Chapter 6 of Ernst Cassirer, Language and Myth, translated by
Susanne K. Langer, New York, Harper & Brothers, 1946 [Dover
Publications, 1953], 83-99. The book was “[o]riginally published in
German as Number VI of the
‘Studien der Bibliothek Warburg,’
under the editorship of Fritz Saxl” as Sprache
und
Mythos:
Ein Beitrag zum Problem der Götternamen. Leipzig, B. G. Teubner,
1925, 87pp.
This little study, entitled Sprache und Mythos, reveals
the genesis of some of those great conclusions for which he
[Cassirer] is known to the world; it gives one a look into the
mental laboratory where new ideas are generated and developed.
Susanne K. Langer,
Translator’s
Preface
Language and myth stand in an original and indissoluble
correlation with one another, from which they both emerge but
gradually as independent elements. They are two diverse shoots from
the same parent stem, the same impulse of sym-bolic formulation,
springing from the same basic mental activity, a concentration and
heightening of simple sensory experience.
Ernst Cassirer
Posted August 29, 2008
The Power of
Metaphor
Ernst Cassirer
The foregoing considerations
have shown us how mythical and verbal thought are interwoven in every
way; how the great structures of the mythic and linguistic realms,
respectively, are determined and guided through long periods of their
development by the same spiritual motives. Yet one fundamental motive
has so far remained unnoticed, which not only illustrates their
relationship, but offers an ultimate explanation of it.
That myth and language are
subject to the same, or at least closely analogous, laws of evolution
can really be seen and understood only in so far as we can uncover the
common root from which both of them spring. The resemblances in their
results, in the forms which they produce, point to a final community of
function, of the principles whereby they operate.
In order to recognize this
function and represent it in its abstract nakedness, we have to pursue
the ways of myth and language not in their progress, but in regress—back
to the point from which those two divergent lines emanate.
And this common center really
seems to be demonstrable; for, no matter how widely the contents of myth
and language may differ, yet the same form of mental conception is
operative in both. It is the form which one may denote as metaphorical
thinking; the nature and meaning of metaphor is what we must start with
if we want to find, on the one hand, the unity of the verbal and the
mythical worlds and, on the other, their difference.
It has frequently been noted
that the intellectual link between language and myth is metaphor; but in
the precise definition of the process, and even in regard to the general
direction it is supposed to take, theories are widely at variance. The
real source of metaphor is sought now in the construction of language,
now in mythic imagination; sometimes it is supposed to be speech, which
by its originally metaphorical nature begets myth, and is its eternal
source; sometimes, on the contrary, the metaphor-ical character of words
is regarded as a legacy which language has received from myth and holds
in fee. Herder, in his prize essay on the origin of speech, emphasized
the mythic aspect of all verbal and propositional conceptions.
As all nature sounds; so to
Man, creature of sense, nothing could seem more natural than that it
lives, and speaks, and acts. A certain savage sees a tree, with its
majestic crown; the crown rustles! That is stirring godhead! The savage
falls prostrate and worships! Behold the history of sensuous Man, that
dark web, in its becoming, out of verbis nomina—and the easiest
transition to abstract thought! For the savages of North America, for
instance, everything is still animate; everything has its genius, its
spirit. That it was likewise among Greeks and orientals, may be seen
from their oldest dictionary and grammar—they are, as was all nature to
their inventor, a pantheon! A realm of living, acting creatures. . . .
The driving storm, the gentle zephyr, the clear fountain and the mighty
ocean—their whole mythology lies in those treasure troves, in verbis
and nominibus of the ancient languages; and the earliest
dictionary was thus a sounding pantheon.79
The romantics followed the way
indicated by Herder; Schelling, too, sees in language a “faded
mythology,” which preserves in formal and abstract distinctions what
mythology still treats as living, concrete differences.80
Exactly the opposite course was
taken by the “comparative mythology” that was attempted in the second
half of the nineteenth century, especially by Adalbert Kuhn and Max
Müller. Since this school adopted the methodological principle of
basing mythological comparisons on linguistic comparisons, the factual
primacy of verbal concepts over mythic ones seemed to them to be implied
in their procedure. Thus mythology appeared as a result of language.
The “root metaphor” underlying all mythic formulations was regarded as
an essentially verbal phenomenon, the basic character of which was to be
investigated and understood. The homonymity or assonance of denotative
terms was supposed to break and direct the way for mythic fantasy.
