From Graceful Reason: Essays in
Ancient and Medi-eval Philosophy Presented to Joseph Owens, CSSR,
ed. Lloyd P. Gerson. Papers in Mediaeval Studies 4 (Toronto:
Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1983), pp. 301-314.
Anthony Flood
May 10, 2010
The Metaphysics of Religious Art: Reflections on a Text of St.
Thomas Aquinas
W. Norris Clarke, S.J.
The
purpose of this essay is to draw out the impli-cations hidden in a
single brief text of St. Thomas (Summa theologiae 1. q. 84.
a. 7) for understanding the metaphysical and epistemological
structures latent in religious art. I came rather suddenly to the
realization of these implications one day when I was travelling in
India and was studying a splendid bronze sculpture of Shiva, the
dancing God, with eight arms—somewhat a challenge, at first, to our
ordinary Western artistic sensibilities. I would like to share with
my readers my reflections on that day, as a sample of what seems to
me the ever-fresh fecundity of the philosophical thought of St.
Thomas as applied to areas outside of philosophy itself. This is my
humble way of joining in this tribute to Father Joseph Owens, whose
life-work has also been dedicated so long and fruitfully to the
unfolding of the riches hidden within the texts of St. Thomas.
A
brief preliminary clarification as to what I mean by “religious
art.” I am taking the position—contro-versial, perhaps—that there
is a distinctively religi-ous character to certain works of art that
is somehow intrinsic to them, and not merely due to the extrinsic
accident that they are inserted in a religious setting or even
illustrating some religious subject matter. Thus the mere fact that
a painting—let us grant a good one in itself—depicts a mother
lovingly holding a child and carries the title “Madonna” does not
make it automatically a piece of religious art. There must be
something within the painting itself which gives expression to the
religious dimension. Perhaps the simplest way to define or identify
this characteristic, so as to apply to all the religious traditions
of mankind, whether they use the name “God” or not for the Ultimate
Reality they are in quest of, is to describe it as a thrust
toward Transcendence, a reaching beyond the ordinary, all too
painfully limited level of our human lives toward a higher, more
ulti-mate dimension of reality freed from these limita-tions. In a
word, it is the reaching out of the finite toward the Infinite,
expressed through finite sensible symbols. I take it that the
symbol, in this rich con-text of psychology, art, and religion, may
be aptly described as man’s ever unfinished effort to express in
form what is beyond all form and expression.1 The
challenge—and the genius—of authentic religious art is therefore to
succeed somehow in giving effective symbolic expression to this
thrust toward Trans-cendence. I am not going to argue here that
such authentic and distinctively recognizable religious art exists.
The striking examples of it in many religious cultures seem to me
sufficient evidence for the fact. My effort here will be focused
toward uncovering the hidden metaphysical and epistemological
structure behind such art.
The
text of St Thomas which I wish to unpack is the famous one on the
dependence of all our human thinking on the imagination as a
springboard; this dependence in turn is the expression in the
cognitive life of the deeper metaphysical union of soul and body to
form a single per se unity, the unified being that is man.
This text is from the Summa theologiae, Part 1, Question 84,
Article 7, first the body of the article, which lays out the
foundational doctrine, and then more specifically the Reply to
Objection 3, which applies this general doctrine to how we know
higher, purely spiritual beings, in particular God. Let me first
quote the text of the article:
I
answer that, in the state of the present life, in which the soul is
united to a corruptible body, it is impossible for our intellect to
understand anything actually, except by turning to phantasms. And
of this there are two indications. First of all because the
intellect, being a power that does not make use of a corporeal
organ, would in no way be hindered by the lesion of a corporeal
organ, if there were not required for its act the act of some power
that does make use of a corporeal organ. Now sense, imagination and
the other powers belonging to the sensitive part make use of a
corporeal organ. Therefore it is clear that for the intellect to
understand actually, not only when it acquires new knowledge but
also when it uses knowledge already acquired, there is need for the
act of the imagination and of the other powers. For when the act of
the imagination is hindered by a lesion of the corporeal organ, for
instance, in the case of frenzy, or when the act of the memory is
hindered, as in the case of lethargy, we see that a man is hindered
from understanding actually even those things of which he had a
previous knowledge. Secondly, anyone can experience this of
himself, that when he tries to understand something, he forms
phantasms to serve him by way of examples, in which as it were he
examines what he is desirous of understanding. For this reason it
is that when we wish to help someone to understand something, we lay
examples before him from which he can form phantasms for the purpose
of understanding.
