From Neoplatonism and Christian Thought, Dominic J. O’Meara,
ed., International Society for Neoplatonic Studies, Norfolk,
Virginia, 1982, 109-258. Scanned from booklet given me by the later
Father Clarke sometime in the early ‘90s. (It consisted of a
small-font facsimile of the book’s chapter, preceded by its editor’s
preface.)
Anthony Flood
April 14, 2010
The Problem of the Reality and Multiplicity of Divine Ideas in
Christian Neoplatonism
W. Norris Clarke, S.J.
My
purpose in this paper is to trace a chapter in the history of ideas
within the broad stream of Neoplatonism as it passes into Christian
thought. The theme is one that caused special difficulties to
Christian thinkers as they tried to adapt the old wine of
Neoplatonic metaphysics to the new wineskins of Christian theism.
My intention is not to focus in detail on just what each thinker
involved held, as a matter primarily of historical scholarship. My
interest will rather be focused primarily on the basic philosophical
problem itself, and on tracing out the general types of solutions
tried out by various key thinkers along the line from Plato to Saint
Thomas. The problem is this: For Plato and all pre-Christian
Platonists the world of ideas was “the really real”; hence, the
multiplicity of the ideas’ and their mutual distinctions were also
real, though in the mutual togetherness proper to all spiritual
reality. Such multiplicity, however, was not admitted into the
highest Principle, the supreme One, who by nature had to be
absolutely simple to be absolutely one. But the Christian God, as
personally knowing and loving all creatures and exercising
providence over every individual, had to contain this world of
archetypal ideas within his own mind, in the Logos. Yet the real
being of God was also held to be infinite and simple; the only real
multiplicity allowed within it was that of the relational
distinction of the three Persons: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. How
would it be possible to put all these doctrines together without
internal contradiction in a consistent doctrine of God? The story
of the various efforts to meet the problem is a fascinating and
illuminating study in the history of ideas. Let us retrace the
principle moments in it.
Plato
For
Plato himself it is clear that the world of ideas possesses a strong
dose of reality. The breakthrough to discover the abiding presence
of this transcendent dimension of reality, for the first time in the
history of Western thought, must have been a powerful, almost
intoxicating, experience for him, as though a veil had been pulled
aside to reveal at last the splendor of the truly real, in
comparison with which our changing world of sensible objects was
only a shadowlike imperfect image. No modern neo-Kantian or
analytic philosophy reinterpretation of the theory of ideas as
merely conceptual or linguistic categories should be allowed to
vitiate the strength of Plato’s ontological commitment to the
objective reality of ideas, however this be finally interpreted.1
But when we come to the relation between the world of ideas and the
mind as knowing them, clouds of ambiguity begin to thicken. Where
are the ideas? What is their ontological “location” or ground? Do
they constitute an independent dimension of reality on their own,
whose autonomous light is then passively received by any mind
knowing them? Or do they reside in some ultimate mind that supports
them by always thinking about them?
With respect to the human mind it is clear that the world of ideas
constitutes a realm that is ontolo-gically quite independent of our
minds. We do not just make them up; our knowledge is true because
they are there. The matter is more obscure when we come to the
demiurge of the Timaeus. No direct statement is made; but
the images used suggest that the demiurge, in order to create an
ordered cosmos, contemplates and copies an objective world of ideas
that is already given even for him; it is the natural object of his
contemplation, as it is for all the gods and unfallen souls who
drive their chariots across the eternal heaven of ideas, but it is
not something they think up or produce out of their own substance
but which they gaze on as already given. Contemplation, the highest
act of any Platonic mind, is a motionless reception, not a
productive act.2
This leaves the ultimate status and ground of the world of ideas
veiled in obscurity for Plato. The sparsely adumbrated doctrine of
the One and the Good as the ultimate source for both ideas and minds
does significantly complete the picture. But it is never made clear
whether the Good is a mind or something above it, whatever that
might mean. There are indeed highly significant hints in the
Timaeus and the Sophist that the whole world of ideas is
part of a single great living unity. But the generation of the
world of ideas by the Good, even if conceived as ultimate mind,
which Plato never calls it, is quite compatible with the objective
reality and the multiplicity of this world as the really real. In
any case, the ultimate relation between the world of ideas and mind
remains unfinished business in Plato, a legacy for his successors to
unravel.
Plotinus
When we come to Plotinus—I will pass over the intermediate
preparatory stages of Middle Platon-ism—a major resolution of the
problem has been achieved, but with serious internal tensions still
re-maining. On the one hand, the ideas are now firmly located
ontologically within the divine Nous; they no longer float in
ambiguous ontological independence, but are eternally thought by
this eternal mind as its connatural object. As a result the ideas
themselves, though immutable, immaterial, and eternal, are alive
with the very life of the divine Mind itself, each one a unique,
self-thinking, spiritual perspective on the whole of reality.
On
the other hand, there still remains a strong dose of the old
Platonic realism of ideas, and this creates a tension between two
somewhat conflicting perspectives on the status of the ideas in
Plotinus—a tension that it does not seem to me that he com-pletely
resolves. This tension concerns the relation of priority between
the Nous and the ideas: Is the Nous absolutely prior
in nature (not, of course, in time) to the ideas, the realm of
authentic being, as generative act to its product? Or do the ideas
have a certain priority over the Nous as the true existence
over the act that contemplates it? Or is there simultaneous
reciprocal dependence, inherence, or even identity without any
priority at all?
We
would be tempted at first, viewing the problem from within the
central dynamic perspective of the descending flow of emanation from
the One, to assert that obviously the Nous (or Intellectual
Principle) has priority over the realm of being or ideas, as their
generating source. As the Nous, emanating from the One,
turns back toward the One in its first ontological “moment,” as an
empty and formless ocean of potentiality, it is fecundated, so to
speak, by its contemplation of the splendor of the One and bursts
forth into producing the whole multi-ple world of ideas in atemporal
ordered sequence (corresponding to the inner order of the
intelligible numbers, one, two, . . .).3
This dynamic perspective is certainly present in Plotinus, but
surfaces only occasionally and briefly. I might add, speaking in my
own name as a philosopher, that in this direction lies, it seems to
me, the only satisfactory metaphysical explanation of the relation
between mind and ideas: the absolute priority of mind, as ultimate
spiritual agent, over all ideas; existential act must always precede
idea. This perspective gradually became dominant in Neoplatonism,
both Christian and Islamic, after Plotinus, and in most modern
thought. But it is still a minor chord in Plotinus himself.
There is another and more prominent perspective in Plotinus,
however, which runs through the whole gamut of his works, both early
and late; here the old Platonic priority of being over intelligence
still stubbornly holds on and is never explicitly negated by
Plotinus. This can be found especially in Ennead V, 9, “The
Intellectual Principle, the Ideas, and the Authentic Existent,” a
very early treatise (no. 5) in chronological order. The first point
developed here is that the ideas cannot be outside the Intellectual
Principle, otherwise its truth would be insecure and its knowledge
imperfect. The ideas must thus be part of the very self of the
Nous, identical with its being as a single unitary life flowing
through all the distinct parts. But Plotinus goes on to say more,
giving a certain priority to the ideas over the Nous as
thinking principle, so that they seem to constitute the very life of
the Nous itself.
Being true knowledge, it actually is everything of which It takes
cognizance; it carries as its own content the intellectual act and
the intellectual object since it carries the Intellectual Principle
which actually is the Primals and is always self-present and is in
its nature an Act . . . but always self-gathered, the very Being of
the collective total, not an extern creating things by the act of
knowing them. Not by its thinking God does God come to be; not by
its thinking Movement does movement arise. Hence it is an error to
call the Ideas intellections in the sense that, upon an intellectual
act in this Principle, one such idea or another is made to exist or
exists. No: the object of this intellection must exist before the
intellective act (must be the very content not the creation of the
Intellectual Principle). How else could this Principle come to know
it. . . .
