From Thomist, 40 (1976), 32-60. This replies to Kai
Nielsen’s “Talk of God and the Doctrine of Analogy” in the same
issue. It was reprinted in Clarke’s Explora-tions in
Metaphysics: Being-God-Person, University
of Notre Dame Press, 1995, 123-149.
Anthony Flood
May 13, 2010
Analogy and the Meaningfulness of Language about God:
A Reply to Kai Nielsen
W. Norris Clarke, S.J.
I must
say that I feel considerable sympathy with Professor Nielsen in his
difficulties in making sense out of the Thomistic doctrine of analogy as
a device for rendering language about God meaningful. In fact, for many
years now I have been struck by the constantly recurring phenomenon of
philosophers outside the Thomistic tradition trying to understand the
doctrine of analogy as applied to God and being quite sincerely baffled
in their attempts to see how it can do the job assigned to it. When
this occurs so often, there is a good chance that the fault is not all
on the one side. And, to be honest, I do not think Professor Nielsen
gets adequate help from either Father Copleston or Professor Ross. He
may not get adequate help from me either, but I would still like to try,
since I consider the issue such an important one.
The
main reasons for the obscurity surrounding the Thomistic theory of
analogy seem to be three. First, historically, St. Thomas
himself, ordinarily such a systematic thinker, for some unexplained
reason was never willing to pin himself down to any one consistent
terminology or structural analysis of the logical form of analogy. He
simply used it, very sensitively, but without any full dress explanation
of what he was doing. When Thomistic commentators after him have tried
to pin down the theory more precisely and technically, they too often
have fallen into the straight jacket of Cajetan’s oversimplified and
restrictive systematization, in which the structure of proper
proportionality is understood as a four-term proportion, a structure
that St. Thomas himself quietly abandons as not adequate by itself after
his early work, De Veritate.1
Secondly, doctrinally speaking, Thomists tend too often to omit
in their formal analyses of analogy the indispensable metaphysical
underpinning that alone justifies the application of analogy when one of
the terms is not known directly in itself. No purely logical or
semantic analysis of the structure of analogous concepts can supply this
extra-logical component. In addition, Thomistic commentators for the
most part do not bring out clearly enough—if indeed they accept the
point at all—the fact that analogy does not lie so much in any formal
structure of concepts themselves as in the actual lived usage of
meaningful analogous language, found only when the so-called analogous
concepts are used in judgments.2 In the light of the
above comments I would like to see if I can shed some light of my own on
Professor Nielsen’s difficulties, so that at least the authentic and
essential points of disagreement may be brought more clearly into focus
and allow more fruitful dialogue thereon than usually seems to be the
case in this elusive question of analogy.
Objections of Professor Nielsen
The
three most crucial objections of Professor Nielsen against the
explanations of Copleston and Ross seems to me to be the following.
(1) The
first concerns the distinction made by Copleston between the “subjective
meaning” of an analogous term, i.e., our understanding of the meaning as
drawn from instances in our experience, which he admits is
anthropomorphic, and the “objec-tive meaning,” i.e., the objective
reality referred to by the concept as found in God and affirmed of him,
even though we do not know just what this is like, but only point to it
in the dark, so to speak, and for good reasons, since it is an
infinitely higher mode beyond the direct grasp of our experience and
concepts. But the trouble here, as Professor Nielsen points out, is
that, since we have no access to this objective meaning as it is
verified in God, which is quite different from the subjective meaning
drawn from our experience, this so-called objective meaning is vacuous,
empty of meaningful content for us who are using the term. And the gap
between the two meaning-contents indicates that the concepts predicated
in each case are not the same, though the same word is used; hence there
is equivocation.
(2) The
second concerns the very meaning of an analogous concept in itself. At
the heart of every analogous concept, Professor Nielsen insists, there
must be “a common core of meaning,” which in turn necessarily implies
that this core of meaning must be univocal. “Common core of meaning”
and “univocal” are co-extensive and convertible terms. No merely formal
structure of isomorphic relations can supply such a common core.
(3)
Third, Professor Nielsen points out that there is no way of confirming
or verifying the meaningful-ness or truth of what is analogously
predicated of God, since there is no way of verifying or falsifying it
from experience or by any kind of testing for consequences.
Most of
my reply will be directly concerned with the objections to Copleston,
since the objections to Ross seem to me merely a more technical
application of the same basic difficulties. And, besides, I agree with
much of Professor Nielsen’s dissatisfaction with any attempt to lay out
analogy in some formal logical structure. No isomorphism of formal
relations can supply for intrinsic similarity in content between the
sets of relations compared. Since I do not think it feasible to
separate out the answers to the three objections, for they all involve
the same roots, I shall give my own account of how analogy works and
pick up the objections along the way at appropriate points. I will not
give any distinct answer to the third objection. Many have handled this
already. And there is simply no testing from experience or from
consequences of predications when one is discour-sing about the
attributes of God. The only testing is the metaphysical exigency of
intelligibility itself: predications about God must have both
meaning and truth if our own world is not to fall into
unintel-ligibility. They are all metaphysical musts flowing from
the primary must of the causal bond itself. Hence I will divide
my exposition into three main sections: I. Must Analogy Be Rooted in
Univocity? II. The Extension of Analogy Beyond the Range of Our
Experience. III. The Application of Analogy to God and Its Metaphysical
Underpinning.
I. Must Analogy Be Rooted in Univocity?
As we
read through Professor Nielsen’s criticism of both Copleston and Ross,
we notice one crucial assumption functioning over and over again, at
first more or less implicitly, then finally surfacing with full
explicitness. It is this: if there is to be any genuine similarity
within difference in the various predications of an analogous term, then
this similarity necessarily involves some “common property” or
attribute, even if only a relation, which holds in all applications; now
the presence of such a common property necessarily involves a “univocal
core of meaning.” Analyzing one of St. Thomas’s descriptions of knowing
(it should be noted, however, that this does not apply to all knowing
but only to the knowing of another than oneself), which runs, “the
possession of the form of another as another, according to one’s natural
mode of possession,” Professor Nielsen comments:
This
last qualification presumably gives us the difference which keeps the
predication from actually being univocal. But it remains the case that
on the assumption (questionable in itself) that Aquinas’ account of
knowing is intelligible, it is true that in all cases of ‘knowing’ there
is a property that remains common to and distinctive of all these uses.
That is to say, we could construct a predicate signifying the res
significata of ‘knowing’ that would be predicated of all cases of
knowing. This would be a univocal predication. (p. 50)
In
other words, whenever there is a common pro-perty predicated, there must
be a univocal core of meaning. Hence even the qualifying phrase added
by St. Thomas, “according to one’s natural mode of possession,” must
leave intact the univocal core of meaning, “possession of the form of
another as another.”
Here is
the central and clear-cut point of conten-tion between Professor Nielsen
and the Thomistic tradition in the very meaning of analogy itself.