Now the reason for this is that the power of knowledge is
proportioned to the thing known. Therefore the proper object of the
angelic intellect, which is entirely separate from a body, is an
intelligible substance separate from a body. Whereas the proper
object of the human intellect, which is united to a body, is the
quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter; and it is through
these natures of visible things that it rises to a certain knowledge
of things invisible. Now it belongs to such a nature to exist in
some individual, and this cannot be apart from corporeal matter; for
instance, it belongs to the nature of a stone to be in an individual
stone, and to the nature of a horse to be in an individual horse,
and so forth. Therefore the nature of a stone or any material thing
cannot be known completely and truly, except inasmuch as it is known
as existing in the individual. Now we apprehend the individual
through the sense and the imagination. And therefore, for the
intellect to understand actually its proper object, it must of
necessity turn to the phantasms in order to perceive the universal
nature existing in the individual. But if the proper object of our
intellect were a separate form, or if, as the Platonists say, the
natures of sensible things subsisted apart from the individual,
there would be no need for the intellect to turn to the phantasms
whenever it understands.
Objection 3:
There are no phantasms of incorporeal things, for the imagination
does not transcend space and time. If therefore our intellect
cannot actually understand anything actually without turning to the
phantasms, it follows that it cannot understand anything
incorporeal. Which is clearly false, for we understand truth, and
God, and the angels.
Reply to Objection 3:
Incorporeal beings, of which there are no phantasms, are known to us
by comparison with sensible bodies of which there are phantasms.
Thus we understand truth by considering a thing in which we see the
truth; and God, as Dionysius says, we know as cause, by way of
excess, and by way of remotion. Other incorporeal substances we
know, in the state of the present life, only by way of remotion or
by some comparison to corporeal things. Hence, when we understand
something about these beings, we need to turn to the phantasms of
bodies, although there are no phantasms of these beings themselves.2
The
body of the article expresses the classic teaching of St. Thomas on
the necessary collabora-tion between intellect and sense knowledge
(either the external senses or the imagination) for all natural
acts of understanding in a human subject. I stress “natural”
in order to leave open the possibility of various modes of
supernatural infused knowledge which could bypass the senses. I
also stress “understanding” in order to leave open the possibility
of some directly intuitive acts of knowledge (whether natural or
supernatural), such as the intuition of one’s own self as conscious
active presence. Any conceptual understanding of the nature
of this self would involve the cooperation of sense and abstractive
intellect. The cognitional theory itself is grounded, as St. Thomas
clearly points out, in the metaphysical per se unity of soul
and body to form a single being. All this is too well known to need
any further commentary here by me.3
Our
special interest in this article is twofold: first, the way in which
such a mode of knowing tied to imagination can come to know purely
spiritual beings, in particular God, of which there can be no sense
image. This is by way of introduction. Our second and primary
focus of interest is in how this way of knowing is reflected in
religious art. The Reply to Objection 3 contains in very
condensed form the essence of St. Thomas’ teaching on how a human
knower can come to know God, a purely spiritual and infinite being,
through the collaboration of sense and intellect. This doctrine is
also well known, but let me summarize it briefly.4
I. The Mind’s Ascent to God
St.