If the Intellectual Principle were envisaged as preceding Being, it
would at once become a Principle whose expression, its intellectual
Act, achieves and engenders the Beings; but, since we are compelled
to think of existence as preceding that which knows it, we can but
think that the Beings are the actual content of the knowing
principle and that the very act, the intellection, is inherent to
the Beings, as fire stands equipped from the beginning with
fire-act; in this conception the Beings contain the Intellectual
Principle as one and the same with themselves, as their own
activity. But Being is itself an activity; there is one activity,
then, in both or, rather, both are one thing.4
The
above presents a significantly different per-spective: here the
inner being and act of the ideas seems to constitute the very act of
the Nous itself, rather than the Nous giving them its
own being by actively thinking them up. The older Platonic
conception of mind, here faithfully reproduced, seems to be that
mind as such, even the divine Mind, is by nature contemplative, not
constitutive, of its object. This position, however, leaves open
the difficulty we saw earlier in Plato, that is, what is the
ultimate ground for the unified multiplicity of the world of ideas?
It seems to be an exigency for intelligibility that only the active
power of a unitary mind can ground both the multiple reality of the
ideas and their mutual correlation into a single unified system.
That is why the later more dynamic per-spective in Plotinus, that
of the Nous as generative of the world of ideas, is more
metaphysically satisfying, and is the one that actually dominated in
the subsequent history of Neoplatonism.
Even though priority is occasionally given to Nous over the
ideas, the strong realism of the ideas still remains undimmed in
Plotinus. And it is this that forbids allowing the world of ideas
to be in the One. Since the ideas are really real, true being, and
really multiple or distinct, and the One as pure unity cannot
tolerate the slightest shadow of multiplicity within itself, even
that between mind and idea, the entire world of ideas or true being
must be relegated to a lower level of divinity, the second
hypostasis or Nous.5
The Early Christian Fathers
When the first philosophically minded and trained Christian thinkers
took over the Neoplatonic philoso-phical framework to use in the
intellectual explication of their faith, during the third and fourth
centuries, they had to make two drastic changes in the matter which
concerns us. First, the subordinationist hierarchy of divine
hypostases in Plotinus had to be condensed into a single supreme
divine principle, in which the three Persons within the divine
nature were perfectly coequal in perfection of being, distinguished
only by internal relations of origin, not by differing levels of
perfection. Thus the Word or Logos, the Second Person,
corresponding analogous-ly to Plotinus’ Nous, was declared
perfectly coequal with the Father (corresponding analogously to
Plotin-us’ One) sharing the identical divine nature and perf-ection.
Secondly, the single supreme God of the Christians was identically
creator of the universe through knowledge and free act of love, and
exer-cised personal providence over each and every indi-vidual
creature. This required that the one divine Mind, the same for all
three Persons but attributed by special aptness to the Word or
Logos, contain the distinct knowledge of every creature as well as
the universal archetypal ideal patterns guiding the creation of the
world according to reason. The old Platonic and Neoplatonic world
of ideas, enriched with the distinct knowledge of individuals, is
now incorporated directly into the one supreme divine nature itself.
Christian thinkers simply had to do this to do justice to their own
revelation, and they had no hesitation, but rather took pride, in
doing so.
The
metaphysical repercussions, however, of making the above changes in
Neoplatonic tradition were of seismic proportions, and did not seem
to be recognized very clearly for some time in their full
philosophical implications. Two basic Neoplatonic axioms have now
been violated. First, knowing a dis-tinct multiplicity of objects,
even only as ideas, is no longer considered an inferior mode of
being, wea-kening and compromising the radical purity of unqualified
unity and simplicity in the One. To know multiplicity is no longer
a weakness, but a positive perfection, part of the glory, of a One
that is person-al. To know multiplicity is not to
become multiple oneself. Secondly, purely relational
multiplicity even within the real being or nature of the One is no
longer a compromise or destruction of its unity, but an enrichment.
The highest form of unity is now not aloneness but communion of
Persons with one mind and will. We are not concerned here with this
second principle, relational multiplicity within the nature of the
One. Our concern is limited to the status of the world of ideas
within the divine Mind.
It
was one thing for Christian thinkers to assert that the world
of ideas must be within the divine Mind as Logos, in order that God
may personally know and love his creatures. But it is another thing
to come to grips successfully with the metaphysical problems
involved in thus adapting the Neoplatonic doctrine of the world of
ideas. In particular, what about the strong realism of ideas as
true being, the really real, which was so deeply ingrained in the
whole Platonic tradition, no less, in fact even more, in Plotinus
than in Plato himself? If the ideas remain, as always in this
tradition, true and real being, they must also be really multiple.
Does this not introduce an immense multiplicity of real beings, an
immense real pluralism, within the very being of God himself, thus
negating his infinite simplicity? In orthodox Christian doctrine,
as it was gradually worked out, the only distinct realities allowed
in God were relations, and the only real relations allowed were
relations of origin resulting in the three Persons. But if all the
divine ideas are also authentic, hence, real being, and at the same
time distinct from each other in the intelligible (real) order, then
there is not only a multiplicity of distinct real beings within God
himself but a still greater multiplicity of real relations bet-ween
them. For the relations between ideas are clearly distinctly
intelligible, and for every traditional Platonist whatever is
intelligible is also real.6
It
is not clear to me that the Greek Fathers ever came to grips
explicitly with this metaphysical problem of the reality of the
divine ideas in God, aside from asserting that God knew them all
with a single act of knowledge, which Plotinus would also admit. (I
would be very happy to receive any information from my colleagues on
this point, since patristics is not my field and I have not had the
time in preparing this paper to do extensive study on this point.)
My general impression is that we will have to wait till a later
period to find explicit metaphysical discussion on this point.
Let
us turn briefly to Saint Augustine in the West, as a prime example,
it seems to me, of avoiding the issue. He holds simultaneously two
metaphysical doctrines that I do not see that he has brought
toge-ther in a consistent whole. On the one hand, one of his
central doctrines, learned, as he tells us, from the Platonists, is
that of divine exemplarism, namely, that the divine Mind contains
the ideal exemplars, the rationes aeternae, of all created
things, accord-ing to which he creates them by willing them to be,
to be expressed, outside of himself as real creatures, as
real essentiae.7
It should be noted along the way that Augustine is careful not to
call the divine ideas essentiae aeternae, the eternal
essences of things, but only rationes aeternae—eternal
“reasons” or ex-emplary ideas, models. Since the concrete term
ens, entia did not yet exist in Latin in Augustine’s time—it was
introduced deliberately by Boethius centuries later—essentia
was the standard noun derivative from the verb esse used in
Augustine’s time for referring to existential being.8
Hence, on the one hand, one might be led to believe that these
rationes aeternae were not considered by Augustine to be a realm
of true being, in God, since the entire universe of real being was
created in time freely, not from all eternity, as these rationes
necessarily existed in the mind of God.
On
the other hand, when Augustine comes to an explicit discussion and
definition of what it means to be—to be a being—his criterion of
true being is quite unambiguously the old Platonic one of
immutability; to be is to be immutable, to be
identically and immutably what one is. His texts could hardly be
more forceful:
There is only one immutable substance or essence, which is God, to
which being itself (ipsum esse), from which essence draws its
name, belongs supremely and in all truth. For that which changes
does not keep its very being, and that which is capable of changing,
even if it does not change, is capable of not being what it was.