Thomists would admit—though a few, like David Burrell, seem unduly
squeamish about doing so—that in some significant sense there must be
some common core of meaning in all analogous predications of the same
term, for otherwise it could not function as one term and concept. But
they insist, on the other hand, that this common core of meaning is not
therefore univocal, but remains analogous, similar-in-difference, or
diversely similar. If it is any consolation to Professor Nielsen, his
objection is exactly the same as that brought against Thomistic analogy
by Duns Scotus and William of Ockham shortly after the time of Thomas
himself. For them the sufficient requirement that a term be univocal is
that it be able to function as a middle term retaining the same meaning
in both premises of a syllogism, enough to avoid equivocation. An
analogous term was for them really a verbal unity of two distinct,
though related, concepts, and if used in both senses in the same
argument would introduce a fourth term and invalidate the argument.3
Yet
this is definitely not the Thomistic under-standing of univocity and
analogy. The difference in approach between the two positions might be
summed up thus: The Scotus-Ockham analysis is geared primarily to the
demands of deductive reasoning and the logical functioning of concepts.
It also takes the word and concept as the fundamental unit of meaning,
which remains intact in its own self-contained meaning no matter how it
is moved around as a counter in combination with other concepts,
including its use in a judgment, which is interpreted simply as a
composition of two concepts, subject and predicate, without change in
either. The Thomistic analysis is geared much more to the actual lived
usage of the concept in a judgment, interpreted as an intentional act of
referring its synthesis of subject-predicate to the real order, as it is
in reality. Hence it tends to look right through the abstract meaning of
the concept to what it signifies, or intends to signify (intendit
significare), in the concrete, and so adjusts the content of the
concept to what it knows about its realization in the concrete. The
difference in pers-pective—and in theories of the relation of concept to
judgment—leads to quite different conclusions, which I think are
considerably more than a merely verbal dispute over different
terminologies for the same thing, though there is some of that hanging
like a cloud over the scene too, causing the opponents to pass each
other in the fog without meeting.
Let me
explain now how I think Thomistic analogy actually works, building it up
genetically from its actual origin and use in living language. I take
it as understood that from now on when I speak of analogous terms and
concepts I am referring only to what Thomists identify as properly and
intrinsically analogous terms, i.e., those that are intended to express
a proportionate intrinsic similarity found in all the analogates
(hence not analogies of the so-called “extrinsic attribution,” such as
“healthy” applied to man and to food, which is not designed to express
similarity but some relation of causality, belonging to, etc.). Such
intrinsic analogies are found in terms like “knowledge,” “love,”
“activity,” “unity,” “goodness,” “being.”
We
construct and use analogous concepts in our language-life to fit
occasions wherein we cannot help but use them. This occurs when we
notice some basic similarity-in-difference, or proportional
similarity, across range of different kinds of subjects (or on
different levels of being, of qualitative perfection), such that the
similarity we notice does not occur in the same qualitative way in each
case but is noticed to be found in a qualitatively different way
in each case. When we form a univocal concept, on the other hand, we
pick out some similarity, usually some form or structure or quantitative
relation, which we judge or notice to be found with significant
qualitative variation in each case, usually falling within the same
species or a genus with closely related properties. In such a case we
notice that, even though a few examples are needed to get started, the
meaning content, what the term objectively signifies, once grasped,
remains neutral, indifferent, unchanged with respect to any further
instances. Such a content is thus quite well defined, determinate, and
fixed.
Not so
with an analogous concept. The similarity we notice here is not some
one thing or characteristic that remains exactly the same in all cases,
except for some new additional note being added on each time from the
outside. It is rather that the similar proper-ty itself is more or less
profoundly and intrinsically modified in a qualitatively different way
each time, so that through and through the whole property is
recognized as at once similar yet different (not just found in some new
instance that in other ways is different). An analogous concept is not
a compo-sition of one part exactly identical and another part different,
as Scotus, Ockham, and Nielsen seem to imply; rather it is an
indissoluble unity where the similarity itself is through and through
diversified in each case. As a result there is quite a bit of “give,”
flexibility, indeterminacy, or vagueness right within the concept
itself, with the result that the meaning remains essentially incomplete,
so underdetermined that it cannot be clearly understood until further
reference is made to some mode or modes of realization.
This
leads us to discover one of the most remar-kable and distinctive
features of analogous concepts, especially the ones of broadest range:
it is in fact impossible to define what we mean by an analogous concept,
to grasp the similarity involved, except by actually running up and down
the known range of cases to which it applies, by actually calling
up the spectrum of different exemplifications, and then
catching the point. The similarity involved cannot be isolated from
its qualitatively diversifying modes and expressed by itself clearly, as
it can be in the case of a univocal concept. It can indeed be caught or
recognized by an act of intellectual insight as we run up and down the
scale of examples. It can be seen, and shown forth by our
meaningful linguistic behavior, as Wittgenstein would say, but it cannot
be said or expressed clearly by itself. Or, if you wish, it can
be said by framing one linguistic term for use in all cases, but the
meaning of the term cannot be grasped at all clearly without actually
calling up a diversified range of cases. The meaning of the term,
therefore, must be completed and made determinate in each case by
reference to some concrete qualita-tive mode. That is why the notion
always contains within it, at least in an implicit way—which can easily
be made explicit, as St. Thomas does in the example of knowledge—the
parenthetical indication (like a kind of metalinguistic instruction or
warning) that the property in question will be present in each
case “according to the mode proportionate to the nature of each.” Yet
the concept itself, as an abstract predicate by itself, fit to be used
in many different predications as somehow the same one concept, does not
mention or contain within its expressed content any of these
particular modes in any of its predications, but is understood as
transcending them all. Otherwise, it is clear, it could not be used to
refer to any other instance with a different mode. How-ever, when this
indeterminate abstract concept, unified as such, is actually used in
a concrete judg-ment, its meaning, as understood in the
whole con-crete act of knowing that is the judgment, then molds
itself or shifts to take on the particular determination of the case in
hand, while at the same time con-tinuing to recognize the intrinsic
proportional similarity-in-difference of this instance with all the
others in the range outlined by the concept. This is the point of the
very astute remark made by Gilson long ago, that “‘analogy’ for Aquinas
refers to our ability to make the kind of judgments we do,” that it is
to be explicated “on the level of judgment “and “not of concept “alone.4
Analogy is to found and understood on the level of the lived use
of concepts and terms, not in any formalizable logical structure of the
concept in itself. Thus when I understand in an analogous way a
proposition like “is intelligent,” what I mean is, “exhibits or realizes
in this different but still sufficiently similar way the same
similarity-in-difference which I have already noticed running through a
certain range of cases, so much so that I feel justified in expressing
this case by the same analogous term as the others.”
I have
laid special stress in the above on the im-portance of the lived use of
concepts in judgment, because it is not always brought out sufficiently
by Thomists, and is one of the distinguished marks of the approach of
St. Thomas when compared to that of Scotus and Ockham. A Thomistic
analogous term does indeed contain a certain genuine unity, though
heavily laced with indeterminacy at its core, enough unity to function
logically quite like a univocal term. And, of course, if one
considers an analogous concept from a comparative or negative point of
view with respect to other concepts, it is quite determinate in what it
excludes from consideration, in how it delimits its whole
range from that of other concepts. But the point remains that when
looked at in what it positively includes within its range it cannot
express clearly by itself the similarity in isolation from the
differences. When it tries to do so through so-called definitions it
can only call up as paraphrases other equally analogous and
indeterminate terms, which themselves require reference to a range of
diverse examples in order to be meaningful. And whenever it tries to
become too precise, it contracts to become identical with just one of
its modes and loses its analogical function.
