analysis of his rational self and in his
interpretation of reality by his transcendental method. Lonergan thinks
that he can identify himself in terms of a modernized Thomistic
philosophy.
But
when I try to say I to myself with the help of Lonergan’s self-analysis,
I fail. To identify itself, Lonergan’s self needs, on the one hand, to
participate in pure rationality or determinism and, on the other hand,
in pure non-rationality or indeterminism. This is true of every attempt
that is made at self-identification on the part of any non-Christian
philosopher. And Lonergan assumes that Christianity has nothing to say
to the non-Christian on this point. To be sure, Lonergan criticizes
non-Christian attempts at self-identification but he does so only on the
ground that they go too far either in the direction of pure contingency,
i.e., of equivocism, or in the direction of pure determinism, i.e. of
univocism. Lonergan takes for granted that it is possible for Socrates
to identify himself if only he does not go too far with Heraclitus into
the realm of pure flux or too far with Parmenides into the realm of pure
static being.
Now
Socrates does indeed identify himself. But he does this in spite of the
fact that he tries to do so in terms of the Parmenidean-Heraclitean
dialecticism and because of the fact that he is what Christ says he is.
When any one tries to identify himself in terms of the
Parmenidean-Heraclitean dialecticism, he has to do so by knowing himself
and all things else exhaustively by becoming identical with all reality
as one block of static being and, at the same time, by being
exhaustively identical with all reality as a bottomless, shoreless ocean
of chance. If on such a principle Socrates were successful in his
attempt at identifying himself he would, at the same time, be successful
in losing himself.
Lonergan’s view of the self, like that of St. Thomas, assumes that man
can identify himself in terms of the Organon of Aristotle, in
spite of the fact that Aristotle has no room for the creation and the
fall of man at the beginning of history. Yet he, as well as St. Thomas,
wants, by his philosophy, to prepare room for a truly Christian
theology. But the theology for which Lonergan makes room thinks of man
as unique because participant in pure contingency and rational because
participant in a timeless principle of rationality. He rejects the idea
of drawing the image of man in terms of the Genesis narrative. (Method,
p. 315) In its place he puts a construction similar to that of
Teilhard de Chardin. “It has been the great merit of Teilhard de
Chardin to have recognized the Christian’s need of a coherent image of
himself in his world and to have contributed not a little toward meeting
that need.” (Idem.) Now, as is well known, it is the principle of
progressive evolution by which Teilhard explains all reality. Claude
Cuénot says of Teilhard’s philosophy that in it “man is truly the key to
things, the ultimate harmony, the hub of the universe, around whom the
elements of the world are distributed concentrically, in accordance with
a definite structure. Synthesis of the cosmic and the human—such is the
profound meaning of the Noosphere.” Then, Cuénot speaks of Teilhard’s
further synthesis, i.e. “that of the cosmological and the
Christological.” “Mankind, dominating and assimilating the universe, has
transformed it into a human home. Christ, through the Eucharist,
assimilates mankind, and, in the process, all the essentials of the
universe. The conclusion from Teilhard’s premises is logical: since
Christ before his death was an integral part of the cosmos, organically
included in the stuff of the universe, then the risen Christ, who can
have been nowise less than he had been before his death, became the
organic center of the cosmos. In all this Teilhard was following the
inspired words of St. Paul, who had already revealed the cosmic
attributes of Christ, conqueror of death. By the resurrection, the body
of Christ became coextensive with the cosmos, to which it had already
been organically bound by the Incarnation, and the Pantocrator of the
ancient Byzantine churches was revealed as the organic center of the
universe and the motive power of evolution. In the cosmic Christ,
Christian realism found its logical conclusion.” (Claude Cuénot,
Teilhard de Chardin, London: Burns & Clates, 1965, p. 122.
Cf. the writer’s Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Presbyterian
and Reformed Publ. Co., Nutley, N.J.)
Cuénot is quite right when he argues that the Christ of Teilhard’s
activism is essentially the same as the Christ of Thomistic
essentialism.