There only remains, therefore, that which not only does not change
but is even absolutely incapable of changing which we can truthfully
and honestly speak of as a being.9
Being (esse) is the name for immutability (incommutabilitatis).
For all that changes ceases to be what it was and begins to be what
it was not. True being, authentic being, genuine being is not
possessed save by that which does not change.10
Being (esse) refers to that which abides. Hence that which
is said to be in the supreme and maximal way is so called because of
its perdurance in itself.11
All change makes not to be what once was; therefore he truly is who
is without change.12
The
difficulty here for a Christian thinker is that this criterion for
true being is verified perfectly by the divine ideas, as well as by
God himself in his own being. The ideas in God are indeed eternal
and immutable, as the ideal pattern for all creatures and the ground
for all truth, which by its nature must be immutable. Since they
perfectly verify the criterion, they should indeed be true being,
real being for Augustine, just as they were for Plato and Plotinus,
from whom the doctrine of divine ideas was directly inherited. Yet
strangely enough, Augustine never quite seems to draw this
conclusion and speak explicitly of the divine ideas as real being in
themselves. He just seems to drop the point, to pull back into
discreet silence just before he gets into metaphysical trouble. It
is, however, common Augustinian doctrine that things are present
more truly and nobly in the divine ideas of them than in their
mutable, imperfect, created existence. Perhaps he did not see
clearly the difficulty of the ideas as real multiplicity in God, as
did Plotinus; or perhaps he did see it, but did not know quite what
to do with it, and just quietly let it drop. At any rate, he gives
us no clear philosophical principles by which to solve it.13
John Scottus Eriugena
Let
us now skip to a later Christian Neoplatonist, the early medieval
thinker John Scottus Eriugena, whose thought has the advantage for
our purposes of bringing together both the Augustinian and the
Dionysian traditions. Its special interest lies in that the
problems that remained latent and untreated by Saint Augustine now
come out into the open with striking sharpness in this daring but by
no means always consistent thinker.
The
point that concerns us is the ontological status of the second
division of nature in the vast cosmic schema of John Scottus’ De
Divisione Naturae, namely, natura creata et creans. This
comprises the divine exemplary ideas or, as he calls them, the
“primordial causes,” which are the “first creation” of God,
coeternal with the divine Word, but always dependent on the Word, in
whom they subsist. They are created but also creating in their
turn, charged with the power to unfold and produce the whole
material cosmos spread out in space and time.14
The
first point to notice is the strong Platonic realism of this realm
of creative ideas. This is the realm of true being below God (who,
for John Scottus, is the superessential Source above being itself).15
It is in this ideal realm that all creatures, especially the
sensible world of creation, have their true being, perfect and
immutable; they are more real, they more truly exist, in these
eternal idea-causes than in themselves as the explicated effects or
emanations of these causes, for the latter are not merely abstract
ideas or static models but causal forces charged with creative power
of their own, though deriving, of course, from their higher
Principle. Thus each one of us exists more truly in the eternal idea
of man than in our own temporally spread out existence in this lower
material world. We have here one of the strongest statements of
what is to be a favorite theme of Christian Neoplatonists all
through the Middle Ages, at least in the pre-Scholastic period.16
The
realism of these primordial causes is also borne out by the
assertion that they have been “made,” “formed,” “created” by God as
the first level of creation—a stronger term than any previous
Christian thinker had used to refer to the divine ideas, though, to
do him justice, he sometimes warns that “created” here is not used
in as strong and proper a meaning as its ordinary sense as applied
to the second creation, that of the present contingent world. These
primordial causes are produced by the Father in the
Word from all eternity, in whom they subsist; yet as made (produced)
they deserve to be called created. But what is created by God and
which, itself, has causal power must certainly be real, and because
immutable, also eternal, and spiritual, that is, authentic being, of
which the changing world of bodies is but a shadowy image or
participation. No statements of Augustine about the being of this
realm of divine ideas are nearly as strong and clear as those found
in John Scottus. It looks as though the Neoplatonic world of true
being in the Nous has reappeared with new vigor and splendor.
It
is a little surprising, therefore, to discover that, when Eriugena
comes to speak of the mode of being of these primordial causes in
the Word, with respect to their real multiplicity and distinction,
he asserts in the strongest possible terms that in the divine Word
they are absolutely “simple, one, unseparated,” perfectly identical
with the Word’s own being, and “indistinguishable, without
differentiae,” until they unfold in their actual effects in the
space-time sensible world.17
To illustrate how they subsist in simply unity in the Word, he uses
the example of how all numbers are present in the monad before
division and how all lines are present in the point that is the
center of a circle, with no distinction until they begin to unfold
from the center.
Here I have the impression that Eriugena is being a better Christian
than a Neoplatonist. I do not see how he can consistently hold both
the real being and plurality of the primordial causes and also their
perfect simplicity, unity, and identity with the Word as subsisting
in it. Plotinus in fact holds the exact opposite, and would object
as follows: The way that all numbers are in the number one and all
lines in the point at the center of the circle is indeed the way
that all things are precontained in the highest principle, the One,
who is “the potentiality of all things” (dynamis pantōn)
without being any of them. But this is not the way the ideas, the
realm of true being, are in the second hypostasis, the Nous.
There they are indeed held together in the unity of a single
undivided spiritual life of intelligence; but this unity is a
complex unity, not a simple one; it includes all the distinct
intelligibilities of each Idea-Being as intelligibly distinct
(though not separated or divided), as well as the distinction
between the Nous as subject and the realm of being as
intelligible object. It is precisely because of this multiplicity
that the world of ideas can have no place in the perfect, simple
unity of the One, but only in a lower, less unified hypostasis.18
But
there seems to be no trace in Eriugena of these reservations about
the perfect unity and simplicity of the primordial causes in the
Word. It is not clear how he can have it both ways, though if he is
to remain both a good Christian and a good Neoplatonist he must try.
Here we have the latent tension between the conflicting demands of
the two traditions coming sharply to a head, since Eriugena pushes
each one all the way to the limit. It is a remarkable case of the
coincidence of opposites. If one looks at this apparent impasse as
a speculative philosopher, there seems to be only one possible way
in which one could hold onto both sides of the opposition without
contradiction, although this “solution” brings its own new train of
problems with it. Suppose that one were to hold that true being,
the very being of the primordial causes, is nothing else but
their being thought by God. Their truth is identical with their
being. In this case since the act of knowing or thinking them is
one single simple act, and they have no other being save
their being thought, it could be said that their being, as identical
with the act of thinking in the Word and never really emanating out
from it to possess their own distinct being—until, of course, they
are unfolded in the material cosmos—is really one single simple
being identical with the Word.
In
fact, it seems that this is precisely what Eriugena himself has
followed, at least in certain of his strong formulations, such as:
For
the understanding of all things in God is the essence of all things
. . . all things are precisely because they are foreknown. For the
essence of all things is nothing but the knowledge of all things in
the Divine Wisdom. For in Him we live and move and have our being.
For, as St. Dionysius says, the knowledge of the things that are is
the things that are.19
For
the understanding of things is what things really are, in the words
of St. Dionysius: “The knowledge of things that are is the things
that are.”20
It
is true that Eriugena does qualify this identity here and elsewhere
by calling the divine knowledge the cause of the things that are, so
that cause and effect would seem to be distinguished. But if this
distinction is pushed too far, hardened into the strong Aristotelian
real distinction between cause and effect—and I think this is also
true in its own mitigated way in Neoplatonism—then his position on
the unity, simplicity, and identity of the primordial causes in the
Word will collapse. Only in the relation between thought and its
self-generated ideas can there be a real identity of being between
cause and effect, granted that the ideas have no being of their own.