Let me
illustrate what I have been saying above by taking the same example used
by Professor Nielsen, that of knowledge, defined by St. Thomas as “the
possession of the form of another as another, according to one’s natural
mode of possession.” Let us say that we have already recognized as
included within its range of proper instances the dim know-ledge through
touch of the environment around it by an oyster or snail; the more
complicated integration of visual, tactile, and audible sense images by
a dog or other higher animal; the intellectual insight of man into
justice or the inner law of operation of a typewriter or Einstein’s
Theory of Relativity; the Zen master’s empty, imageless,
supra-conceptual aw-areness of reality; the mystic’s awareness of God in
the “fine point of the soul “beyond all concepts and faculties. All are
judged to be genuine though highly different instances of knowing. Now
suppose we try to say or describe just what is the similarity amongst
all of them, in itself. And suppose the person to whom we are trying to
describe it says “I don’t want you to do it by examples; just tell me
what it is in itself.” What could we possibly tell him that could
capture the commonness by itself? We can only run through the spectrum
of examples on different levels and then appeal to the person’s own
experience. “Do you know what I mean? Do you get the point?”
Professor Nielsen, it seems, would like to insist: “But there is a
common univocal core: possession of the form of another as another. . .”
Yet suppose we try to apply this even to only two cases, such as a
dog’s “possession” of the “form” of a typewriter in the mode of a visual
image of its external shape and color, compared with a man’s
“possession” of the “form” as intellectual insight into the inner law of
operation of the machine. What in the world does “possession” mean
here? How can we describe it in itself? Is it like the possession of a
marble in one’s pocket? No. Or having a cast in one’s eye? No. Is it
possessing a visual image in consciousness? Aside from the problem of
defining “consciousness,” this is one example, but not one that
adequately circum-scribes the meaning, since having an intellectual
insight into the intelligible form or law is vastly different, even
though somehow similar—it is impossible to specify just how. The
same difficulty would occur in trying to explain “form.” The only thing
one can finally do is call up the whole range of examples and ask,
“Don’t you catch the point? Do you see what I mean?” This is not an
evasion; it is precisely the intelligent (in fact, the only effective)
way to do it. The same with other analogous concepts, such as unity,
activity, love, goodness, power, perfection (imagine trying to describe
precisely what is similar in all instances of activity or perfection).
In a word, although one can indeed say that in some true sense
(analogous) there is a com-mon core of meaning in an analogous concept,
it is nonetheless clear that the concept functions quite differently—if
we look at it from within as used, not just from without as a
logical counter in an argu-ment—from a univocal concept with its
common core.
This
leads me to one more distinctive character-istic of the analogous
concept which I think it most important to mention, since it too is
frequently not made explicit by Thomist commentators. What kinds of
things, or aspects of reality, or properties are thus amenable to, even
necessarily require, expression through analogous terms? As I see
it—and I am willing to defend this, even though it is not commonly
mentioned—there is only one “dimension” of reality or “kind” of property
that is capable of truly anal-ogous expression: this is the realm of
activities or dynamic functions, what we might call “activity
properties” understood in the widest possible sense (plus, of course,
the opposite correlative properties of receiving, being acted on, etc.:
loving and being loved, causing and being caused are equally analogous).
All such properties are expressed originally and primarily by verbs,
not nouns, or are in some way reducible to verbs. Analogous terms
can of course be nouns, but then the noun presupposes the verb—e. g., it
signifies a subject, but as the doer of such and such an action,
which aspect alone is made explicit (knower, lover . . .).
The
reason why activity properties are such fit candidates for analogous
expression is that the same general “kind” of activity can be performed
quite differently by different kinds of agents or subjects without
destroying the similarity-in-difference of the activity aspect itself.
This is not true of forms, structures, quantitative relations, and the
like, which are not thus elastic in their realizations. Different kinds
of things in the universe, different levels of being, are not like each
other in their essential specific forms or essences considered
statically. But they are proportionally alike in their modes of
activity, in their dynamic functions. Different forms
themselves can only be compared as alike insofar as they are forms or
structures for similar actions. If there is any formal structure to
analogous concepts, it is not a strictly logical or formal structure,
but the structure of an activity situation: an analogous term expresses
this general kind of activity x, recognized as carried on in one
distinctive proportionate way by subject a, in another
distinctively different propor-tionate way by subject b, etc.
The subjects and modes of acting are quite different in each case; the
activities themselves are recognized as propor-tionately similar,
similar-in-difference, although it remains impossible to state just
what this similarity is apart from its range of varied modes. Let
me add that if the term “activity “itself here is allowed to expand to
its full analogous breadth of illuminative meaning, existence itself
then not only can be described but is uniquely appropriate to be
described as the most radical kind of activity or act, the act of “presencing.”
This is the Thomistic analogous notion of being itself: “that which
has, or exercises, the act of existing.”
II. The Extension of Analogous Terms Beyond the Range of Our Experience
So far
we have been analyzing how analogy functions within a range where all
the main levels of exemplification lie within our experience, hence
where the different modes can be directly known to us. The next phase
of our investigation, crucial for the application to God, concerns the
extension of analogous concepts beyond our present range of known
examples, i.e., the formation of “open-ended” concepts whose range
extends indefinitely beyond our present experience, at least in an
upward direction. The ranges of analogous concepts can be roughly
classified as follows: (1) those having a ceiling but no floor
(no lower limit) in their applica-tion: terms like physico-chemical
activity, whose up-per limit is biological activity, or perhaps
conscious-ness, but that extend downward to unknown depths of matter
still hidden from us and perhaps very strange indeed compared with what
we know; (2) those having both floor and a ceiling, say,
biological activity, or sense knowledge, limited by the non-living or
unconscious below and intellectual know-ledge above; (3) those having a
floor but no ceiling: intellectual knowing, love, life, joy,
etc.; (4) those having neither ceiling nor floor: the
all-pervasive “transcendental properties” applicable across all levels
of being, such as being, activity, unity, power, intelligibility,
goodness (in the widest sense). Our special concern will be with
numbers (3) and (4), as alone applicable to God.
How in
general do we go about opening up an analogous concept beyond its
presently known range of examples? Let us take the example of knowing.
Suppose we reflect on how remarkably diverse are the modes we already
know, and how impossible it is to deduce from a lower level what a
higher level will be like; it then appears to us, when reflecting on the
analogous meaning of knowing, that we have no good or decisive reasons
for closing off its possible range at the level we know; in fact, there
is some plausible suspicion that there may be higher kinds of
intelligence on other planets or perhaps even beyond all corporeal
entities (not yet God). We decide we should remain prudently open to
the possibility of higher intelligence trying to communicate with us
through some kind of signal. We have no idea what kind of communication
or signals—they would not even have to be through material signs but
might be by direct telepathy or thought-communication—or what the mode
of intelligence involved might be like or how it might function in
itself, even when not attached to a body. Yet it makes perfect sense,
and in the concrete it is quite easy—we are actually doing it already—to
open up the range of meaning of what we now experience and understand as
intelligence to include in expectancy some possible level at present
quite unknown and uncharacterizable by us. The new extension of the
term, though empty of any precise content describable by us now, is not
simply empty. It gets its new and very useful content of meaning from
its place on an ascending (it might also be des-cending) scale,
which serves as guide for evaluation assessment (respect,
awe, fear, caution, etc.). Such a role as guide to evaluation
procedures, and their practical consequences, is an indispensable one
for our concrete life of the mind in the midst of a reality that is
always partly known, partly concealed in relation to us.