Let us consider, then, that
there was, necessarily and really, a period in the history of our race
when all the thoughts that went beyond the narrow horizon of our
everyday life had to be expressed by means of metaphors, and that these
metaphors had not yet become what they are to us, mere conventional and
traditional expressions, but were felt and understood half in their
original and half in their modified character . . . . Whenever any word,
that was at first used metaphorically, is used without a clear
conception of the steps that led from its original to its metaphorical
meaning, there is danger of mythology; whenever those steps are
forgotten and artificial steps put in their places, we have mythology,
or, if I may say so, we have diseased language, whether that language
refers to religious or secular interests . . . . What is commonly called
mythology is but a part of a much more general phase through which all
language has at one time or other to pass.81
Before one can attempt any
decision between these antagonistic theories, this battle for the
priority of language over mythology or myth over language, the basic
concept of metaphor requires scrutiny and definition.
One can take it in a narrow
sense, in which it comprises only the conscious denotation of one
thought content by the name of another which resembles the former in
some respect, or is somehow analogous to it. In that case, metaphor is
a genuine “translation”; the two concepts between which it obtains are
fixed and independent meanings, and betwixt them, as the given
terminus a quo and terminus ad quem, the conceptual process
takes place, which causes the transition from one to the other, whereby
one is semantically made to stand proxy for the other.
Any attempt to probe the
generic causes of this conceptual and nominal substitution, and to
explain the extraordinarily wide and variegated use of this sort of
metaphor (i.e., the conscious identification of avowedly diverse
objects), especially in primitive forms of thinking and speaking, leads
one back to an essential attitude of mythic thought and feeling. Heinz
Werner, in his study of the origins of metaphor, has presented a very
plausible argument for the supposition that this particular kind of
metaphor, the circumlocution of one idea in terms of another, rests on
quite definite motives arising from the magical view of the world, and
more especially from certain name and word taboos.82
But such a use of metaphor
clearly presupposes that both the ideas and their verbal correlates are
already given as definite quantities; only if these elements, as such,
are verbally fixed and defined can they be exchanged for one another.
Such transposition and substitution, which operate with a previously
known vocabulary as their material, must be clearly distinguished from
that genuine “radical metaphor” which is a condition of the very
formulation of mythic as well as verbal conceptions.
Indeed, even the most primitive
verbal utterance requires a transmutation of a certain cognitive or
emotive experience into sound, i.e., into a medium that is foreign to
the experience, and even quite disparate; just as the simplest mythical
form can arise only by virtue of a transformation which removes a
certain impression from the realm of the ordinary, the everyday and
profane, and lifts it to the level of the “holy,” the sphere of mythico-religious
“significance.” This involves not merely a transfer-ence, but a real
μετάβασις εις αλλα γενος; in fact, it is not only a transition to
another category [the meaning of the Greek phrase.—A.F.],
but actually the creation of the category itself.
If, now, one were to ask which
of these two types of metaphor begets the other—whether the meta-phorical
expressions in speech are produced by the mythic point of view, or
whether, on the contrary, this point of view could arise and develop
only on the basis of language—the foregoing considerations show that
this question is really specious. For, in the first place, we are not
dealing here with a temporal relation of “before” and “after,” but with
the logical relation between the forms of language and of myth,
respectively; with the way the one conditions and determines the other.
This determination, however,
can be conceived only as reciprocal. Language and myth stand in an
original and indissoluble correlation with one another, from which they
both emerge but gradually as independent elements. They are two diverse
shoots from the same parent stem, the same impulse of symbolic
formulation, springing from the same basic mental activity, a
concentration and heightening of simple sensory experience.
In the vocables of speech and
in primitive mythic figurations, the same inner process finds its
consummation: they are both resolutions of an inner tension, the
representation of subjective impulses and excitations in definite
objective forms and figures. As Usener emphatically said:
It is not by any volition that
the name of a thing is determined. People do not invent some arbitrary
sound-complex, in order to introduce it as the sign of a certain object,
as one might do with a token. The spiritual excitement caused by some
object which presents itself in the outer world furnishes both the
occasion and the means of its denomination. Sense impressions are what
the self receives from its encounter with the not-self, and the
liveliest of these naturally strive for vocal expression; they are the
bases of the separate appellations which the speaking populace attempts.83
Now this genesis corresponds
precisely, feature for feature, with that of the “momentary gods.”