Thomas insists that we have no direct intellectual understanding of
God’s being as it is in itself. We must always begin with the
knowledge of the sensible world, and then allow ourselves to be “led
by the hand,” as he puts it elsewhere,5 by ma-terial
things, in a dialectical process of “comparison with sensible
things,” as he says in our present text, all the way up to an
indirect knowledge of God as ultimate cause, with all the attributes
appropriate for such a cause.
It
is hard for us to appreciate today what a revolutionary stand that
was in St. Thomas’ own time. The common doctrine of the dominant
Augustinian school before him and in his own time (e.g., St.
Bonaventure) had by the mid-thirteenth century assimilated the new
Aristotelian technical theory of knowledge by abstraction from the
senses with respect to the material world around us, since St.
Augustine’s illumination theory was focused more on necessary and
eternal truths or judgments and had little to say about the
formation of concepts about the material world. This
Aristotelian “face of the soul,” as they put it, looked down, as it
were, on the material world around it and abstracted the forms of
sensible things from matter. But there was also a second,
definitely higher and more noble, face of the soul, more directly
illumined by God, which looked directly up to know spiritual things,
such as one’s own soul, angels, God, eternal truths, etc.6
St.
Thomas resolutely rejected this doctrine of two natural faces of the
soul, one looking down into the world of matter, the other looking
directly up into the world of spirit.7 The structure of
our natural human knowledge is far more humble, he believed. There
is only the one face of the soul, which is turned directly only
toward the material cosmos around it as presented through the
senses. Then, by the application of the basic inner dynamism of the
mind, its radical and unrestricted exigency for intelligibi-lity—which
can be expressed as the first dynamic principle of knowledge: the
principle of the intelligi-bility of being, “omne ens est verum”8—we
can step by step trace back the intelligibility of this material
world to its only ultimate sufficient reason, a single infinite
spiritual Cause that is God. Man is the lowest and humblest of the
spirits, whose destiny it is to make his way in a spiritual journey
through the material world back to his ultimate Source and his own
ultimate home.
What is the general structure of this ascent of the mind to God from
the sensible world? It passes along the classic “Triple Way” first
outlined by Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite and adapted to his own
use by St. Thomas9–as well as by many other
thirteenth-century Christian thinkers. St. Thomas refers to it very
tersely in our present text when he says that we know God “as cause,
and by way of excess, and by way of remotion.” We first discover
God as ultimate cause of all material and finite beings, since no
material being in particular, and no finite being in general, can be
the sufficient reason for its own existence. What more can we say
about this First Cause? Here the Triple Way of Pseudo-Dionysius
enters in more explicitly: (1) the way of positive affirmation
of divine perfections grounded in the causal relation; (2) the way
of negation or “remotion,” when we remove from what we have
affirmed any limit or imperfection; and then (3) the way of
reaffirmation of the perfection in question by expanding it to
an infinite degree. This final stage, St. Thomas calls the
ways of “excess,” a somewhat pale translation of the Latin
excessus, which means a “going out of itself” by the mind in a
movement beyond all finites toward the Transcendent.
The
first step of affirmation based on causality rests on the
principle that every effect must in some way, at least analogously,
resemble its cause, since all that is in the effect—as effect—as
must come from its cause, and a cause cannot give what it does not
possess in any way, at least in some equivalent higher mode of
perfection. Hence we can affirm that whatever positive perfection
we find in creatures must have its counterpart, either in an equal
or in some higher analogous equivalent mode, in the cause.
The
second step, that of negation or remotion, purifies what can be
affirmed of God in a proper and literal mode of speech (opposed to a
metaphorical mode). Since God is pure spirit and infinite in
perfection, we cannot affirm literally and properly of Him any
perfection which contains within its very meaning some note
of imperfection or limitation. This eliminates at once a whole class
of attributes or predicates which can be applied literally to
material beings or finite creatures but not to infinite pure spirit.