Another
example arises from the new scientific interest in para-psychology and
psychic phenomena of various kinds. There is widespread talk of some
new kind(s) of force that produces effects in the material world, yet
seems to operate in ways thus far unknown to us and is quite different
from the other physical forces we know—“psi-forces,” some call them.
They may be a new kind of physical radiation, or more probably psychic
energy fields, or what have you. The point is that we quite readily
enlarge the notion of force to make room for the possible
discovery of a new mode, concerning which we can say nothing clear as
yet, not even that it really exists. It may be objected that there is a
univocal core in all description of such forces, in that they produce
observable effects in the material world. There may, it is true, be one
element of their definitions that has a univocal cast: the material
effects produced. But the notion of force does not mean the
effects produced. It means the power producing such effects, and
as long as this central part of the meaning is variable in its mode the
meaning must remain analogous.
In both
of the above, and many other possible examples, in order to extend the
range of an analogous concept we must “purify” its meaning-content, what
it explicitly signifies, making it indeterminate enough so that its
range of application will not be restricted within present limits. If
we judge that this cannot be done without a violent and arbitrary wrench
in the meaning that renders the term no longer comfortably serviceable
enough, we judge the proposed extension inviable, too confusing, and
devise an entirely new term to express the additional range of cases
presumed to exist. This is a matter of good judgment, of a sense for
successful living language, not a matter of the logical structure of
concepts.
It is
within the context of this extension of an analogous concept to a new
application whose mode of realization is unknown to us that the
traditional distinctions arise between “objective meaning” and
“subjective meaning” (Copleston), the res signifi-cata, or the
objective property signified by the term, and the modus significandi,
or the modes by which we express to ourselves this property (St.
Thomas), and other similar semantic devices. There is unfortunately
much confusion in terminology here (and not infrequently in thought too,
I fear), and I am not happy with either of the above ways of trying to
spell out the same general point. St. Thomas’ way is clear enough in
itself—though often misunderstood, as it clearly is here by Professor
Nielsen—but is so narrow in scope as he uses it that it does not do the
entire job that has to be done. Copleston’s way is, I fear, open to
serious misunderstanding and seems to me to be inadequate to its task.
So let me first state the job to be done, and how I think it best to
express it, and then return to assessing the two sets of distinctions
mentioned above.
In such
a context of using analogous language, we must separate out the
following: (1) the res signi-ficata, i.e., the “thing” or common
property signified, which is what is actually predicated in each case,
whether previously known or not. Its meaning-content as expressed in
the analogous concept is deliberately or systematically vague and
indeter-minate, not restricted to any of its modes so as to be truly
predicable of all cases. (It does not mean, by the way, the actual
concrete referent of this predicate in a given judgment, although the
terminology of “thing”—res—has misled some into thinking so.) (2)
The real modes, or modes of being, in which this common objective
property or attribute is understood to be realized in given
applications, as we apply the term in concrete complete acts of knowing
in the judgment. These modes may already be known to us, as the animal
and human modes of knowing, or they may as yet be unknown to us, in
which case we intend to signify what is there in the concrete but
through a vague and incomplete act of knowing. Or, if you wish, we
intend to refer to what is really there, but through a vague and
incomplete mental sign, recognized as such, although we do recognize
clearly that we are referring to a mode different from the others
we know. These modes, however, are not part of what is actually
predicated by the abstract analogous predicate itself, as is (1) above,
although we understand the indeterminate content to take them on
in the concrete, as we actually use the term.5 (3) The
modes of our understanding of the res significata, which are
the best known modes of concrete realization of the common property,
considered as ways or media through which we first come to lay
hold of the meaning of the property and upon which we fall back
as the clearest examples when we wish to evoke its meaning for ourselves
anew—since, as we noted above, it is always necessary to call up some
examples across a range in order to grasp or recall the meaning of an
analogous concept. Among these there is usually—not necessarily always,
it seems—one or more that stand out as prime analogates for us, i.e., as
focal meanings or privileged exemplars closest to us by which we most
easily and immediately grasp the meaning experientially, and out from
which as from a center we extend it in lessening degrees of clarity.
This usually means the properties as experienced and lived in our own
selves, whether in body, psyche, or spirit. But it should be clearly
understood that these ways of our coming to understand most vividly the
common property do not themselves enter into the object meaning of the
term when it is predicated analogously, in any of its
predications. They are modes of revealing the analogous meaning
of the term; they do not constitute its objective meaning
itself—otherwise they would restrict it and destroy its analogical
spread. Its objective analogical meaning as predicated is deliberately
expanded, enlarged, made more vague and indeterminate than these modes
of discovery, so that it will be able to transcend them in scope of
application. Thus at the same time that we call up these privileged
modes in order to evoke the meaning of the concept for ourselves, we
understand (at least implicitly, but in a way that effectively
controls our use of the term) that the meaning of the analogous
term is being left open for further application, that it is not tied
down to these modes of discovery. Thus if we were asked, in the example
of speaking of hypothetical higher forms of “intelligence” that might
communicate with us from outer space, what we mean by “intelligence,” we
would say something like this: “You know, the kind of thing we do, being
self-conscious, compre-hending the natures and properties of things,
making signs or communicating in some way, in a word, understanding, but
probably in quite different ways from ours.” We do not confuse the
modes of under-standing with the reality understood, or signified.
We
could add another aspect (4) which would cor-respond exactly to St.
Thomas’ modus significandi, or modes of signifying the res
significata. These are often misunderstood as signifying aspect (2),
the actual modes of concrete realization of the common property in
particular cases, as Professor Nielsen seems to understand them. This
is quite incorrect. They are also sometimes extended to coincide with
our (3), man’s modes of understanding the res significata. There
is no great harm in deliberately using modus significandi with
this meaning, and one does need some appropriate term to express these.
But it is still not what the expression itself means as Aquinas uses it.
It refers only to our human modes of expressing the res significata,
i.e., conceptual-linguistic modes. It was originally intended to
take care of the obvious difference between the way God’s perfections
are found in him and our way of expressing the perfections of God
through multiple verbal predicates, each distinct from the other, which
are predicated of a subject as though they were accidents inhering in a
distinct substance: “God is wise, and loving, and
powerful.” This is the way they are found in us, where wisdom can come
and go and where a man can be wise but not powerful or vice versa. But
what they signify as found in God himself is that God is
identically all the positive perfections signified by these terms but
united together in a single simple plenitude of perfection. Similarly
we speak of God, who is beyond time, through verbal forms with tenses.