Similarly, the significance of linguistic and mythic metaphors,
respectively, will reveal itself, so that the spiritual power embodied
in them may be properly understood, only as we trace them back to their
common origin; if one seeks this significance and power in that peculiar
concentration, that “intensifi-cation” of sense experience which
underlies all linguistic as well as all mythico-religious formula-tions.
If we take our departure once
more from the contrast which theoretical or “discursive” conception
presents, we shall find indeed that the different directions which the
growth of logical (discursive) and mythic-linguistic conception,
respectively, have followed, may be seen just as clearly in their
several results. The former begins with some individual, single
perception, which we expand, and carry beyond its original bounds, by
viewing it in more and more relationships. The intellectual process
here involved is one of synthetic supplementation, the combination of
the single instance with the totality, and its completion in the
totality.
But by this relationship with
the whole, the separate fact does not lose its concrete identity and
limitation. It fits into the sum total of phenomena, yet remains set
off from them as something independent and singular. The ever-growing
relationship which connects an individual perception with others does
not cause it to become merged with the others. Each separate “specimen”
of a species is “contained” in the species; the species itself is
“subsumed” under a higher genus; but this means, also, that they remain
distinct, they do not coincide.
This fundamental relation is
most readily and clearly expressed in the scheme which logicians are
wont to use for the representation of the hierarchy of concepts, the
order of inclusion and subsumption obtaining among genera and species.
Here the logical determinations are represented as geometric
determinations; every concept has a certain “area” that belongs to it
and whereby it is distinguished from other conceptual spheres. No
matter how much these areas may overlap, cover each other or
interpenetrate—each one maintains its definitely bounded location in
conceptual space. A concept maintains its sphere despite all its
synthetic supplementation and extension; the new relations into which it
may enter do not cause its boundaries to become effaced, but lead rather
to their more distinct recognition.
If, now, we contrast this form
of logical concep-tion by species and genera with the primitive form of
mythic and linguistic conception, we find immediately that the two
represent entirely different tendencies of thought. Whereas in the
former a concentric expansion over ever-widening spheres of perception
and conception takes place, we find exactly the opposite movement of
thought giving rise to mythic ideation. The mental view is not widened,
but compressed; it is, so to speak, distilled into a single point. Only
by this process of distillation is the particular essence found and
extracted which is to bear the special accent of “significance.” All
light is concentrated in one focal point of “meaning,” while everything
that lies outside these focal points of verbal or mythic conception
remains practically invisible. It remains “unremarked” because, and in
so far as, it remains unsupplied with any linguistic or mythic “marker.”
In the realm of discursive conception there reigns a sort of diffuse
light—and the further logical analysis proceeds, the further does this
even clarity and luminosity extend. But in the ideational realm of myth
and language there are always, besides those locations from which the
strongest light proceeds, others that appear wrapped in profoundest
darkness. While certain contents of perception become verbal-mythical
centers of force, centers of significance, there are others which
remain, one might say, beneath the threshold of meaning.
This fact, namely, that
primitive mythical and linguistic concepts constitute such punctiform
units, accounts for the fact that they do not permit of any further
quantitative distinctions. Logical contempla-tion always has to be
carefully directed toward the extension of concepts; classical
syllogistic logic is ultimately nothing but a system of rules for
combining, subsuming and superimposing concepts. But the conceptions
embodied in language and myth must be taken not in extension, but in
intension; not quantitatively, but qualitatively. Quantity is reduced
to a purely casual property, a relatively immaterial and unimportant
aspect. Two logical concepts, subsumed under the next-higher category,
as their genus proximum, retain their distinctive characters
despite the relationship into which they have been brought.
In mythico-linguistic thought,
however, exactly the opposite tendency prevails. Here we find in
operation a law which might actually be called the law of the leveling
and extinction of specific differences. Every part of a whole is the
whole itself; every specimen is equivalent to the entire species. The
part does not merely represent the whole, or the specimen its class;
they are identical with the totality to which they belong; not merely as
mediating aids to reflective thought, but as genuine presences which
actually contain the power, significance and efficacy of the whole.