Thus we cannot argue that because God is the Cause of the
perfection of eyesight in creatures, therefore He has infinitely
good eyesight; for eyesight implies the built in limitation of
matter and finitude. A rather small number of basic attributes
remains which describe perfections which we first find exemplified
in creatures in a limited way, but which contain no imperfection or
limitation in their meaning. That is, they are purely positive
unqualified perfections, values which we must judge to deserve our
unqualified approval, to be unqualifiedly better to have than not to
have. Such are, for example, existence, unity, goodness, beauty,
activity, power, intelligence, will, love, etc. These alone can be
affirmed positively and properly of God, not metaphorically. But
they too must first be purified of any imperfection or limitation we
find attached to them in creatures.
Once we have thus purified them by “removing” all traces of
imperfection and limitation, we can then, in the third step,
reaffirm them of God, adding the index of infinity. Here the mind
leaps beyond what it can directly represent or conceive in a clear
concept, and, borne aloft by what Plato called “the wings” or “eros”
of the soul, i.e., the radical drive of the spirit toward the total
intelligibility and goodness of being, projects out the positive
content of the perfection it is affirming, along an ascending scale
of analogy, to assert that this perfection must be found in infinite
fullness in God, though the mind cannot directly see or clearly
conceive just what this fullness is like in itself. This movement
of the mind beyond all finite beings, and hence all clear concepts,
is called in our text “the way of excess,” that is, the mind’s going
out of itself (ex-cedere) beyond all finite concepts.
II. Application to Religious Art
Now
let us apply this basic movement or ascent of the mind toward God to
the domain of religious art. How does the work of art succeed in its
own way in leading us through sensible symbols to make this leap
beyond all sensible symbols toward the Infinite which they
symbolize, that is itself beyond all form and symbol? Let us first
note that the general structure of the two movements is strikingly
similar. Both must start from sense images. And both must make a
final leap beyond images and concepts toward a Transcendent Infinite
beyond all images and concepts. The way of passing from the first
step to the last differs in each. The philosophical ascent follows
a purely interior path of intellectual analysis, insight, argument,
etc. The work of religious art, on the other hand, must somehow
stimulate, through the very medium of sensible symbols themselves,
the leap of the mind and heart to what is beyond them. How can the
work of religious art pull off this remarkable feat of leading its
viewer (or hearer) beyond itself, beyond even the entire world of
symbols and matter? It seems to me that the process follows very
closely the triple path outlined in our present text, in the
Reply to Objection 3: (1) comparison, (2) remotion, (3) élan
toward the Transcendent.
The
first step corresponds to St. Thomas’ “com-parison with sensible
things.” It selects some sen-sible symbolic structure which
suggests some posi-tive similitude, however distant, to the
Transcendent reality the artist is trying to express. Thus he can
lay out symbols of power, majesty, wisdom, love, etc. as found in
our world.
The
second step corresponds to the “remotion” or purification stage in
St. Thomas’ Triple Way. Here the artist must suggest the radical
difference between his sensible symbol, taken literally, and the
Beyond he is trying to express through it. This is equivalent to
the removal of limitation and finitude from our concepts in the
philosophical ascent. The artist expresses it by introducing a note
of strangeness or dissimilitude of some kind into the primary
similitude he has first laid down, in order to indicate that what he
is pointing to is far different from, and higher than, the original
sensible springboard from which he started.
There are many ways an artist of genius can do this, some crude and
simple and obvious, such as the lifting of a human figure above the
earth, encircling it with a halo of light, etc. Or it can be in
some striking creative way that breaks the mold of the ordinary,
jolting the viewer into the awareness that the work of art is
pointing beyond this dimension of ordinary experience. Such, for
example, are the Hindu statues of Shiva, Creator and Destroyer of
worlds, portrayed as a dancer with six, eight, ten arms. Since the
upraised hand and arm is a sign of power, a human figure with six
arms breaks through our accustomed images and evokes a power beyond
that of ordinary humans. It is a similitude shot through with
dissimilitude, at once a comparison with sensible things of our
experience and a negation of them in their present limited state,
or, to turn to Byzantine Christian art, consider the great icons,
which sometimes seem so strange to us in the West, in part because
we do not understand what the artist is trying to accomplish. An
icon of Mary, the Mother of God, for example, will first exhibit a
positive similitude with the human figure of a Woman. But if we
examine the face we notice a strange unearthly, fixed, and
apparently empty stare in the eyes, unlike any ordinary human look.