The
“incarnation” of which Lonergan speaks is the same incarnation of which
St. Thomas speaks. And the Christ of Lonergan is, to all intents and
purposes, identical with the Christ-Event of neo-orthodox Protestant.
In Barth’s theology Christ is the only man, i.e., the only true
man. All other men are men by participation. Moreover, according to
Barth, Christ is his work and his work is that of saving all men.
In
the process of the progressive evolution of man and his cosmos man
becomes increasingly aware of his identity, as being that of
participation in the all-conquering Christ-Event.
Lonergan does not pretend to be able to say a syllable about the Self
without, at once, relating it to the cosmos. He knows the self in a way
similar to the way the Greeks, particularly in the way Aristotle knows
the self, i.e., by the idea of the analogy of being, i.e., by the
idea of the correlativity of the idea of abstract chance to the idea of
abstract timeless being. The “essen-tialism” of St. Thomas was built on
the same idea. The difference between Lonergan and Thomas lies in the
fact that Lonergan has made the form of Aristotle’s philosophy more
formal than did Thomas by means of making it more exclusively
correlative to contingency and by making contingency more contingent by
making it more exclusively correlative to form. And making the ideas of
form and matter more correlative to one another, presupposes making the
two together, more obviously, if not more really, the projection of the
would-be original constructive effort of the would-be autonomous man.
Over
against this stands the position of orthodox Protestantism, in
particular that of orthodox Calvinism. In his Institutes Calvin
sets his position on the human self and its world squarely over against
a position like that of the Roman Catholic picture of man and his
cosmos. Man cannot know himself at all, says Calvin, unless he, at once,
sees himself for what God, speaking to him through Christ in the
Scriptures, tells him he is.
In
the beginning God told man what he was. Man cannot say I
unless he says so in response to what God has told him he is. What has
God told him about himself and his cosmos? God has told him that he is
created in the image of God, and that he has the task as God’s
representative to subdue the cosmos to the glory of God.
Man
and his cosmos are alike revelational of the power and glory of God. As
a scientist, as a philosopher, and as a theologian man must consecrate
all things to his maker. But Adam, representing all mankind, disobeyed
God. He refused to act as a re-interpreter of God’s interpretation of
himself and of all the cosmos. He wanted to be as God, i.e., the
original interpreter of himself and his world. He wanted to be his own
law-giver and the law-giver to the cosmos. In Adam mankind declared its
independence of God. In Adam mankind became apostate. Paul speaks of
man, after the fall, as repressing the truth in unrighteousness and as
“dead in trespasses and sins,” as therefore “under the wrath” of God.
But
God sent his only Son into the world to save his people from their sin.
In his own body, on the tree, he bore the sin of his people for them
and set them free from the wrath to come. Having been crucified for
their disobedience he rose again from the dead for their justification.
They are now the heirs of God, and joint heirs with Christ. The Holy
Spirit enables them to repent and believe in him and testifies with
their spirits that they are members of the family of God. When he comes
again to judge all men he will finally acquit them and take them into
his presence.
The
rest of mankind, who have refused to repent of their sin will be cast
out of his presence.
Paul
the Apostle came to tell this story to the Greeks. Some believed but
the many did not. They assumed that this “story” could not be true. It
did not fit in with their uncritically accepted principle of human
autonomy. There cannot have been, they said in effect, the sort of God
and the sort of man this story mentions. Such a God and such a man
would not be intelligently related to one another. The rational
self-consciousness of man, the Greeks contended, demands that any God
speaking to any man must be united to mankind and to any gods that might
exist by means of a principle of rationality and being that informs them
both. If this is not the case, as it is not the case in the case of the
biblical story, then they are both lost in pure contingency.