Yet St. Thomas is quite clear that, although our modes of expressing
these attributes bear the mark of their origin in our experience,
these modes are not what is expressed and predicated by the
concept itself, in any of its predications.6 To say that
John is wise and powerful does not mean, though it may indeed be
understood to be also true, that wisdom in John is an accidental
attribute really distinct from his power and his own essence. It is
simply stating that it is true that he is wise and it is true that he is
powerful, without stating how these are related. Hence our modes of
expression do not corrupt with anthropomorphism our predications about
God, or about anything, for that matter. This is as far as St. Thomas’s
modes of expressing take us, though he also speaks of the “modes
in which a perfection is found” or realized in its subject, which are
not quite the same thing, but correspond rather to our modes of
realization in (2) above. Where do Copleston’s “objective meaning”
and “subjective meaning” fit in here?7 It is not entirely
clear to me from his text how they do, and it is no wonder to me that
Professor Nielsen had serious—and to my mind quite
justified—difficulties with his explanation. For Copleston, the
“objective meaning” means “the objective reality itself referred to by
the term in question,” which in his example, “God is intelligent,” he
maintains is “the divine intelligence itself,” as it is in itself. The
“subjective meaning” is “the meaning-content in my own mind . . .
primarily determined for me by own experience . . . of human
intelligence.” But here it seems that “intelligence” means in this
predication “divine intelligence” and yet the only meaning-content in my
mind in all predications is “human intelligence.” This opens up a
yawning gap between the two which Prof. Nielsen has very astutely seen,
and it is not at all clear from this text alone just how one crosses the
gap. What Copleston fails to explain is that what he calls the
“subjective meaning” is not really the meaning-content in my mind
at all which I mean to signify by the analogous concept. It is my
way of discovering the meaning, but not the purified more
indeterminate analogous meaning itself. He needs another
intermediate term in his discussion to indicate this. He comes close to
it, in fact, when he adds at the end of his text, not quoted by Nielsen,
“But seeing that human intelligence as such cannot be predicated of God,
I attempt to purify the ‘subjective meaning’ . . . . And in so doing we
are caught inextricably in that interplay of affirmation and negation of
which I have spoken.” It is this “purified meaning,” purified by being
made more indeterminate and open, that is the one actually predicated of
God, which is not Copleston’s objective meaning either, since that is
already determined to fit God only. He does not make this clear enough
in his text. (I fear there is some confusion too in Fr. Copleston’s
text between meaning and reference, when he speaks of the meaning as
“the reality referred to.”) Thus it should be clear that I
dissociate myself from Fr. Copleston’s explanation and consider it an
inaccurate rendering of St. Thomas’s teaching, or at least an easily
misleading one. Professor Nielsen has good reasons for finding it
unsatisfactory. There is in fact no gap between the meaning of
“intelligence “as predicated of God and its meaning as predicated of
man. But there is a gap between the modes of realization which I
understand this attribute will take on in the concrete in each case,
as well as between my mode of coming to understand this meaning and the
mode I affirm in God.
III. Application to God
Let us
now take brief stock of what we have accomplished. We have tried to
explain what the structure of analogous predication is in general, how
it works, and what it means to extend the range of an analogous concept
beyond its ordinary range in our experience. But the actual extension
of our anal-ogous language to some new entity, such as God, that is
beyond the range of our experience requires three further steps: (1) we
must have good grounds for affirming that there actually is (or
at least might be) such a new candidate for the application of our
language; (2) we must have good grounds for affirming that this new
candidate is actually objec-tively similar in some way or ways to
the presently known beings in our experience—in other words, that there
are good grounds for applying our concepts and language at all; (3) once
we are in possession of these grounds we must then proceed to figure out
just which of the attributes in our store of knowledge are apt to be
extended meaningfully and legitimately to such an entity. But the first
two suppositions cannot be provided by a theory of analogy itself. They
must come from outside, to build a bridge across which our analogical
language can walk. It is especially the lack of any awareness of the
second point above, the establishment of a bond of similarity between
God and creatures, that renders Professor Nielsen’s exposition of
Thomistic analogy so crip-plingly incomplete. Let us now turn to each
of these three points. The first two will be handled together under
Section 1.
1. Causality as the Bond of Similarity between God and World
The
first step is establishing the existence of God. This is done through a
causal argument, which postulates that, under pain of our world of
experience falling into unintelligibility, there must exist, as
experience’s ultimate condition of intelligibility, or adequate
sufficient reason, one ultimate Source of all being, whose only
intelligible mode of being must be infinite perfection—for otherwise it
could not be the ultimate condition of intelligibility. I would not
carry on this argument through the Five Ways of St. Thomas, since they
are too incomplete by them-selves and defective in structure to do the
job for us today. I would use rather the simpler and more basic
metaphysical resources of St. Thomas, not drawn on clearly enough in the
Five Ways, to show that no being that begins to exist, or is finite in
perfection, or composed in its radical being, or member of a system of
dynamically interrelated elements—to sum it up most simply, no finite
being or group of finite beings—can supply the sufficient reason or
ground of its own existence, and that such an ultimate condition of
intelligibility is not reached until we posit an infinite being, a being
infinite in perfection.
It is
not my purpose to work out this argument here, since it would take
another whole article, and our main aim here is explaining the function
of analogy within such a framework. Let us therefore suppose that this
step has been carried out successfully. If it cannot be, there is no
point in discussing Thomistic analogy any further as applied to God.
But as soon as we have established the argument, without paying any
explicit attention to analogy in the process, we discover that a strange
thing has happened. Analogy is already being used in the very
formulation of the conclusion: there is an ultimate Source
or condition of intelligibility for the existence of. . . , or
cause. (This by the way is all we mean by “cause” here in
its widest metaphysical sense: that which fulfills a need for
intelligibility, which answers the question, “What is effectively
responsible for the existence of this datum x, which has turned
out to be non-self-explanatory?”—not some meaning drawn from the
sciences.)8 For to be intelligible to us, these terms
themselves must all be analogous when applied to a being outside our
experience.
Does
this mean that a vicious circle is here in-volved, that analogy
presupposes causality and cau-sality itself presupposes analogy? This
is an ex-cellent and crucial question, which Professor Nielsen himself
has certainly seen, when he speaks of a circle where one religious
statement backs up another. There is indeed a circle of mutual
involvement, but it is not a vicious circle; it is a vital one. For it
is the very thrust of the mind’s search for intelligibility, reaching
out into the unknown to postulate a suffi-cient reason somewhere in
being, that both sets up a new beachhead in being for our knowledge to
explore further and at the same time carries with it its own enveloping
field of analogy. Immanent in the entire innate drive of the mind toward
intelligibility is an unrestricted commitment to intelligibility,
wherever it may lead, and simultaneously to its objective correlate,
being itself, as the source of all answers to this quest. To this range
of intelligibility and its correlate being it is impossible to set any
limits, since the mind, as soon as it becomes aware of these limits as
limits, immediately transcends them by this very awareness. Our own
inner experience of this quest for intelligibility that defines
the very life of the mind reveals to us that both the quest itself and
the answers to it are infinitely Protean, taking on endlessly different
forms and modes. In a word, we experience the field of intelligibility,
enveloping our own minds and reaching out beyond into its correlate,
being, as intrinsically analogical, open-ended but somehow all
bound together in some vague unspecifiable unity. The first and
all-embracing analogous field which we discover—not by constructing it
deliberately but by waking up within it, so to speak—is the correlation
intelligibility-being.
Hence
it is that when, as in the case of the affir-mation of God, the mind is
convinced—for what it believes are good reasons—that it can save the
intelligibility of the world of our experience only by positing or
postulating as existent outside this world (i.e., transcending its
limitations) an ultimate in-finitely perfect source of all being, it
necessarily en-velops this term that it posits with its own pre-exis-tent
and potentially all-embracing field of analogy, at once positing it as a
real condition of intelligibility and as necessarily analogous
in the same movement of thought. This initial analogy is extremely
vague, not yet extending beyond the immediate correlates of the
intelligibility-being field itself, together with the index of location
within this field at the supreme apex of perfection, whatever that may
be. For all the terms used to describe God in this initial stage,
“ultimate condition of intelligibility for the existence of the
world = cause,” are nothing but reaffirmations of the general principle
of the intelligibility of all being in principle, tailored to the
particular situation where the beings we start with do not contain their
own sufficient ground of intelligibility within themselves, hence force
us to look beyond them.9
Thus
the very initial positing of God as cause of the world situates him
within the primary a priori (a dynamic and existential, not a logical, a
priori) analogous field of both intelligibility and being—of being
precisely because this is demanded by intelli-gibility. From the
very beginning of our intellectual life there is a necessary mutual
co-involvement of in-telligibility, being, and analogy. This very vague
ini-tial analogous beachhead of knowledge about God is now ready to be
expanded by further judicious search for more determinate valid
analogies.