This is the negative moment, the affirmation of dissimilitude,
which stimulates us to recognize that she is looking with the eyes
of the soul beyond our material world directly into timeless
eternity, into the world of the spirit and the divine, beyond change
and motion.
There are an inexhaustible number of other, sometimes infinitely
subtle and sophisticated, ways in which an artist of genius can
suggest this negative moment of breaking the similitude with our
world: e.g., the elongated figures of the saints in El Greco, the
monumental, often frightening masks of African ritual art, the cone
emerging from the top of the head in statues of the Buddha, etc. If
this dimension of negativity, of purification from the limitations
of our world is not present in some way in a work of art, it may
indeed be good art, but cannot, it seems to me, qualify as properly
religious art. It remains too stuck in the world of our ordinary
human reality to help us spread the wings of the soul and soar
toward the Transcendent. This criterion can lead us, I think, to
disqualify as religious art many famous paintings and sculptures
labelled “Madonnas,” both in our own and in earlier times—including
not a few by renowned Renaissance artists, such as Raphael himself.
The absorption of these Renaissance artists in particular in
exploiting to, the full the new realism of the human form
effectively stifles, all too often, any élan toward the
Transcendent. We remain absorbed in the natural beauty of womanhood
and childhood in themselves.
The
third step, the élan toward the Transcendent beyond the
merely human and the finite, is really only the other side of the
previous stage and so closely woven into it as to allow only
conceptual abstraction from it. This is the most mysterious aspect
of a work of religious art, where the individual genius of the
artist comes most to the fore—a genius often eluding explicit
analysis. Somehow, by the dialectical opposition and
complementarity of the two preceding, positive and negative steps
the artist must stimulate our minds, hearts, and feelings, set them
resonating in depth, so that they will be spontaneously inspired to
take off from the natural, the this worldly, the material, and the
finite to reach out on the wings of the spirit toward the transcen-dent
Mystery of the Infinite, the divine. Great religious art has an
uncanny power to draw us thus out of ourselves, to help us to take
off and leave behind both ourselves and the work of art. Thus it is
the express aim of Hindu religious music, for exam-ple, to draw the
listener slowly. through the quality of the music, into a
meditative state, which gradually deepens so that the listener is
drawn beyond himself into communion with the Transcendent and
forgets all about the music. All the examples, we gave previously
as illustrations of the negative moment are also examples, through
the very dynamism inherent in the expression of this negative
moment, of how religious art can stimulate the élan of the spirit
toward the Infinite: the statue of the dancing Shiva, the great
Byanztine icons, the paintings of El Greco, the African ceremonial
masks, etc. So too the reverent contemplation of certain statues of
the Buddha, if one follows carefully the continuous rip-pling folds
of his garments, can have a quasi-psychedelic effect and draw one
deep into contem-plation. So too the Tibetan Buddhist paintings,
which are carefully designed as meditation guides. So too the Pietá
of Michelangelo, by its deeply moving expression of the meditative
silence of Our Lady, draws us into her own contemplation of her son,
as God-man and Savior of the world through His Passion.
One
of the most obvious and striking examples, one deeply familiar to
St. Thomas himself, is the medieval Gothic cathedral, Chartres, for
instance, whose soaring élan of incredibly attenuated, almost
dematerialized, stone columns and arches, suffused with light from
the sun beyond the structure itself, admirably symbolizes the
soaring of the human spirit in adoration and prayer toward the
transcendent God, the Light of all finite minds, who “dwells in
light inaccessible.”10
What is happening way in all these instances is that the artist has
found a way through his symbolism to tap into and trigger off the
great underlying, ever present, but ordinarily latent dynamism of
the human spirit toward the Infinite. Thus stimulated, the
simmering coals of this immense underground longing of the spirit
suddenly flame up into consciousness and, using the symbol as a
springboard, leap out toward the hidden Magnet that draws them.