Here one is reminded forcefully
of the principle which might be called the basic principle of verbal as
well as mythic “metaphor”—the principle of pars pro toto. It is
a familiar fact that all mythic thinking is governed and permeated by
this principle. Whoever has brought any part of a whole into his power
has thereby acquired power, in the magical sense, over the whole itself.
What significance the part in question may have in the structure and
coherence of the whole, what function it fulfills, is relatively
unimportant—the mere fact that it is or has been a part, that it has
been connected with the whole, no matter how casually, is enough to lend
it the full significance and power of that greater unity. For instance,
to hold magical dominion over another person’s body one need only attain
possession of his pared nails or cut-off hair, his spittle or his
excrement; even his shadow, his reflection or his footprints serve the
same purpose. The Pythagoreans still observed the injunction to smooth
the bed soon after arising so that the imprint of the body, left upon
the mattress, could not be used to the owner’s detriment.84
Most of what is known as “magic
of analogy” springs from the same fundamental attitude; and the very
nature of this magic shows that the concept in question is not one of
mere analogy, but of a real identification. If, for instance, a
rain-making ceremony consists of sprinkling water on the ground to
attract the rain, or rain-stopping magic is made by pouring water on red
hot stones where it is consumed amid hissing noise,85
both ceremonies owe their true magical sense to the fact
that the rain is not just represented, but is felt to be really present
in each drop of water. The rain as a mythic “power,” the “daemon” of
the rain is actually there, whole and undivided, in the sprinkled or
evaporated water, and is thus amenable to magical control.
This mystic relationship which
obtains between a whole and its parts holds also between genus and
species, and between the species and its several instances. Here, too,
each form is entirely merged with the other; the genus or species is not
only represented by an individual member of it, but lives and acts in
it. If, under the totemistic conception of the world, a group or clan
is organized by totems, and if its individual members take their names
from the totem animal or plant, this is never a mere arbitrary division
by means of conventional verbal or mythical “insignia,” but a matter of
genuine community of essence.86
In other respects, too,
wherever a genus is involved at all, it always appears to be wholly
present and wholly effective. The god or daemon of vegetation lives in
each individual sheaf of the harvest. Therefore, an ancient but still
popular rural custom demands that the last sheaf be left out in the
field; in this remnant, the power of the fertility-god is concentrated,
from which the harvest of the coming year is to grow.87
In Mexico and among the Cora Indians the corn-god is supposed to be
present, fully and unrestrictedly, in every stalk and even every grain
of corn. The Mexican corn-goddess Chicomeco-atl in her maidenhood is
the green stalk, in her old age the corn harvest; but she is also each
separate kernel and each particular dish. Likewise, there are several
deities among the Coras who represent certain kinds of flowers, but are
addressed as individual flowers. The same is true of all the Coras’
demoniac creatures: the cicada, the cricket, the grasshopper, the
armadillo are simply treated as so many individual wholes.88
If, therefore, ancient rhetoric
names as one of the principal types of metaphor the substitution of a
part for the whole, or vice versa, it is easy enough to see how this
sort of metaphor arises directly out of the essential attitude of the
mythic mind. But it is equally clear that for mythic thinking there is
much more in metaphor than a bare “substitution,” a mere rhetorical
figure of speech; that what seems to our subsequent reflection as a
sheer transcription is mythically conceived as a genuine and direct
identification.89
In the light of this basic
principle of mythic metaphor we can grasp and understand, somewhat more
clearly, what is commonly called the metaphorical function of language.
Even Quintilian pointed out that this function does not constitute any
part of speech, but that it governs and characterizes all human talk;
paene quidquid loquimur figura est. But if this is indeed the
case—if metaphor, taken in this general sense, is not just a certain
development of speech, but must be regarded as one of its essential
conditions—then any effort to understand its function leads us back,
once more, to the fundamental form of verbal conceiving.
Such conceiving stems
ultimately from that same process of concentration, the compression of
given sense experiences, which originally initiates every single verbal
concept. If we assume that this sort of concentration occurs by virtue
of several experiences, and along several lines, so that two different
perceptual complexes might yield the same sort of “essence” as their
inner significance, which gives them their meaning, then at this very
point we should expect that first and firmest of all the connections
which language can establish; for, as the nameless simply has no
existence in language, but tends to be completely obscured, so whatever
things bear the same appellation appear absolutely similar.