I
have two remarks to make about this doctrine of the identity of
thought and being in Eriugena. First, if this is the case, it is
now easy to understand how all creatures can be more truly in God,
that is, in his knowledge, than in themselves, since it is this
knowledge that in fact constitutes their true and perfect being.
Another daring doctrine of Eriugena also becomes clear: in a sense,
man himself is the creator of the material world, because he holds
it together in unity in his own mind, as participating in the divine
wisdom, and the material world exists more truly and perfectly even
in man’s mind than in itself. Again true being is identical with
being known. We are here on the edge, if not over the edge, of
something like the Hegelian mode of idealism, as has often been
pointed out. We will consider the philosophical difficulties of
this position later.
Secondly, it seems to me that here Eriugena has gone farther than
Plotinus and classic Neoplatonism itself, and in a sense
dramatically reversed the old Platonic realism, which on the other
hand he seems to be strongly asserting and certainly wishes to
assert. For in the Plotinian Nous, or world of true being,
as we have seen, even though the ideas are held together in the
unity of a single unified spiritual life, the act of divine
intelligence, still this life, this unity of the world of being and
knowing, is a multiplex unity, an intelligible (hence, real)
diversity in unity and unity in diversity. The ideas truly emanate
from the Nous, while remaining within it, to the extent that
they are distinguished as subject and object; also the ideas truly
have being within them, so much so that it is almost equally
legitimate to say that the Nous itself is constituted in
being by its union with the ideas as to say that the ideas are
constituted in being by the Nous—there is a kind of
reciprocal priority between them; a strong dosage of the old
Platonic realism of ideas as in themselves true being still remains.
Nothing like this can be found in Eriugena. In no way can it be
said that the Word for him is constituted by the ideas it eternally
thinks. The relation of dependence is strictly one-way,
asymmetrical. His solution is Christian; can it still be called
authentically Neoplatonic? I doubt it.
Let
us now turn briefly to some of the purely metaphysical difficulties
inherent in the Neoplatonic side of Eriugena’s doctrine of the
divine ideas as true being, with the result that we, like all
creatures, exist more truly in our primordial idea-causes in God
than in our own “explicated” temporal existence in our-selves—the
third division of nature, that which is created but does not create.
If this position is taken literally and in full seriousness, then
the problem arises, What is the point of this unfolding of our true
being, already present from all eternity in God, into our present
lesser mode of existence? What is the point of our existential
struggle for salvation in human history in a lesser mode of being
when we are already perfect in our truest being in God? The whole
value of human history, including that of the Incarnation and
temporal life of Christ himself, seems to become so secondary and
“accidental,” as he puts it, that it becomes disturbingly ambiguous,
if not tinged with unreality. His only answer seems to be the
classic Neoplatonic one, a purely impersonal kind of metaphysical
law of emanation—that the emana-tion must go on to its furthest
multiplicity, that the Craftsman of the universe would not have
shown forth the fullness of his power unless he had made all that
could be made and unfolded all the oppositions between creatures and
not just their harmonies. It should be remembered that in the
second division of nature, the primordial causes, there are no
oppositions or differentiae between the various genera and
species; all is perfect togetherness.
This is a typical Neoplatonic theme or axiom of emanation, that the
great chain of being must unfold all the way to the limit of its
possibilities, by an inherent necessity of the self-diffusiveness of
the Good. But such a view of the value and meaning of the
contingent world as only an inferior ontological state of the same
world at a higher level is hardly compatible with the inspiration of
Christian personal-ism, where the supreme locus of value is the
existen-tial dimension of freely given personal love, moral
nobility, and so on. The subject of the salvific redem-ption of
Christ and the final beatific vision in the heavenly Jerusalem is
not the eternally perfect, im-mutable idea of man, but the unique
contingent indi-vidual John Smith who has worked out his salvation
freely with the help of God on the stage of human history. In a
word, there is a profound metaphysical, epistemological, and
religious ambiguity in the Neoplatonic conception of the relation of
the ideas to true being, not indeed in the presence of exemplary
ideas of all things in God, but in their ontological evaluation,
namely, that the true being of anything is found more fully, as true
being, in its idea state in the mind of God than in itself. The
classic Neoplatonic worldview of reality is not ultimately a
personalism. The tension, if not contradiction, between this
meta-physical view of reality and that implicit in any authentic
Christian personalism seems to me to be profound and irreconcilable;
it remains one of the central unsolved problems haunting Christian
Neoplatonists—also, I might add, Islamic and Sufi Neoplatonists—throughout
the pre-Scholastic Middle Ages. To sum it up, as this problem
surfaces in John Scottus Eriugena, I do not think he can hold, if he
is to be a consistent and authentically Christian thinker, both
that the primordial causes are absolutely simple and one in the
Word, which a Christian must hold, and that the true being of
all creatures resides in these divine ideas, rather than in their
own contingent being in history, which a traditional Neoplatonist
should hold. One of these two positions will have to give way if a
consistent Christian metaphysics is to develop. But for this we
have to look beyond the daring and seminal, but not always
consistent, brilliance of John Scottus Eriugena.
In
thus casting doubts on the metaphysical consistency and Christian
assimilability of the cher-ished Neoplatonlc theme that our true
being is found in, consists in, the eternal idea of ourselves in the
mind of God, I do not wish to deny the power and fruitfulness of the
theme as it functioned—under-stood somewhat loosely, without
pressing its meta-physical implications too rigorously—as a guide
for spiritual development in the rich flowering of Chris-tian
spirituality during the Middle Ages. The oper-ative concept here is
that we understand our true self and come to realize it by turning
toward and striving to fulfill the ideal model or exemplar of our
fulfilled selves that God holds eternally to his mind and draws us
toward by the magnetism of his goodness. Our true selves are indeed
seen in God’s ideas of us, and this vision is pregnant with
the magnetic drawing power of the Good. But this does not require
the further metaphysical commitment that our true being, our true
selves, literally is, consists in, the divine idea of us. But it
took a long time for these underlying metaphysical issues to be
worked out explicitly in medieval Christian thought.
The School of Chartres
Let
us now move several centuries down the line and take a brief look at
another Christian Neopla-tonist treatment of the same problem. This
is the famous School of Chartres, known for its exaggerated Platonic
realism of ideas.21
Its main themes are really a revival of John Scottus Eriugena with
some original variations. The themes we are interested in are the
realism of the divine ideas and their ontological status in the mind
of God. Again we find almost the identical position of Eriugena.
The true being of creatures is found in the divine ideas, which
Thierry of Chartres, perhaps the most daring of the school, calls
formae nativae. These are found in their pure state in the mind
of God, and become imprisoned and diminished by union with matter.
As Clarembald of Arras tells us, the true being of anything comes
from its form: omne esse ex forma est . . . . quoniam forma
perfectio rei et integritas est.22
But all these forms as in God become a single simple form; God is
the forma essendi of all forms and through them of all
things.23 But as they
exist in God these exemplary forms are not yet explicated or
unfolded as they are in the created world. Just as all numbers are
already precontained in the simple unity of the monad or number one,
so all forms are complicatae (enfolded as the opposite of
unfolded) in the unity of one form in God. As Thierry puts it in a
striking image, in God all forms fall back into the one: “The forms
of all things, considered in the divine mind, are in a certain way
one form, collapsed in some inexplicable way into the simplicity of
the divine form.”24
And thus “every form without matter is God himself.”25
Clarembald of Arras explains further how the many forms are enfolded
without real plurality in the one:
Every multitude lies hidden in the simplicity of unity, and when in
the serial process of numeration a second is numbered after the one
and a third after the second, then finally a certain form of
plurality flowing from unity is recognized, and so without otherness
there can be no plurality.26
Here again, it seems to me, we run into the same unresolved tension
as we found in Eriugena. It is indeed an authentically Christian
metaphysical doctrine that all ideas are identical in being with the
one perfectly simple being of the divine Mind. But I submit that
this is not an authentically Neoplatonic doctrine; the ideas in the
divine Nous for all classic Neoplatonists are already
unfolded in their distinct intelligible multiplicity and hence in
their plurality of being, thus forming the system of true being as
integrated plurality—a plurality, however, without spatial or
temporal separation, held together in the unity-multiplicity whole
of a single spiritual life. (It is indeed true—this was objected to
me in the discussion of the paper—that the ideas, like all things,
are in a sense in the One, as the “power of all things” [dynamis
panton]. But this is in a mode of supereminent simplicity, as
in the power of the cause from which all else emanates, not in the
mode of distinct intelligibility or of true being as in the Nous.
