Preface, dated November 1, 1945, to Ernst Cassirer, Language and
Myth, translated by Susanne K. Langer, Harper & Row, 1946 [Dover
Publications paperback, 1953], vii-x.
Language, “man’s prime instrument of reason, reflects his mythmaking
tendency more than his rationalizing tendency.”
For a fuller treatment of the topic, see her
“On Cassirer’s Theory of
Language and Myth.”
See also Chapter 6 of Language and Myth,
“The
Power of Metaphor.”
Posted August 20, 2008
Ernst Cassirer’s
Language and Myth
Susanne K. Langer
Twenty-two years ago
[1923],
Ernst Cassirer pub-lished the first volume of a work which struck a new
note in so-called “theory of knowledge.” It was called Die
Philosophie der Symbolischen Formen (The Philosophy of Symbolic
Forms). In this work, the “theory of knowledge” became a theory of
mental activity, which gave as minute and scholarly atten-tion to
the forms of feeling and imagination as to the categories of sense
perception and logic.
The book has not yet
[as of 1945*--A.F.]
been translated into English; the only access we
have to his ideas, therefore, is his recent small volume, An Essay on
Man, which presents his main conclusions in brief résumé. But to be
presented with a thinker’s conclusions, not really seeing the path
whereby he reached them, or knowing the first suggestion—the insight or
naïve perception—which opened that path, is unsatisfactory to anyone
whose philosophical interest is more than skin deep.
Now unfortunately, at the time when Professor Cassirer was
engrossed in the first half of his great work—tracing the story of human
mentality before the birth of that rather abstract form of
conception which we call “logic”—he wrote a short but faithful account
of his growing idea, his theory of myth and language. This little
study, Sprache und Mythos, reveals the genesis of some of those
great conclusions for which he is known to the world; it gives one a
look into the mental laboratory where new ideas are generated and
developed.
Americans like to look into laboratories, especially when they know
that something big is in the making there. So this philosophical
fragment which prepares a whole world view is here presented to the
English-speaking public, for the same reason that the Bibliothek Warburg
(one of the world’s great ventures in popular education) saw fit to
publish it originally.
But an expert in his sanctum sometimes appears to make strange
moves, unless we know what he is trying to do. A layman seriously
watching him may well appreciate a tip to that effect from some fellow
worker in the place. Therefore I may be permitted to point out in
advance what Professor Cassirer was undertaking, and how he proposed to
do it.
He was originally struck with the fact that the “theory of
knowledge,” as philosophers had devel-oped it since the Middle Ages,
concerned itself solely with the appreciation of “facts” and the
development of orderly thought about facts. The inveterate belief of
all mankind in myth, sometimes crystallized into dogmas, sometimes
degraded into superstition, was always excluded from the field of
philosophical interest, either as divine revelation, which philosophy
could not touch, or (especially in modern times) as a miscarriage of
logical explanation, a production of ignorance. But the whole realm of
mythical concepts is too great a phenomenon to be accounted for as a
“mistake” due to the absence of logically recorded facts. Mere
ignorance should be agnostic—empty and negative—not exciting and
irrepressible. And it dawned on the philosopher that theory of mind
might well begin not with the analysis of knowledge, but with a
search for the reason and spiritual function of this peculiar sort of
“ignorance.”
Here he was helped by a stroke of insight: the realization that
language, man’s prime instrument of reason, reflects his mythmaking
tendency more than his rationalizing tendency. Language, the
symboliza-tion of thought, exhibits two entirely different modes
of thought. Yet in both modes the mind is powerful and creative. It
expresses itself in different forms, one of which is discursive
logic, the other creative imagination.
Human intelligence begins with conception, the prime mental
activity; the process of conception always culminates in symbolic
expression. A concep-tion is fixed and held only when it has been
embodied in a symbol. So the study of symbolic forms offers a key to
the forms of human conception. The genesis of symbolic forms—verbal,
religious, artistic, mathe-matical, or whatever modes of expression there
be—is the odyssey of the mind.
The two oldest of these modes seem to be language and myth. Since
both are of prehistoric birth, we cannot fix the age of either; but
there are many reasons for regarding them as twin creatures. The
intuitions about nature and man reflected in the oldest verbal roots,
and the processes by which language probably grew up are the same
elementary intuitions and the same processes which are expressed in the
development of myths. They are not the categories and canons of
so-called “discursive logic,” the forms of reason, which underlie
both common sense and science. Reason is not man’s primitive endowment,
but his achieve-ment. The seeds of it—fertile, yet long
dormant—lie in language; logic springs from language when that greatest
of symbolic modes is mature (as it is by the time we meet it in history
or ethnology).
Myth never breaks out of the magic circle of its figurative ideas.
It reaches religious and poetic heights; but the gulf between its
conceptions and those of science never narrows the least bit. But
language, born in that same magic circle, has the power to break its
bounds; language takes us from the mythmaking phase of human mentality
to the phase of logical thought and the conception of facts.
Theory of knowledge has always treated this final achievement as
man’s natural and primitive way of thinking, and taken “facts” as his
earliest stock in trade. Consequently, it could find no connection at
all between myth and truth, poetry and common sense, religion and
science; most of man’s actual ideas, most of his cultural and spiritual
background, had to be discounted as error, caprice, or emotional
indulgence. Professor Cassirer’s great thesis, based on the evidence of
language and verified by his sources with quite thrilling success, is
that philosophy of mind involves much more than a theory of
knowledge; it involves a theory of prelogical conception and expression,
and their final culmination in reason and factual knowledge.
Such a view changes our whole picture of human mentality. The
following pages give the reader the high lights of significant fact
which suggested, supported, and finally clinched the theory. I offer
the translation of this little study (with some slight modifications and
abridgments made by the author shortly before his death) both as a
statement of a new philosophical insight and as a revelation of the
philosopher’s work: his material, his technique, and the solution of the
problem by a final flash of interpretive genius.
* Yale University
Press published Ralph Manheim’s English translations of Volumes I, II, and III
in 1953, 1955, and 1957 respectively, and John Michael Krois’ translation of
Volume IV in 1996, the manuscript of which he and Donald Phillip Verene
prepared from drafts that Cassirer left at his death in 1945. -- A.F.
Cassirer main page