Just how the artist succeeds in doing this is his own secret, and
often the secret of a whole tradition, once the initial geniuses
have found the way. But it seems that the individual artist must
himself experience this soaring of the spirit in order to charge his
symbols with the power to do this for others. The work of a lesser
artist, who either has not had the personal experience of this élan
of the spirit, or who has not found the way to incarnate it
effectively in sensible symbols, just will not stimulate the viewer
(or hearer) to take off on the wings of his own spirit, but will
leave him earthbound, stuck in the finite, the thisworldly. His
artwork may be good art in itself, but not good religious art. Too
much so-called religious art is of this earthbound quality.
It
should be noted that the sensible symbols themselves are not capable
of directly imaging or representing the Transcendent in the fullness
of it own reality, any more than our philosophical concepts, and in
fact less so. Their power comes from their ability to set
resonating the underlying dynamism of the human spirit toward the
Infinite and offer it a channel (perhaps, to change the metaphor, we
might say a lightning rod) through which it can flash into
consciousness, and thus allow our integral human consciousness,
mind, heart, and will, to soar for a moment toward the Transcendent
Magnet that draws it secretly all the time, the Good in which all
finite goods participate, the Ultimate Final Cause that draws us
implicitly through all limited particular final causes. This
radical dynamism of the human spirit toward the Infinite is the
dynamic a priori of the human spirit, constitutive of the very
nature of finite spirit. But the human spirit, in order to pass
from the state of latent active potency, just under the level of
consciousness, to actuality on the conscious level, needs to be
triggered by some initial reference to the world of sense and
imagination, since the human act of knowledge is the act of the
whole human being, soul and body together.
Once triggered off by the sensible image, this dynamism of the
spirit can use the latter as a springboard to reach out toward the
Transcendent in two main ways: (1) in a purely intellectual way by
the use of abstract analogous philosophical concepts, or (2) in a
more total existential way, by the use of sense images as symbols
which set resonating the integral psychic structure of man, mind,
will, imagination, emotion—or, if you will, to use the synthetic
term preferred by the oriental tradition, the entire “heart” of man.
The intellectual path of concepts points more accurately and
explicitly toward the Infinite as infinite. But because these
concepts are so abstract and imprecise, they move only the mind.
The path of the sensible symbol, on the other hand, is much vaguer
and less explicit on the intellectual level, but by its much richer
evocative power it sets resonating the whole psyche (including the
body in which it is so deeply rooted), and thus tends to draw the
whole person into existential communion with the symbolized that it
points to. The aim of the abstract concept (or, more accurately, on
the judgment in which the concept is imbedded) is to lead us toward
deeper intellectual comprehension of the Transcendent Mystery; the
aim of the artistic symbol is to lead us into deeper existential
communion with this same Mystery. Both ways are needed, and
complement each other; neither can supplant the other.
The
last point to note in our discussion of the text of St. Thomas is
his interesting addition about our mode of knowing purely spiritual
beings, which are higher than ourselves but still finite. St.
Thomas says that because they are not the efficient cause of our
material cosmos or ourselves we cannot use the path of causal
similitude, the first of the Three Ways by which we come to know
God. Hence we can know them, he says only “by comparison or
remotion.” He does not not even mention here the excess us or élan
of the mind. This seems to suggest that it is in fact easier to
come to know God and something about his nature than to know angels.
This is certainly true with respect to our first coming to know of
the existence of angels compared to knowing the existence of God.