The realm of being is below the pure unity of the One.) And if the
thinkers of the school of Chartres insist that these divine ideas or
native forms, though simple and one in God, are nonetheless the true
being of all things, then we have a metaphysical impasse. Either
this is a metaphysical contradiction or incoherence, or true
being is nothing but its being thought, has no being of its own but
only that of the act that thinks it. This seems to me the
conversion of the Neoplatonic realism into a latent idealism that is
quite foreign to the original inspiration of the doctrine, and, I
believe, to the explicit intentions of the Christian Neoplatonist
thinkers themselves. Which side of the dilemma did they actually opt
for? I have the impression that they were just not that clearly
aware of the metaphysical implications of their thought and made no
clear option, but remained oscillating ambiguously somewhere in the
middle, unwilling to give up either end of the opposition.
But
to be fair to them, the blame is not entirely theirs. They are
trying to cope with the rich but enigmatic heritage of the
Pseudo-Dionysius, who in his turn has tried to impose a new
dialectic of the unmanifest-manifest divinity on the old Neoplatonic
doctrine of the emanation of the world of ideas and the Nous from
the One, but without making it that clear that some significantly
new metaphysical laws have been introduced. Although something
similar to the unmanifest-manifest dialectic can certainly be found
in classical Neoplatonism, still the particular way in which
Pseudo-Dionysius interprets it to hold onto the ontological
simplicity of God—in terms of the divine “energies” which are both
divine, God as manifested, and yet somehow multiple—seems to me to
have a strong dose of oriental as well as Neoplatonic roots, unless
one considers it an original creative Christian adaptation of
Neoplatonism. I cannot go into this complicated but intriguing
prob-lem here. The Dionysian doctrine has remarkable af-finities
with the Hindu notion of the shakti, or divine power, of the
“manifest” Brahman at work in the world. It was given central
prominence later in the Eastern Orthodox theology of Gregory Palamas,
but was rejected by Western Scholastic theologians. Like the
doctrine of multiple divine ideas, it is filled with metaphysical
tensions of its own.
Thirteenth-Century Scholasticism
We
now come to a decisive new chapter in the history of our problem,
one that finally provides a coherent metaphysical resolution to the
almost 1,000 years of tension within Christian Neoplatonism. This
solution emerges gradually during the twelfth cen-tury, due to the
struggle over the reality of univer-sals, and finally comes to a
head in thirteenth-cen-tury Scholasticism. Here the technical
precision demanded of professors trained in Aristotelian logic and
functioning in a professional academic commu-nity could no longer be
satisfied with inspiring but metaphysically fuzzy
pantheistic-sounding formulas that at the same time repudiated
pantheism, or with the simple assertion of unexplicated paradoxes
held together by metaphors such as “all forms fall back into the
simplicity of the one divine form.” The crucial decision is finally
made: the Platonic realism of ideas must once and for all be given
up.
There seems to have been a fairly wide consensus on this point,
though, as we shall see, not universal. It was not only the
Aristotelian current of Albert and Thomas Aquinas that sponsored it:
leading Augustinians such as Saint Bonaventure also agreed. In fact
the latter provides us with an admirably succinct summary of the
basic position:
God
knows things through their eternal “rea-sons” (rationes aeternae)
. . . . But these eter-nal intelligibilities are not the true
essences and quiddities of things, since they are not other than the
Creator, whereas creature and Creator necessarily have different
essences. And therefore it is necessary that they be exemplary forms
and hence similitudines re-presentativae of things
themselves. Conse-quently these are intelligibilities whereby things
that are are made known (rationes cognoscendi), because
knowledge, precisely as knowledge, signifies assimilation and
expression between knower and known. And therefore we must assert,
as the holy doctors say and reason shows, that God knows things
through their similitudes.27
The
die is cast. The divine ideas are no longer the very forms, the
true being, of creatures, but their intentional similitudes, whose
only being is that of the one divine act of knowing. (It is quite
true—as was objected in the discussion—that the divine ideas in
Bonaventure seem to have a greater ontological density and dynamism
than in Saint Thomas. But this remains the creative dynamism of the
Word itself and is not the true being of creatures as for John
Scottus. The very next question after the above quotation, whether
there is any real, multiplicity in the divine ideas, makes this
clear beyond the shadow of a doubt. Hence, the suggestion made that
he qualifies his position in the next paragraph is entirely without
textual foundation.) But the firmest and clearest grounding for
this common position is provided by Thomas Aquinas, with his new
metaphysics of the composition of essence and act of existence (esse)
in creatures and the location of the real perfection of beings no
longer on the side of form but on the act of existence of which form
is limiting principle.28 Thus creatures have no true
being until God as creative cause gives them their own intrinsic act
of existence, which is not their intelligible essence but a distinct
act by which form itself comes to be as a determinant structure of a
real being. As creatures are precon-tained in the divine ideas,
they simply do not yet have this act of their own intrinsic esse,
hence are not yet properly beings at all, let alone the really real.
Their “subjective” being is identified entirely with the being of
the simple act of divine intelligence which “thinks them up” (adinvenire
is the word Saint Thomas carefully picks out, which means to invent
or think up, not discover, which would be invenire) as
possible limited modes of participation in his own infinite act of
esse subsistens.29 Thus their entire being is
their being-thought-about by God, in a single simple act
without any plurality of real being, though there is a clear
plurality and distinction on the level of the objective intelligible
content thought about by this one act. In a word, in the new
technical ter-minology, the divine ideas are now only the “sig-nifying
signs of things” (intentiones rerum), not things themselves;
their being is esse intentionale not esse naturale or
reale.30 This crucial distinction between esse
intentionale and esse naturale, in terms of which alone
the doctrine makes sense, is the one piece that has been
conspicuously missing from the entire Platonic tradition, and for
good reasons. To have admitted it would have blown up classical
Platonism from within, or at least forced such a profound adaptation
as to involve almost a change of essence. The term itself is an
inheritance neither of the Platonic nor even the Aristotelian
tradition, but from Arabic sources.
This single stroke of distinguishing the subjective being of ideas,
which is nothing but the act of the mind that thinks them, from
their objective content, their intentional meaning and reference
which can be multiple and distinct, opened the way at last to a
metaphysically coherent assimilation of the whole Eriugenian
doctrine of the presence of the divine ideas in the Word in a
single, simple act prior to any plurality. The latter was indeed a
brilliant insight of Christian Neoplatonism, but one that could not
make sense unless the doctrine that accompanied it in Eriugena—that
of the ideas as true being in them-selves—was jettisoned. The
divorce was painful, but inevitable. But this move also entailed
the dropping of another cherished theme of classical Neopla-tonism,
namely, that the passage from the divine ideas, or realm of true
being, to their unfolded exem-plifications in the contingent world
of matter is a passage to a lower mode of being, a degradation or
diminution in being. Creation now becomes, on the contrary, a
positive expansion from the merely mental being of the world of
divine ideas to a new dimension of true being “outside” the divine
Mind (extra causas), as an enrichment of the universe through
a gracious free sharing of its own real perfection; for this real
perfection is always in the line of actual esse, and this was
not yet accomplished in the realm of the divine ideas by themselves.