On
the other hand, the “story” Paul brought to the Greeks could not be
true, the Greeks virtually said, because their rational consciousness
demanded that any man must be distinguished from every other man and
from any of the gods that might exist by their common participation in
purely contingent being. If this were not the case then both man and
God would be lost in blank identity. Now Lonergan works up his
self-analysis in terms of Greek philosophy brought up to date with
modern philosophy. He says that he does not dictate to the theologian
and the church what they may believe or require him as a member of the
church to believe.
Yet,
it is clear that when on Lonergan’s view the Church proclaims Christ as
the Savior of men, this Christ must be the sort of Christ that Teilhard
de Chardin proclaims, and not the sort of Christ that Luther and Calvin
proclaimed.
The
church must not proclaim the Christ that Paul preached to the Greeks.
When Paul required the Greeks to repent in terms of the story of
creation, of the resurrection and the coming judgment, the Greeks were,
in Lonergan’s view, right in refusing to listen to him. When Paul went
on to tell the Greeks that wisdom, the wisdom based on human autonomy,
had been shown to be “foolishness” with God the Greeks were right in
turning from him with disdain. There cannot have been a creation, a
resurrection and a judgment such as Paul proclaimed.
Of
course Lonergan, as well as St. Thomas and the Roman Catholic
philosophers in general, do not put the relation of Christianity and
philosophy in this way. It is of the essence of the Roman Catholic
philosophy of history as a whole that it seeks to synthesize the Greek
and the Christian positions. But such a synthesis is artificial at its
center. What is more serious is that it is destructive of the gospel of
God’s saving grace to men. Instead of challenging the natural man to
repent, the Roman Catholic synthesis establishes him in his notion that
he is not a creature of God who has sinned against his maker and
therefore is rightfully under the wrath of God as he walks the way of
death in this life toward final death hereafter. In teaching a theology
that is consonant with a philosophy such as that of Lonergan the mother
Church today, together with neo-orthodox Protestants, leaves men where
they are, i.e., without God and without hope in the world.
2. The Transcendental Method
We
need not add much now on Lonergan’s view of the transcendental method.
One would think that as a Christian believer he would offer the
biblical story as briefly presented just before as the presupposition of
the possibility of predication. But then that would be, for him as a
Roman Catholic philosopher, to mingle theology with philosophy. On
Lonergan’s view the results of a Christian’s philosophical efforts must
be seen to be true, not because they comport with the truths of the
faith, but because they are in accord with the principles of autonomous
reason.
When, therefore, Lonergan says that his trans-cendental method does
while Kant’s does not indicate the real presuppositions underlying the
fact of human knowledge he says this only because he has made Kant’s
“form” more formal than Kant had made it and has made Kant’s “matter”
more contingent than Kant had made it. Lonergan’s principle of unity,
like that of Teilhard, is flexible enough to include all reality in
oneness of kind from the amoeba to Christ. Modern temporalistic and
existentialistic philosophies have helped him in this matter.
Kant
effected his Copernican revolution from the object to the subject in the
interest of saving the truth in rationalism and the truth in empiricism
by making them correlative to one another and, as such, the projection
of the self-sufficient unity of the human consciousness. Lonergan’s
Copernican revolution from the objective essentialism of the middle age
[sic: Middle Ages] to his stress on subjective existentialism of
modern philosophy is, at best, and at most a refinement of Kant’s
position. The all important point is that underneath Lonergan’s
transcendental method as well as underneath Kant’s transcendental method
is the assumption of human autonomy, the assumption of a non-Christian
principle of unity and the assumption of a non-Christian principle of
diversity. Only the triune God of Scripture is self-sufficient. Unless
we accept on his absolute authority speaking through Christ in Scripture
what he says about ourselves and our world everything we say and do is
futile and worse than futile, we abide under the wrath of God and add to
our sins daily. If we strive to find the conditions of the possibility
of human predication in ourselves we walk on the way of death.
Surely then, as a Calvinist, I should plead with my kind Roman Catholic
friends to forsake their alliance with the natural man and, with us, to
repent and then, by believing the story of Scripture, find that we can
offer men the only conditions in terms of which human predication is
intelligible.