Since they are not the cause of our universe, it is not possible to
make a firm argument that they must exist under pain of rendering
our universe unintelligible, as one can do for the existence of God
in the Thomistic perspective. One has to learn of the existence of
angels (both good and bad) either through some Revelation, which we
accept on faith, or by some merely suasive argument (such as that
they are needed to complete the harmony of the universe as
expression of God).
Does this inferiority of our knowledge of the existence of angels
compared to our knowledge of the existence of God hold also for an
understanding of their nature? St. Thomas does not tell us here.
But one might make the case that this position could be defended,
since our knowledge of God contains one added note of precision that
cannot be applied to any finite spirit, namely, that God is the
infinite fullness of all perfection and situated very precisely at
the apex of all reality and value for us. Thus it is easier for our
concepts about God, joined with the pointing index of infinity, to
tap into the underlying dynamism of the human spirit toward the
Infinite and stimulate the inner leap of the spirit (excessus)
toward its ultimate Source and Goal. It would then follow, if we
transfer this argument to the sphere of religious art, that it would
be in principle easier to create a work of art symbolizing God (or
at least our relation to God) than one symbolizing angels.
Interesting thesis! and one that contains not a little truth.
However, we do find in fact that the symbolic representation of
higher spiritual beings (e.g., angels, both good and evil) is common
in religious art, not only in the Christian but in other traditions
as well. And the experience of the viewer, including the leap of
the mind beyond the sensible symbol, seems to be very similar to the
experience of religious art referring directly to God himself. So I
would prefer to fit it in to the same basic structure outlined
above, using not the causal similitude between God and creature but
the doctrine of participation of all finite beings in the unitary
perfection of God. Since all finite beings, both material and
spiritual, proceed from the same ultimate Source, and every effect
must to some degree resemble its cause, it follows that all of them
must participate in some analogous way in the basic transcendental
perfections of God, such as existence, unity, activity, power,
goodness, beauty, etc. This immediately posits a bond of analogical
similitude between all creatures, reaching in an ascending hierarchy
of being from the lowest material being all the way up to Infinite
Spirit. Furthermore all intellectual beings share a bond of
analogous similitude in the order of spirit, both with God and each
other. It follows that in a work of art, through the dialectical
interplay of comparison and remotion, similitude and dissimilitude,
the dynamism of our spirit can be stimulated to leap beyond the
sensible symbol toward something higher and better than ourselves,
along the way of God, along the ascending ladder of being towards
its infinite apex, hence worthy of our profound reverence. The
attractive power of the higher, precisely because it leads along the
path of participated goodness towards the infinite goodness of the
Source, can trigger the élan of the spirit to soar beyond our
present level of incarnate spirit towards the realm of pure finite
spirit, even though this be only a finite participation in Infinite
Spirit, which alone is the ultimate Magnet activating the entire
life of our minds and wills and enabling them to transcend their own
level.
III. Conclusion
Our
aim has been to follow the lead of St. Thomas in uncovering the
underlying metaphysical and epistemological structures supporting
the ability of authentic religious art to give symbolic expression
to the Transcendent and our relation to it. The epistemological
structure is based on St. Thomas’ distinctive theory of human
understanding as a synthesis of sense and intellect, according to
which any act of the intellect must first find footing in some image
of the senses or the imagination and then use it as a springboard to
go beyond the sense world, either to the formal essence of the
sensible thing itself or to its cause. The ascent of the mind to
know God takes place through a triple process of (1) causal
similitude, (2) negation of all imperfections and limits, i.e.,
negation of exact or univocal similitude, and (3) reaffirmation of
the purified perfection together with a projection of it toward
infinite fullness, accomplished by a burst into consciousness of the
radical unrestricted drive of the human spirit toward the Infinite—a
drive that is constitutive of the very nature of finite spirit as
such. This élan or excessus of spirit enables it to leap
beyond its own level and all finite beings to point obscurely
through the very awareness of its own dynamism (the pondus animae
meae of St. Augustine) toward the Infinite. The metaphysical
underpinnings of this theory of knowledge are (1) the integral union
of body and soul to form a single being with a single unified field
of consciousness; (2) the radical drive of the spirit (intellect and
will) toward the Infinite as ultimate Final Cause; and (3) the
doctrine of creation, ex-plained in terms of participation and
causal simili-tude, which grounds a bond of analogical similitude
not only of all creatures with God but also of all creatures with
each other.