The
same move also forced, if not the total giving up, at least the
drastic toning down and reinterpre-tation of another closely linked
theme long cherished by Christian Neoplatonists in the
pre-Scholastic period following the lead of Augustine himself.31
This is the notion that all creatures exist in a higher, more
perfect state in the exemplary idea of each of them in the mind of
God than in their own created being—especially so, but not
exclusively, in the case of material beings. This theme still keeps
recurring in the spiritual writings of Christian Neoplatonists, used
as a potent motivation and intellectual model for spiritual growth.32
But its literal metaphysical force is now toned down.
Clearly Thomas Aquinas cannot hold this as a metaphysical
doctrine—and not even Bonaventure, if he is to remain consistent
with his text quoted above. For if, as I am present in the mind of
God, I do not yet possess any slightest trace of my own intrinsic
act of esse, in proportion to which alone is measured all my
real participation in the perfection of God, then it cannot be
literally asserted that I exist, have my true being, in a higher and
more perfect state in God’s idea of me than in my own contingent
created existence in myself. It is true that my intelligibility,
the intelligible content of the divine idea of me, exists in
a higher, more perfect way in God than in me; but this is still not
my true being, my esse.
Thomas is quite aware that he is laying aside a long and venerable
Augustinian tradition. But as is his wont in so doing, he never
directly contradicts it, but reinterprets it to draw the most he can
out of it without compromising his own metaphysical integ-rity.33
Thus in the present case he is quite willing to admit that there is
a certain fulfillment for a material being to exist, as known, in a
spiritual intelligence, a fortiori in God’s, since in being
thus known the material mode of existence is transposed into a
spiritual one, that of intentional existence, which is identical
with the spiritual act of the mind knowing it. But this fulfillment
can exist only if the material being already exists in its own
material being and is also known in a spiritual mode. The
real being of the material thing does not consist in its
being known and the latter state cannot be substituted for the
former with the full value retained. It does remain true, however,
that the perfection of our real being is represented, held
before us by the divine idea as an ideal goal, a final cause,
drawing towards its actual realization through the drawing
power of the Good reflected in it. It functions thus as a powerful
motivation for spiritual growth toward the fulfillment of our
true being to-be-realized; but it is not this true being already
existing in the mind of God. For if the latter were literally the
case, why bother with working out on an inferior level the same
perfection already given on a higher level? This was the enigma
haunting, as we saw, Eriugena’s emanation from the second to the
third division of nature—a problem to which he gave no recognizably
Christian solution.
All
did not agree, however, with this deontologi-zing of the divine
ideas. Henry of Ghent, teaching in Paris at the end of the
thirteenth century, and drawing his inspiration both from Avicenna
and Neoplatonism, complains that the more “current theological
opinion” has gone too far in rejecting the doctrine of Eriugena and
reducing the divine ideas to nothing but understood “modes of
imitability of the divine essence (rationes imitabilitatis).”
To this he opposes “the position excellently expressed by Avicenna
in his Metaphysics, according to which the ideas signify the
very essences of things.”34 Expoun-ding this position
elsewhere he distinguished bet-ween two aspects of the ideas: (1)
“the essences of things in the divine knowledge as objects known . .
. which are really other (secundum rem aliae) than the divine
nature”; and (2) “the rationes by which these are known,
which are really identical with the divine nature.”35 To
explain this he introduces his own technical terms of a distinction
between an idea and its ideatum or object, and a distinction
between the being of essence and the being of existence (esse
essentiae and esse existentiale):
Since therefore the ideas in God exercise cau-sality in every way
over the things of which they are the forms, by constituting them in
both their esse essentiae and their esse exis-tentiae,
and this according to the mode of the exemplary formal cause,
therefore the relation of the divine idea to its ideata . . .
is according to the first genus of relation, which is that between
the producer and its product . . . so that it follows from the
divine perfection that from the ideal ratio in God, the first
essence of the creature flows forth in its esse essentiae,
and secondly, through the mediation of the divine will, this same
essence flows forth in its esse exislentiae.36
But
the introduction into Christian thought of this Avicennian attempt
to salvage Neoplatonism in a creationist universe, by means of a
world of possible essences which, as someone put it, “stands up
stiff with reality” (the reality proper to essence in itself,
distinct both from the idea that thinks it up and its later mode of
created actual existence), did not find hospitable acceptance among
the thirteenth-century and especially later Christian theologians.
The ghost of John Scottus Eriugena was no longer welcome at the
banquet of Christian theology, although the overtones of the
doctrine do linger on in Duns Scotus and down through Descartes,
Spinoza, and the early rationalism of modern philosophy.
Fourteenth-Century Nominalism
We
cannot conclude our story, however, without a brief word on the
final denouement in medieval times. The thirteenth century gave
birth to a careful balance between a firm maintaining of the
presence and role of the divine ideas in God and a firm rejection of
their identification with the true real being of creatures. The
pendulum now swings all the way to the opposite extreme. The
deontologizing of the divine ideas is pursued so relentlessly that
the divine ideas themselves, even in their esse intentionale,
finally disappear entirely. This is the work of William of Ockham
and his nominalist followers. His sledgehammer metaphysics, pairing
the principle of contradiction with the divine omnipotence, will
allow no medium between full reality—evidenced by full real
distinction and separability—and nothing at all. One of the first
casualties is the esse intentionale of the great
thirteenth-century metaphysical systems. Either the so-called
divine ideas are real being, and thus real multiplicity, in
God—which a Christian thinker cannot accept—or they are nothing at
all. The divine ideas, venerable tradition though they be, must be
resolutely jettisoned in the name of Christian thought purified of
all pagan Platonism. Nothing in the divine nature is immutable or
eternal except the being of God himself. But God is not an idea:
The
divine essence is not an idea, because I ask: the ideas are in the
divine mind either subjectively or objectively. Not subjectively,
because then there would be subjective plurality in the divine
essence, which is manifestly false. Therefore they are there only
objectively: but the divine essence does not exist only objectively
(i.e., as the object of idea). Therefore it is not an idea.37
As
Gabriel Biel, a later Ockhamist disciple, puts it succinctly:
These two, namely, immutability or eternity, and multiplicity or
plurality, do not seem com-patible (for the divine essence, which is
immu-table and eternal, does not allow that plurality which is
posited among the ideas—for each creatable thing has its own proper
and distinct idea—and although this plurality is proper to the
creature, immutability and eternity are not, but are proper to God
alone).38
The
so-called divine ideas must therefore be ba-nished from God and
identified simply with creatures themselves as the direct objects,
without interme-diary of any kind, of the divine act of knowing. The
danger of this position, of course, as became all too clear with the
unfolding of nominalism, was that, in the name of saving the divine
simplicity, all intel-ligible structures of creatures as causally
prior to creation also seem to have vanished from the divine mind,
and we are threatened with an unfathomable abyss in God of pure
unillumined will power which seems at the root of intelligence
itself, leading to the substitution of divine will rather than
intelligence as the ground of morality. As Biel does not hesitate
to put it: “It is not because something is right or just that God
wills it, but because God wills it therefore it is right and just.”39
With the banishment of the divine ideas, we have now come full
circle in the spectrum of positions within Christian thought. The
divine simplicity has been preserved, but at the expense of that
other pillar of traditional Christian metaphysics, which Saint
Thomas and other thirteenth-century Christian thinkers worked so
hard to bring into equilibrium with the divine simplicity, the
theory of divine exemplary ideas. The total negation of the
Neoplatonic world of ideas is as unacceptable in Christian
philosophical thought as its ultrarealism. A Christian metaphysics
of God can survive only at a point of balance in the middle.