It is
at this point that a second crucial corollary of the causal bond comes
into play, one that is too often neglected in expositions of analogy,
and of which there is likewise no hint in Professor Nielsen’s
discussion. This is the principle, handed down to St. Thomas by both
the Neoplatonic and the Aristotelian traditions, that every effect
must in some way resemble its cause. In a word, every causal bond
sets up at the same time a bond of intrinsic similarity in being. In
the Platonic-Neoplatonic tradition this took the form of the principle
that every higher cause communicated something of its own perfection to
its effect beneath it, which participated in the latter as much as its
own limited nature allowed. In the Aristotelian tradition it took the
form of the principle that no being can cause any perfection in another
unless it already possesses in act (in some equivalent way) this same
perfection. These two strands were joined together in a single
synthesis of causal participation by St. Thomas and other
medieval thinkers; and the same general principle of causal
similitude has been accepted by most realistic metaphysicians ever
since, in one form or another.
The
philosophical reason why every effect must in some way resemble its
cause, at least analogously, is this: since all the positive perfection
of the effect, as effect, derives precisely from its cause(s), the
latter cannot give what it does not have; the effect must in some way
participate or share in the per-fection of the cause that is its source.
If the cause does not possess in an equal, or some higher equi-valent
manner, the perfection it communicates to its effects, then the
perfection of the latter would have to come from nowhere, have no
relation to its cause. Where there is no bond of similarity whatever
bet-ween an effect and its cause, there can be no bond of causality
either. The similarity in question, however, could be of two main
kinds. If both cause and effect were of the same species the similarity
would be on the same level and kind, that is, univocal. If the cause
were a higher level of being than the effect, then the similarity could
not be strictly univocal but would have to be at least analogous. In
this perspective, the very fact of establishing a causal link between a
lower effect and a higher cause at once ipso facto generates an
analogous similarity, a spectrum of objective similarity extending from
the known effect at least as far as the cause, whether the latter is
directly known or only postulated as a necessary condition of
intelligibility for an already known effect. Whether both terms of the
relation are known or only one, every effect has to be similar in some
way to its cause, or it could not be a real effect, and the same holds
for the cause. As St. Thomas sums it up:
Effects
which fall short of their causes do not agree with them [i.e., are not
exactly like them] in name and nature. Yet some likeness must be found
between them, since it belongs to the nature of action that an agent
produce its like, since each thing acts according as it is in act. The
form of an effect, therefore, is certainly found in some measure in a
tran-scending cause, but according to another mode and another way
[i.e., analogously]. For this reason the cause is called an
equivocal cause [a term that is “equivocal by design” in
Aristotelian terminology is the same as what was later called
“analogous”—opposed to “equivocal by chance “]. . . . So God gave all
things their perfections and thereby is both like and unlike all of
them.10
An
effect that does not receive a form speci-fically the same as that
through which the agent acts cannot receive according to a univocal
predication the name arising from that form. . . . Now the forms of the
things God has made do not measure up to a specific likeness of that
divine power; for the things which God has made receive in a divided and
particular limited way that which in Him is found in a simple and
universal unlimited way. It is evident, then, that nothing can be said
univocally of God and other things. . . . For all attributes are
predicated of God essentially. . . . But in other beings these
predications are made by participation.11
It is
because of this metaphysical context of causality and causal
participation undergirding the Thomistic theory of analogy that the most
recent and authoritative—in the sense of being almost univer-sally
accepted among Thomists— commentaries on St. Thomas’s theory of analogy
now all agree that despite his many changes in terminology he fairly
early drops the structure of proper proportionality, taken by itself
alone, for a richer structure involving both immanent proportionality
among the analogates of a term and a reference to the causal
source from which the analogous perfection in question is com-municated
to all the participating analogates. This fuller metaphysical-semantic
structure of anal-ogy as applied to the relation of God and creatures is
most aptly called “the analogy of causal partici-pation.” The previously
long accepted “orthodox” explanation of Cajetan in terms purely of
proper proportionality without reference to a source is now recognized
as inadequate to handle the application of analogy to a being not
accessible to our experience, as is the case with God. A purely formal
isomorphism of relations can supply no positive content of know-ledge
about the term of comparison otherwise un-known to us unless some
positive intrinsic bond of si-milarity has already been established
between both ends of the comparison. Cajetan presumed this had been done
elsewhere, but his omission of this step from his formal and explicit
analyses of analogy leaves a very serious gap in his formal theory of
analogy when taken by itself, as most non-Thomistic thinkers, if
not forewarned, would naturally tend to do. St. Thomas himself appears
to have come to re-cognize this, since after his early work De
Veritate—the main source for Cajetan’s systematization of all
Thomistic texts—he never again uses the formal structure of proper
proportionality by itself to express his own thought.
Thus it
is not surprising that when non-Thomistic thinkers like Professor
Nielsen come to the theory of Thomistic analogy through older
traditional expositions in the mode of Cajetan, which omit the context
of causal participation as part of the doctrine itself as applied to God
(or to any unknown cause), they find the structure of the analogy of
proper proportionality by itself quite inadequate to perform the role
claimed for it. Their critical insight is quite accurate.12
2. Which Attributes Can Be Applied to God?
Once we
have set up this basic framework of causal similitude between all
creatures and God, from which it follows that there must be some
appropriate analogous predicates that can be extended properly and
legitimately to God, the next step consists in determining just which
attributes can, in addition to the initial most indeterminate
attributes of being and perfection, allow for open-ended extension all
the way up the scale of being, even to the mode of infi-nite plenitude,
without losing their unity of meaning. This is the search for the
“simple or pure perfec-tions,” as St. Thomas calls them, which are
purely positive qualitative terms that do not contain as part of their
meaning any implication of limit or imper-fection. Once we have
located one of these, even though we enter into its meaning in first
discovering it or in re-evoking it through the limited and imperfect
modes (i.e., our privileged modes of exemplifying it to
ourselves) belonging to the things we find in our experience, what we
intend or mean directly by the concept, once we have purified or
enlarged it for good reasons into an analogous concept, is a flexible,
broadly but not totally indeterminate core of purely positive meaning
that transcends all its particular possible modes, both those we know
and those we do not know.