The similarity of the aspect
fixed by the word causes all other heterogeneity among the perceptions
in question to become more and more obscured, and finally to vanish
altogether. Here again, a part usurps the place of the whole—indeed, it
becomes and is the whole. By virtue of the “equivalence” principle,
entities which appear entirely diverse in direct sense perception or
from the standpoint of logical classification may be treated as similars
in language, so that every statement made about one of them may be
transferred and applied to the other. Preuss, in a characterization of
magic-complex thinking, says: “If the Cora Indian classes butterflies,
quite absurdly, as birds, this means that all the properties which he
notes in the object are quite differently classified and related for him
than they are for us from our analytical, scientific point of view.”90
But the apparent absurdity of
this and other such classifications disappears as soon as we realize
that the formation of these primary concepts was guided by language. If
we suppose that the element emphasized in the name, and therefore in the
verbal concept of “bird,” as an essential characteristic was the element
of “flight,” then by virtue of this element and by its mediation the
butterfly does belong to the class of birds. Our own languages are
still constantly producing such classifications, which contradict our
empirical and scientific concepts of species and genera, as for instance
the denotation “butterfly” (Dutch botervlieg), in some Germanic
tongues called a “butter-bird.”
And at the same time one can
see how such lingual “metaphors” react in their turn on mythic metaphor
and prove to be an ever-fertile source for the latter. Every
characteristic property which once gave a point of departure to
qualifying conceptions and qualifying appellations may now serve to
merge and identify the objects denoted by these names. If the visible
image of lightning, as it is fixed by language, is concentrated upon the
impression of “serpentine,” this causes the lightning to become a snake;
if the sun is called “the heavenly flier,” it appears henceforth as an
arrow or a bird-the sun-god of the Egyptian pantheon, for instance, who
is represented with a falcon’s head.
For in this realm of thought
there are no abstract denotations; every word is immediately transformed
into a concrete mythical figure, a god or a daemon. Any sense
impression, no matter how vague, if it be fixed and held in language,
may thus become a starting point for the conception and denotation of a
god. Among the names of the Lithuanian gods which Usener has listed,
the snow-god Bizgulis, the “Shimmerer,” appears beside the god of
cattle, the “Roarer” Baubis; also in relation to these we find the god
of bees, Birbullis the “Hummer,” and the god of earthquake, the
“Thresher” Drebkulys.91
Once a “Roarer God” in this sense was conceived, he could not but be
recognized in the most diverse guises; he was naturally and directly
heard, in the voice of the lion as in the roaring of the storm and the
thunder of the ocean.
Again and again, in this
respect, myth receives new life and wealth from language, as language
does from myth. And this constant interaction and interpenetration
attests the unity of the mental principle from which both are sprung,
and of which they are simply different expressions, different
manifestations and grades.
Yet in the advance of human
mentality even this conjunction, close and essential though it seems to
be, begins to disintegrate and dissolve. For language does not belong
exclusively to the realm of myth; it bears within itself, from its very
beginning, another power, the power of logic. How this power gradually
waxes great, and breaks its way by means of language, we cannot
undertake to set forth here. But in the course of that evolution, words
are reduced more and more to the status of mere conceptual signs. And
this process of separation and liberation is paralleled by another: art,
like language, is originally bound up entirely with myth.
Myth, language and art begin as
a concrete, undivided unity, which is only gradually resolved into a
triad of independent modes of spiritual creativity. Consequently, the
same mythic animation and hypostatization which is bestowed upon the
words of human speech is originally accorded to images, to every kind of
artistic representation. Especially in the magical realm, word magic is
everywhere accompanied by picture magic.92
The image, too, achieves its purely representative, specifically
“aesthetic” function only as the magic circle with which mythical
consciousness surrounds it is broken, and it is recognized not as a
mythico-magical form, but as a particular sort of formulation.
But although language and art
both become emancipated, in this fashion, from their native soil of
mythical thinking, the ideal, spiritual unity of the two is reasserted
upon a higher level. If language is to grow into a vehicle of thought,
an expression of concepts and judgments, this evolution can be achieved
only at the price of foregoing the wealth and fullness of immediate
experience. In the end, what is left of the concrete sense and feeling
content it once possessed is little more than a bare skeleton.