Professor Anton Pegis has made the suggestion, in a brilliant
article on “The Dilemma of Being and Uni-ty,”40 that in
thus moving to such an extreme anti-Platonic position, Ockham and
the nominalists are still the unconscious prisoners of Platonic
thought, accepting uncritically one of its basic presuppo-sitions;
namely, that the world of intelligibility is necessarily and
unavoidably a world of real multiplicity. The Neoplatonists drew
the conclusion that, since being and intelligibility were
necessarily correlative partners, then the supreme source of
reality, the One, must be beyond both being and intelligibility.
The nominalists drew the conclusion that, since the supreme
principle must be being, Ultimate Being itself must be raised above
intelligibility. But both conclusions proceed from the same
premise. The only solution is to do away with the premise
itself—that an intelligible order is necessarily linked to real
multiplicity. It was this decisive move, rendering Christian
Neoplatonism finally viable, that we owe to Saint Thomas and other
Aristotelian-influenced thinkers of the thirteenth century.
Conclusion
To
sum up briefly, the key point I have tried to make, as a
metaphysician reflecting on the history of a problem, is that,
although large areas of Neoplaton-ism can be assimilated for the
profound enrichment of Christian thought, there is one doctrine that
stubbornly resists coherent assimilation: this is the doctrine of
the realism of ideas, that the true being of things consists in the
pure ideas of them as found in the mind of God (or elsewhere). This
is inconsistent first and foremost with the Christian notion of the
existential identity of all the divine ideas, however distinct in
their intelligibility or esse intentionale, with the one
simple act of the divine mind thinking them, so that there is no
real plurality in God outside that of the three divine Persons. It
is also inconsistent, though this point remained more latent in
actual medieval discussion, with the value given to created
existence as the gift of God’s love and the decisive value given to
human salvation freely worked out in contingent history through the
Incarnation of the Son of God and the free moral response of
historical man. The chapter we have just studied illustrates once
again that the encounter between Neoplatonism and Christian thought
was a deeply challenging one, where genuine assimilation and viable
synthesis could be brought about only by profound creative
adaptation, in some cases even the final rejection, of some aspects
of Neoplatonism.
Notes
1
Cf. Plato’s famous description of the ideas as “the really real” (to
ontos on) in Phaedo 65-66 and other classic discussions
of the ideas.
2
Cf. Parmenides 1321b-c (trans. Cornford):
“But Parmenides, said Socrates, may it not be that each of these
forms is a thought, which cannot properly exist anywhere but in a
mind? In that way each of them can be one and the statements that
have just been made would no longer be true of it.
Then, is each form one of these thoughts and yet a thoughl of
nothing?
No,
that is impossible.
So
it is a thought of something?
Yes.
Of
something that is, or of something that is not?
Of
something that is.”
3
Cf. Enneads VI, 7, 15-16 (trans. MacKenna-Page), and
occasionally through V, 1-2. In these passages the Ideas are spoken
of as the product of the Intellectual-Principle.
4
Enneads V, 9, 7-8. Cf. also V, 3, VI. 6, 7-8, and off and on
throughout V, 1-2. The essence of the position is that Nous
and its objects constitute a single interdependent relational unity,
neither properly prior to the other, but constituted together as a
unitary life simultaneously by the overflow of the Good. But
see VI, 6, 8 for a priority of being, over Nous:
“First, then, we take Being as first in order: then the Intellectual
Principle . . . . Intellectual Principle as the Act of Real Being,
is a second.” The Greek texts here are entirely clear, the terms
used being pro, proteron, etc.
5
This doctrine is clear, explicit, and constant throughout the
Enneads. Cf. V, 1, 4; V, 6; V, 3; 10-15; V, 6; V, 9, 6; VI, 6,
9; VI, 7, 13 and 17. The intellec-tual realm is always a one-many,
both because Being as object is distinct from the act that knows it
and because each Being-Idea is distinct from every other, though not
divided from it.
6
Anton Pegis has admirably summed up the dilemma posed to Christian
thought by the Platonic world of ideas: “St. Augustine . . . thought
to baptize the Pla-tonic Forms and to make them ideas in the mind of
God. But this was easier to assert than to accomplish
philosophically. For the perplexing mystery of the Platonic Forms
is that in a Christian world they can be neither God nor creatures.
They cannot be creatures because they are immutable and eternal; and
they cannot be God because they are a real plurality of distinct and
distinctly determined essences. Yet they rose before the minds of
Christian thinkers again and again, and they hovered somewhere on
the horizon between God and creatures, strange aliens both from
heaven and from earth, and yet aliens whose message proved so
enduringly dear to Christian thinkers that, rather than forget it,
they exhausted their energies in pursuing it.” “The Dilemma of Being
and Unity,” in R. Brennan, Essays in Thomism (New York: Sheed
and Ward, 1942), pp. 158-159. The whole article, in fact, is a
brilliant example of a truly philosophical study in depth of the
history of philosophy.
7
Cf. for example his famous brief treatise on the ideas, De
Diversis Quaestionibus LXXXIII, Qu. 46 (Migne, Pat. Lat.
XL, 29-31), and other standard references.
8
Cf. F. J. Thonnard, “Ontologie augustinienne,” L’Année
théologique augustinienne 14 (1954), 39-52, esp. pp. 42-43.
Clear texts are in Augustine De Trin. V, 2, 3: “Ab eo quod
est esse dicta est essentia,” and De Immortalitate Animae
XII, 19: “Omnis enim essentia non ob aliud essentia est, nisi quia
est.”
9
De Trinitiate V, 2, 3.
10
Sermo VII, n. 7.
11
De Moribus Manichaeorum VII, 7.
12
Contra Manichaeos, c. 19 (PL, XLII, 557). On the
above texts see V. Bourke, St. Augutstine’s View of Reality
(University of Villanova Press, 1965), and J. Anderson, St.
Augustine and Being (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1966).
13
It has been called to my attention, however, by the Augustinian
scholar, Robert J. O’Connell, that Augustine, in Confessions
X, C. 9-12, when speaking about memory, distinguished between the
sensible images of past contingent events, such as going to the
Tiber river, and the intellectual intuition of num-bers and
their relations, which intuition puts us in contact with the very
things themselves (res ipsae), with the very reality of
numbers, which truly are (valde sunt), hence buried
deep in our intellectual memory, which is always in contact with the
immu-table and eternal truths of the intelligible world through
divine illumination. Now since, as rationes aeternae,
numbers are certainly on a par with all the other rationes
aeternae, it would seem necessary to conclude by analogy that
all the rationes aeternae are also res ipsae, et valde
sunt (c. 12). Yet Augustine never quite seems to go this far or
work out the implications.
14
On John Scottus Eriugena’s doctrine, see M. Cappuyns, Jean Scot
Erigène (Paris: Descléc, 1933): H. Bell, Johannes Scotus
Erigena (New York: Russell & Russell, 1964); J. Trouillard.
“Erigene et la théophanie créatrice.” in J. O’Meara and L. Bieler,
eds., The Mind of Eriugena (Dublin: Irish Univ. Press, 1973),
98-113; T. Gregory, Giovanni Scoto Eriugena (Florence: Felice
Le Monnier, 1963), ch. I: “Dall’ Uno al Molteplice”; and the
standard histories of Gilson, etc.