We can
recognize that we have effected this purification when we can
meaningfully affirm, as we certainly do, that all the experienced
modes of these open-ended perfections, such as unity, knowledge, love,
and power, are limited, not yet perfect modes. For to affix the
qualification “limited or imperfect” to any attribute is already to
imply that our understanding of this attribute transcends all the
limiting qualifiers we have just added to it. Any attribute that cannot
survive this process of purification, or negation of all imperfection
and limitation in its meaning (and of course in its actual mode of
realization when applied to an infinite being) without some part of its
very meaning being cancelled out, does not possess enough analogical
“stretch” to allow its predication of God. The judgment as to when this
does or does not happen is of course a delicate one that requires
careful critical reflection, along with sensitivity to the existential
connotations of the use of the term in a given historical culture.13
Two
types of attributes have been sifted out as meeting the above
requirements by the reflective traditions of metaphysics, religion, and
theology: (1) those attributes whose meaning is so closely linked with
the meaning and intelligibility of being itself that no real being is
conceivable which could lack them and still remain intelligible, i.e.,
the so-called absolutely transcendental properties of being, such
as unity, activity, goodness and power; and (2) the relatively
transcendental properties of being, which are so purely positive in
meaning and so demanding of our unqualified value-approval that, even
though they are not co-extensive with all being, any being higher than
the level at which they first appear must be judged to possess
them—hence a fortiori the highest being—under pain of being less perfect
than the beings we already know, particularly ourselves; such are
knowledge (particularly intellectual knowledge), love, joy, freedom, and
personality, at least as understood in western cultures.
a)
The Absolutely Transcendental Properties
Once
established that God exists as supreme infinitely perfect source of all
being, it follows that every attribute that can be shown to be
necessarily attached to, or flow from, the very intelligibility of the
primary attribute of being itself must necessarily be possessed in
principle, without any further argument, by this supreme Being, under
pain of its not being at all, let alone not being the supreme instance.
Thus it is inconceivable that there should exist any being that is not
in its own proportionate way one, its parts, if any, cohering
into one and not dispersed into unrelated multiplicity. Hence God must
be supremely one. Such all-pervasive properties of being are few, but
charged with value significance: e.g., unity, intelligibility, activity,
power, goodness (in the broadest ontological sense as having some
perfection in itself and being good for something, if only
itself), and probably beauty too.
Since
these properties are so general and vague or indeterminate in their
content—deliberately so to allow for their completely open-ended
spectrum of application—we derive from this inference no precise idea or
representation at all as to what this mode of unity, etc., will
be like in itself. But we do definitely know this much: that
this positive qualitative attribute or perfection (in St. Thomas’s
general metaphysical sense of the term as any positive quality) is
really present in God and in the supreme degree possible. Such
knowledge, though vague, is richly value-laden and is therefore a
guide for value assessment and for value responses of reverence, esteem,
etc. I am puzzled as to why Professor Nielsen would consider such
value-laden and value-guiding concepts simply empty and hence apparently
able to serve no cognitive purpose at all.
b) The Relatively Transcendental Properties
There
is a second genre of transcendental attributes of being that are richer
in content and of more immediate interest and relevance in speaking
about God. These are terms that express positive qualitative attributes
having a floor (or lower limit) but no ceiling (or upper limit), and
hence are understood to be properties belonging necessarily to any and
all beings above a certain level of perfection. Their range is
transcendental indefinitely upward but not downward. Such are knowledge
(consciousness, especially self-consciousness and intellectual
knowledge), love, lovableness, joy (bliss, happiness, i.e., the
conscious enjoyment of good possessed), and similar derivative
properties of personality in the widest purely positive sense (not the
restrictive sense it has in many oriental traditions). All such
attributes appear to us as purely and totally positive values in
themselves, not matter how imperfectly we happen to possess them here
and now. As such, they demand our unqualified approval as
uncon-ditionally better to have than not to have. Hence we cannot affirm
that any being that exists higher than ourselves, a fortiori the
supremely perfect being that God must be, does not have these
perfections in its own appropriate mode. To conceive of some higher
being as, for example, lacking self-consciousness in some appropriate
way, i.e., being simply blacked out in unconsciousness, would be for us
necessarily to conceive this being as lower in perfection than
ourselves.
Nor is
there any escape in the well-known ploy that this might merely mean
inconceivable for us but in reality might actually be the case
for all we know. The reason is that to affirm that some state of affairs
might really be the case is to declare it in some way
conceivable, at least with nothing militating against its possibility.
This we simply cannot do with such purely positive perfection-concepts.
What
happens in our use of these concepts, as soon as we know or suspect for
good reasons that there exists some being higher than ourselves, is
that, even though our discovery of their meaning has been from
our experience of them in limited degree, we immediately detach them
from restricting links with our own level, make them more
purified and indeterminate in content, and project them upward along an
open-ended ascending scale of value appreciation. This is not a
logical but an existential move, hooking up the inner understanding of
the conceptual tools we use with the radical open-ended dynamism of the
intellect itself. One way we can experience this power of projection of
perfections or value attributes beyond our own level is by experi-encing
reflectively our own poignant awareness of the limitations and
imperfection of these attributes as we possess them now, even though we
have not yet experienced the existence of higher beings. We all
experience keenly the constricting dissatisfaction and restlessness we
feel over the slowness, the fuzzy, piecemeal character of our knowing
and our intense longing, the further we advance in wisdom, for an ideal
mode of knowledge beyond our present reach. The very fact that we can
judge our present achievement as limited, imperfect, implies that
we have reached beyond it by the implicit dynamism of our minds and
wills. To know a limit as limit is already in principle to have
reached beyond it in dynamic intention, though not yet in conceptual
representation. This point has for long been abun-dantly stressed by
the whole Transcendental Thomist school, not to mention Hegel and
others, who bring out that the radical dynamism of the spirit inde-finitely
transcends all finite determinate conceptual expressions or temporary
stopping places.
The
knowledge given by such projective or pointing concepts, expressing
analogous attributes open-ended at the top, is again very vague and
indeterminate, but yet charged with far richer determination and value
content than the more universal transcendental attributes applying to
all being, high or low. By grafting the affirmation of these
attributes, as necessarily present in their appropriate proportionate
mode in God, on to the lived inner dynamism of our spirits longing for
ever fuller consciousness, knowledge, love (loving and being loved),
joy, etc., these open-ended concepts, affirmed in the highest degree
possible of God, can serve as very richly charged value-assessment
guides for our value-responses of adoration, rever-ence, love,
longing for union, etc. But note here again that the problem of the
extension of analogous concepts beyond the range of our experience
cannot be solved by logical or conceptual analysis alone, but only by
inserting these concepts into the context of their actual living use
within the unlimitedly open-ended, supra-conceptual dynamism of the
human spirit (intellect and will), existentially longing for a fullness
of realization beyond the reach of all determinate conceptual grasp or
representation. Thomistic analogy makes full sense only within such a
total notion of the life of the spirit as knowing-loving dynamism. The
knowledge given by these analogous concepts applied to God, therefore,
though extremely indeterminate, is by no means empty. It is filled in
by a powerful cognitive-affective dyna-mism involving the whole human
psyche and spirit, which starts from the highest point we can reach in
our own knowing, loving, joy, etc., from the best in us, and then
proceeds to project upwards along the line of progressive ascent from
lower levels towards an apex hidden from our vision at the line’s end.
We give significant meaning to this invisible apex precisely by
situating it as apex of a line of unmistakable direction upward.
This delivers to us, through the mediation (not representation) of the
open-ended analogous concept, an obscure, vector-like, indirect,
non-conceptual, but recognizably posi-tive knowledge-through-love,
through the very up-ward movement of the dynamic longing of the spirit
towards its own intuitively felt connatural good—a knowledge “through
the heart,” as Pascal puts it, or through “connatural inclination,” as
St. Thomas would have it.14 Such an affective
knowledge-through-connatural-inclination is a thoroughly human kind of
knowing, quite within the range of our own deeper levels of
experience, as all lovers and artists (not to mention religious
people) know. Yet it is a mode of knowing that has hitherto been much
neg-lected in our contemporary logically and scientifically oriented
epistemology.