The
inner dynamism of the authentically religious work of art follows
the same path of ascent. It must first put forth a positive
symbolic expression of some similitude with the Transcendent, then
partially negate this similitude, by introducing some element of
strangeness or dissimilitude with our ordinary experience on a
finite material level. The dialectical interplay of similitude and
dissimilitude must then be artfully contrived so that by its very
structure it taps into and awakens the ever present but latent
dynamism toward the Infinite that lies at the very root of all
finite spirit, so that our spirit takes wings and soars in an élan
or excessus (a going out of itself) reaching beyond the
sensible symbol toward lived communion of the integral human being
with the Transcendent Reality it is trying to express. The genius
of the artist consists in his ability to give symbolic expression to
dissimilitude within similitude in such a way as to set resonating
the deep innate longing within us all for the Transcendent, so that
the work of art finally leads us beyond itself in a
self-transcending movement, “dying that we might live” more
deeply—an analogue of the loss of self in order to find the true
self characteristic of all authentic religious living. To sum it up
in St. Thomas’ own extraordinarily terse but pregnant terms:
compara-tio, remotio, excessus.
1
For a good explanation of the meaning of symbol and its role in
religious experience and worship, see Thomas Fawcett, The
Symbolic Language of Religion (Minneapolis: Augsburg Publishing
House, 1971).
2
Translation by Anton Pegis: Basic Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas
(New York: Random House. 1944), I: 808-810.
3
The entire book by Karl Rahner—Spirit in the World, trans.
William Dych (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968)—is an extended
commentary on this one article of St. Thomas. Although we do not
agree with all the details of the author’s interpretation of St.
Thomas, his exposition of the main point of the text—the dependence
of all man’s knowing on the senses as a starting point—is very rich
and illuminating.
4
For a convenient reference, see my The Philoso-phical Approach to
God (Winston-Salem: Wake Forest University Publications. 1980),
chapter 2: The Metaphysical Ascent to God.
5
Cf. ST I. q. 12. art. 12; I. q. 43. art. 7: “Now the nature of man
requires that he be led by the hand to the invisible by visible
things (ut per visibilia ad invi-sibilia manuducatur).”
6
For the medieval Franciscan doctrine of the two faces of the soul as
proposed by St. Bonaventure, see E. Gilson, History of Christian
Philosophy in the Middle Ages (New York: Random House. 1955), p.
336.
7
Cf. Quaestiones disputatae de anima, art. 17, my translation:
“For it is manifest that the human soul united to the body has,
because of its union with the body, its face turned toward what is
beneath it: hence it is not brought to fulfillment except by what it
receives from these lower things, namely by forms (species)
abstracted from phantasms. Hence it cannot arrive at the knowledge
either of itself or of other things except insofar as it is led by
the hand by these abstracted forms.”
8
This notion of the radical unrestricted dynamism of the human spirit
toward the unlimited horizon of being and ultimately to the Infinite
itself as the fullness and source of all being is clearly in St.
Thomas, in his doctrine of the natural desire for the beatific
vision, but it has been highlighted as the foundation for all
metaphysics and natural theology by the Transcendental Thomist
School, e.g., Maré-chal, Rahner, Lonergan, etc. For a convenient
expo-sition see my Philosophical Approach to God, chapter 1:
The Turn to the Inner Way in Contemporary Thomism.
9
Cf. ST 1, q. 12, art. 12, and elsewhere.
10
Cf. O. von Simpson, The Gothic Cathedral (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1956), chapters 3-4.