But there is one intellectual
realm in which the word not only preserves its original creative power,
but is ever renewing it; in which it undergoes a sort of constant
palingenesis, at once a sensuous and a spiritual reincarnation. This
regeneration is achieved as language becomes an avenue of artistic
expression. Here it recovers the fullness of life; but it is no longer
a life mythically bound and fettered, but an aesthetically liberated
life.
Among all types and forms of
poetry, the lyric is the one which most clearly mirrors this ideal
development. For lyric poetry is not only rooted in mythic motives as
its beginning, but keeps its connection with myth even in its highest
and purest products. The greatest lyric poets, for instance Hölderlin
or Keats, are men in whom the mythic power of insight breaks forth again
in its full intensity and objectifying power.
But this objectivity has
discarded all material constraints. The spirit lives in the word of
language and in the mythical image without falling under the control of
either. What poetry expresses is neither the mythic word—picture of
gods and daemons, nor the logical truth of abstract determinations and
relations. The world of poetry stands apart from both, as a world of
illusion and fantasy—but it is just in this mode of illusion that the
realm of pure feeling can find utterance, and can therewith attain its
full and concrete actualization.
Word and mythic image, which
once confronted the human mind as hard realistic powers, have now cast
off all reality and effectuality; they have become a light, bright ether
in which the spirit can move without let or hindrance. This liberation
is achieved not because the mind throws aside the sensuous forms of word
and image, but in that it uses them both as organs of its own, and
thereby recognizes them for what they really are: forms of its own
self-revelation.
Notes
79 “Ueber den Ursprung der
Sprache,” Werke (ed. Suphan), V, pp. 53 f.
80 Schelling, “Einleitung in
die Philosophie der Mythologie,” Sämtliche Werke, 2nd div., I, p.
52.
81 Max Müller, Lectures on
the Science of Language, second series (New York: Scribner,
Armstrong & Co., 1875), pp. 372-376.
82 Heinz Werner, Die
Ursprünge der Metapher (Leipzig, 1919), esp. chap. 3, pp. 74 ff.
83 Usener, Göttemamen, p. 3.
84 Jamblichos,
Protreptichos p. 108, 3, quoted after Deubner, Magie und Religion
(Freiburg, 1922), p. 8.
85 See Parkinson, Thirty
Years in the South Seas, p. 7; quoted by Werner, Die Ursprünge
der Metapher, p. 56.
86 Cf. my study, Die
Begriffsform im mythischen Denken (Leipzig, 1922), pp. 16ff.
87 Cf. Mannhardt, Wald- und
Feldkulte, 2nd ed. (Berlin, 1904-1905), I, 212ff.
88 See Preuss, in Globus,
Vol. 87, p. 381; cf. esp. Die Nayarit-Expedition, Vol. I, pp. 47
If.
89 This is the more obviously
valid if we consider that for mythic and magical thought there is no
such thing as a mere picture, since every image embodies the “nature” of
its object, i.e., its “soul” or “daemon.” Cf., for example, Budge,
Egyptian Magic, p. 65:
It has been said above that the
name or the emblem or the picture of a god or a demon could become an
amulet with power to protect him that wore it and that such power lasted
as long as the substance of which it was made lasted, if the name, or
emblem, or picture was not erased from it. But the Egyptians went a
step further than this and they believed that it was possible to
transmit to the figure of any man, or woman, or animal or living
creature the soul of the being which it represented, and its qualities
and attributes. The statue of a god in a temple contained the spirit of
the god which it represented, and from time immemorial the people of
Egypt believed that every statue and figure possessed an indwelling
spirit.
The same belief is held to this
day among all “primitive” peoples. Cf., for instance, Hetherwick:
Some animistic beliefs among
the Yaos of British Central Africa” (see footnote above, p. 70): “The
photographic camera was at first an object of dread, and when it was
turned upon a group of natives they scattered in all directions with
shrieks of terror . . . In their minds the lisoka (soul) was
allied to the chiwilili or picture and the removal of it to the
photographic plate would mean the disease or death of the shadeless body
(pp. 89 f.).
90 Preuss, Die geistige
Kultur der Naturvölker (Leipzig, 1914), p. 10.
91 Usener, Götternamen,
pp. 85 ff., 114.
92 For further details see the
second volume of my Philosophie der symbolischen Formen, esp. pp.
54ff.
Cassirer main page