Conclusion
It is
time to conclude this already too lengthy re-sponse. To sum up,
analogous knowledge of God, as understood in its whole supporting
metaphysical con-text of (1) the dynamism of the human spirit,
tran-scending by its intentional thrust all its own limited conceptual
products along the way, and (2) the structure of causal participation or
causal similitude between God and creatures, delivers a knowledge that
is intrinsically and deliberately vague and indeterminate, but at the
same time richly positive in content; for such concepts serve as
positive sign-posts, pointing vector-like along an ascending spec-trum
of ever higher and more fully realized perfec-tion, and can thus fulfill
their main role as guides for significant value responses, both
contemplative and practical. Such knowledge, with the analogous terms
expressing it, is, and by the nature of the case is supposed to be, a
chiaroscuro of light and shadow, of revelation and concealment (as
Heidegger would say), that alone is appropriate to the luminous Mystery
which is its ultimately object—a Mystery which we at the same time judge
that we must reasonably affirm, yet whose precise mode of being
remains always beyond the reach of our determinate representational
images and concepts, but not beyond the dynamic thrust of our
spirit which can express this intentional reach only through the
open-ended flexible concepts and language we call analogous. Such
concepts cannot be considered “empty “save in an inhumanly narrow
epistemology.
Notes
1
For a summary of these developments, see David Burrell, Analogy and
Philosophical Language (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973),
Chap. 6 on Aquinas, and G. Klubertanz, St. Thomas Aquinas on
Analogy (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1960).
2
Although I had come to this conclusion some time ago myself, I am deeply
indebted to Fr. Burrell for his fine elucidation of this point, one of
the main ones in his fine book cited in n. 1.
3
Cf., on Scotus, Burrell, op. cit., Chap. 5 and 7; C. Shircel,
Univocity of the Concept of Being according to Duns Scotus
(Washington: Catholic University of America, 1942); on Ockham, Burrell,
op. cit., Chap. 7; M. Menges, The Concept of the Univocity of
Being regarding the Predication of God and Creatures according to
William Ockham (St. Bonaventure, N. Y.: Franciscan Institute, 1958).
4
E.
Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas (New York:
Random House, 1956), pp. 105-107.
5
St. Thomas himself is quite clear about this. Cf. his sensitive basic
treatment in Summa Theol., I, quest. 13 entire, esp. art. 3:
“Some words that signify what has come forth from God to creatures do so
in such a way that part of the meaning of the word is the imperfect way
in which the creature shares in the divine perfection. Thus it is part
of the meaning of “rock” that it has its being in a purely material way.
Such words can be used of God only metaphorically. There are other
words, however, that simply mean certain perfections without any
indication of how these perfections are possessed—words, for exam-ple,
like ‘being,’ ‘good,’ ‘living,’ and so on. These words can be used
literally of God” (the translation is the new English one edited by
Thomas Gilby, Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. I, Garden
City, Doubleday Image Book, 1969).
6
See his text in note 5.
7
The main part of the text Professor Nielsen is quoting (Contemporary
Philosophy, Westminster, Md.: Newman Press, 1956, p. 96) runs as
follows: “By ‘objective meaning’ I understand that which is actually
referred to by the term in question (that is, the objective reality
referred to), and by ‘subjective meaning’ I understand the
meaning-content which the term has or can have for the human mind. . .
i.e., my understanding or conception of what is referred to. . . . If
this distinction is applied to the proposition ‘God is intelligent,’ the
‘objective meaning’ of the term ‘intelligence’ is the divine intellect
or intellect itself. . . . And of this I can certainly give no positive
account. . . . The ‘subjective meaning’ is the meaning-content in my own
mind. Of necessity this is primarily determined for me by my own
experience, that is, by my experience of human intelligence. But seeing
that human intelligence as such cannot be predicated of God, I attempt
to purify the ‘subjective meaning’ . . . . And in doing so we are caught
inextricably in that interplay of affirmation and negation of which I
have spoken.”
8
For this whole question of the meaning of “cause” in the context of the
mind’s quest for intelligibility and its necessarily analogous character
as a correlate of the enquiring mind at work, see my own fuller
development in “How the Philosopher Gives Meaning to Language about
God,” in The Idea of God, ed. by E. Madden, R. Handy, M. Farber
(Springfield, III: Charles Thomas, 1968), pp. 1-28; and “Analytic
Philosophy and Language about God,” in Christian Philosophy and
Religious Renewal, ed. by G. McLean (Washington: Catholic University
of America Press, 1966), pp. 39-73, esp. pp. 46-51, 61-71.
9
It is very important to make the point here that according to St.
Thomas’s metaphysical method—and any sound metaphysical method,
it seems to me, which seeks to achieve knowledge of some being beyond
our experience—it is a fatal error to accept the demand so habitually
made by analytic philosophers and others that one must define what he
means by “God” before undertaking to establish His existence.
This stand is not an evasion; it is a question of proper method. It is
impossible philosophically to give any definition of God that can
be shown to make sense before actually discovering Him as an exigency of
the quest for intelligibility. The meaning of “God” emerges only in
function of the argument that concludes to the need of a being to which
we then can appropriately give the name “God” or not, according to our
culture and religious tradition. The philosophical meaning of
God should be exclusively a function of the way by which He is
discovered. Hence a properly philosophical approach to the
existence of God should not ask, “Can I prove that God exists?” but
rather, “What does the world of my experience demand in order to be
intelligible?” Following out this exigency rationally, we “bump into”
God, so to speak, as a being all of whose properties are defined
exclusively by its needs to fulfill its job of satisfying the exigencies
of the quest for intelligibility. Hence any philosophical “proof for
the existence of God” has already taken the statement of the question
from some non-philosophical source, usually religion.
10
Summa Contra Gentes, Bk. I, chap. 29, n. 2. Cf. also Summa
Theol., I, q. 13, a. 5.
11
Ibid., chap. 32, nn. 2 and 7. He goes on to say in chap. 33, n.
2: “For in equivocals by chance there is no order or reference of one to
another, but it is entirely accidental that one name is applied to
diverse things. . . . But this is not the situation with names said of
God and creatures, since we note in the community of such names the
order of cause and effect. . . .”
12
It is because of this basic similitude between all creatures and God
that the phrase applied so often to God by theologians, philosophers of
religion, and spiritual writers, describing His transcendence over
creatures, namely, that God is “totally Other,” is really, if taken in
unqualified literalness as a metaphysical statement, quite unacceptable
as sound philosophy, theology, or spirituality. For if God were
literally totally other, with no similitude at all with us, there could
be no bond whatsoever between us, no affinity drawing toward union as
our true Good, no image of God deep in the soul, etc. He might be
totally other in His essence or mode of being, since He is beyond
all form, but not totally other in His being itself or the
activity properties that flow directly from its fullness of
perfection.
13
Cf. for a fuller development my articles cited in note 8.
14
Cf. Summa Theol., I, q. 1, a. 6 ad 3; I-II, 9-45, a. 2. Also J.
Maritain, “On Knowledge through Connatural-ity,” Review of
Metaphysics, IV (1950-51), 483-94; V. White, “Thomism and Affective
Knowledge,” Black-friars, XXV (1944), 321-28; A. Moreno, “The
Nature of St. Thomas’ Knowledge per connaturalitatem,” Angel-icum,
XLVII (1970), 44-62.
Clarke Page