15
Cf. De Divisione Naturae II, c. 36 (I. ed. Sheldon-Williams,
Johannis Scotti Eriugenae Periphyseon, Dublin Inst. for
Advanced Studies, 1972. pp. 205ff.). See also other main discussions
of the primordial causes, De Div. Nat. III, c. 1-17 (M.
Uhlfelder and J. Potter, John the Scot: Periphyseon—On the
Division of Nature, Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill, 1976).
16
De Div. Nat. II. c. 4-9. Thus material things exist more
perfectly even in the mind of man, as spiritual, than in themselves.
17
De Div. Nat. III, c. I (trans. Uhlfelder and Potter, p. 129):
“The first causes themselves are, in them-selves, one, simple,
defined by no known order, and unseparated from one another. Their
separation is what happens to them in their effects. In the monad,
while all number subsist in their reason alone, no number is
distinguished from another, for all are one and a simple one, and
not a one compounded from many. . . . Similarly the primordial
causes while they are understood as stationed in the Beginning of
all things, viz., the only-begotten Word of God, are a simple
and undivided one; but when they proceed into their effects, which
are multiplied to infinity, they receive their numerous and ordered
plurality. . . . all order in the highest Cause of all and in the
first participation in it is one and simple distinguished by no
differentiae; for there all orders are indistinguishable, since they
are an inseparable one, from which the multiple order of all things
descends.”
18
Thus in Enneads VI, 6, 9 in the order of Being in the Nous
number is declared to be already unfolded, not as it is
in the Monad or One. In V, 3, 15, all the ideas are unfolded as
distinct in the Nous, which thus becomes a one-many, whereas
the One should not be said to contain all things as in an indistinct
total. See the other texts in note 5. Thus what Eriugena describes
as the mode of the primordial causes in the Word is explicitly
denied by Plotinus of the divine Nous and could be applied
only to the One, in which the ideas could in no way be said to be
present
19
De Div. Nat. II. c. 20 (ed. Sheldon-Williams, p. 77).
20
Ibid., II, 8 (ed. Sheldon-Williams, p. 29). For this identity
of the being of things with the thought of them, see Bett, op.
cit., in n. 14, pp. 51, 145; Gregory, op. cit., in n. 14,
p. 12: “Gli essere nella mente di Dio si risolvono nell’atto con cui
elgi li conosce.”
21
Cf. E. Gilson, History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages
(New York: Random House, 1954), ch. III: “Platonism in the
Twelfth Century”; H. Häring, Life and Works of Clarembald of
Arras (Toronto: Pontifical Insitute of Medieval Studies, 1965).
22
Clarembald of Arras, Tractatus super Librum Boetti De Trinitiate
(ed. Häring, op. cit., in n. 21), II, 41, p. 123.
23
Ibid., II, 29-30, p. 118: “Forma sine material est ens a se,
actus sine possibilitatae, necessitas, aeter-nitas . . . et ipsa
Deus est.”
24
Thierry of Chartres’ commentary on Boethius’ De Trinitate,
called Librum Hunc (ed., W. Janssen, Der Kommentar des
Clarembaldus von Arras zu Boethius De Trinitate, Breslau, 1926,
p. 18): “Omnium formae in mente divina consideratae una
quodammodo forma sunt, in formae divinae simplicitatem
inexpli-cabili quodam modo relapsae.”
25
See note 21.
26
Tract. Super Lib. Boet. De Trin. I, 34 (Häring, p. 99):
“Omnis multitudo in simplicilate unitatis complicate latitat, et cum
in serie numerandi post unam alterum et post alterumtercium
numerator, et deinceps tunc demum certa pluralitatis ab unitate
profluentis forma cognoscitur, sicque sine alteritate nulla potest
esse pluralitas.”
27
De Scientia Christi, q. 2, c, Responsio (Obras de S. Buena
ventura, Bibl. De Autores Chrisitianos, Madrid, 1957), p. 138.
Cf. also q.3.
28
Cf. the standard treatments of the ‘‘Thomistic existentialism,”
introduced by St. Thomas: E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of
St. Thomas Aquinas (New York: Random House, 1956), the famous
chapter I on “Existence and Reality”; J. de Finance, Etre et agir
(Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1960, 2nd ed.); and my own
summaries: “What is Really Real?” in ed. J. Williams, Progress in
Philosophy (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1955), pp. 61-90, and “What is
Most and Least Relevant in the Metaphysics of St. Thomas Today?”
Internal. Phil. Quart. 14 (1974), 411-434.
29
For Thomas’ treatments on the divine ideas, see Sum. c. Gentes
IV, c. 13, no. 10; Sum. Theol. 1, q. 15 entire; I, q. 44,
a. 3; 1, q. 18, a. 4: “Whether All Things are Life in God”; De
Veritate, q. 3, q. 4, a. 6 and 8. The description of the divine
ideas as “invented” by God is in De Ver., q., 3, a. 2 ad 6
m; as rationes quasi excogitates is in De Potentia,
q. 1, a. 5, ad 11 m.
30
For Thomas’ fundamental criticism of the Platonic realism of ideas,
see In I Metaph., lectio 10; In I De Anima, lect. 4,
and the general discussion with texts in R. Henle, St. Thomas and
Platonism (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1956), part II, ch. 4: “Basic
Principles of the Via Platonica.”
31
De Trinitate VI, c. 8.
32
Cf., for example, the great Flemish mystic, Jan Ruusbroec.
“According to the Flemish mystic, man’s true essence (wesen)
is his superessence (over-wesen). Before its creation the
soul is present to God as a pure image; this divine image remains
its super-essence after its actual creation.” Louis Dupré, Tran-scendent
Selfhood (New York; Seabury, 1976), p. 103-104.
33
See the texts in note 29, in particular Sum. Theol. I, q. 18,
a. 4; De Ver., q. 4, a. 8; Sum. c. Gentes IV, c. 13.
n. 10 (Pegis trans.), and the special article just on this point,
De. Ver., q. 4, q. 6: “Whether Things are More Truly in the Word
than in Themselves.” In I Sent. d. 36, q. I, q. 3 ad 2 m
(M837): four modes of esse creaturae.
St.
Thomas’ point is that if one looks at the mode of being of the thing
in itself and in an idea (God’s or man’s), the mode of being
in an idea, especially the divine idea, is a spiritual mode,
identical with the being of the mind thinking it, hence from this
point of view higher than the material being of a thing in itself;
but if one considers the proper mode of a thing’s own
being as this thing, this is found only in the thing’s own
material being and not in its idea. Properly speaking, a thing’s
own being is not found in its idea. Thus Thomas is able to preserve
intact the traditional formulas about the existence of things in the
Word as more perfect, but the meaning he gives to them is notably
different from their original intention, where his distinctions were
not yet made.
34
Henry of Ghent, Quodlibeta IX, 2, cited in the fine study by Jean
Paulus, Henri de Gand (Paris: Vrin, 1938), p. 91. n. 1.
35
Summa, 68, 5, 7-14, cited in Paulus, loc. cit.
36
Loc. cit.. Cf. the illuminating remarks on Henry and his
place in the history of our problem by Anton Pegis, art. cit.,
in note 6 above. esp. pp. 172-176.
37
In I Sent., d. 35, q. 5; cited in Pegis. art. cit., p.
170.
38
Gabriel Biel, In I Sent., d. 35, q. 5C (Tübingen, 1501);
cited in Pegis, p. 159.
39
In I Sent., d. 17, q. I, a. 3K; Pegis, p. 171.
40
Art. cit. in note 6, pp. 168-172.