At the fourth meeting of the New York University Institute of
Philosophy in 1960, Father Clarke contributed critiques of fellow
symposiasts, Paul Ziff, Reinhold Niebuhr, and Paul Tillich. Sidney
Hook, who organized the symposium, edited the proceedings for
publication in 1961 as
Religious Experience and Truth: A Symposium,
New York University Press, arranging Clarke’s critiques as three
sections of Chapter 28, “On Professors Ziff, Niebuhr, and Tillich”
(224-230). The following remarks on a paper by
Reinhold Niebuhr
appear on pages 226-227.
Anthony Flood
May 10, 2010
On Professor Tillich’s Paper, “The Meaning and
Justification of Religious Symbols”
W. Norris Clarke, S.J.
Since
we did not have available the text of the paper actually given by
Professor Tillich, I must trust my memory in commenting on the gist of
what was said, using as a guide his previously published paper on the
subject. (The latter paper, by the way, I found to be an
extraordinarily rich, profound, and illumin-ating—and one with which I
could agree to a very large extent. As he understands symbolic
language, I do not think there is as much difference or oppo-sition as
he would seem to think between it and ana-logical language as I
understand it. A Catholic theo-logian, Father Gustave Weigel, who knows
the thought of Professor Tillich well, is now using the term “symbolic
language” more and more as a syno-nym for “analogical language,” and did
so, in fact, throughout his own paper at this same gathering.)
The one
point I would like to comment on is Professor Tillich’s fear that
analogy applied to God is “too static” and his attempts to fix and hold
in a finite concept the ineffable and utterly transcendent nature of
God. I would like to link this with the constant difficulty voiced by
logicians, philosophers of science, linguistic analysts, and others
during the symposium: by what right can we take terms from ordinary ex-perience
and language—which all the theistic philo-sophers and theologians agree
must be done—and apply them with a significant shift and extension of
meaning to something, God, which we cannot directly experience (unless
we are mystics—and then we cannot communicate literally what we have
experi-enced)? Must not the new elements introduced into the concepts
when applied beyond our own experi-ence be necessarily a blank of
positive meaning, a pure shot in the dark?
This is
a genuine and profound problem, the main problem in the
philosophy of religion, one might well say. I have time here to point
out only what seems to me the key notion which permits a working out of
the solution. The objectors commonly presume that what is going on is
this: we take a term which has one definite conceptual content as drawn
from and applied to our own experience, then when we apply it to God, we
add on to it a new element which is quite extraneous to the latter and
whose meaning we cannot possibly understand from this experience. If
this were the case, we would indeed have made an illegitimate conceptual
and linguistic leap.
But the
whole point of the application of analogy to God is that the extra
dimension of content intro-duced into the concepts thus applied is not
dragged in arbitrarily from outside what we discern in our
experience. It is rather a dynamic exigency, a thrust, a direction,
already imbedded deep in the intelligible texture of the finite
world of our own ex-perience. As we confront the world with reflective
intelligence, the profound and ineluctable exigencies of our intellect
and will for total and unconditioned truth, being, goodness, perfection,
etc. help us to discern in the finite, imperfect beings of our ex-perience
their radical state of deficiency or imper-fection, both in the
possession of the perfections they manifest as well as in their
incapacity to satisfy the exigencies built into our intellectual nature.
The
notion of limited and deficient perfection is here the operative one
that acts as a springboard to point the mind beyond its present
experience. Found within the beings of our experience, it yet,
by the very dynamism that constitutes its intelligibility, points beyond
itself to a mysterious source which is pure, simple, unconditioned,
hence infinite, plenitude of what we experience here as “only so much
and no more,” i.e., as radically deficient, limited, and unsa-tisfying.
We do not properly look away from the finite to find the
Infinite. We rather find the exigency for the infinite written right
into the intelligible texture of the finite recognized as such, and
we find it by looking more deeply into the finite itself.
Note
that I am not arguing the point here whether or not one can construct a
valid proof of the real existence of the Infinite from the finite,
though I believe that with care one can. I am making only this point:
the meaningfulness of our language and thought about the
Infinite finds its support in the profound human experience of
discerning within our world the latter’s intrinsic character of radical
limitation, deficiency, and inability to satisfy our own deepest
exigencies of intellect and will. And the notion of deficient or
limited goodness is, by its very inner structure, both psychologically
and conceptual-ly, a highly dynamic one which necessarily and
importunately points beyond itself to a mysterious plenitude in the same
line, affirmable—thought not representable—in the dim mirror of need,
desire, and hope.
Therefore, analogous language which is combined with the peculiar
“pointing-concept” of infinity, what we might analogously call the
“infinity-operator”—and only such language can be legitimately applied
to God—contains within itself all the dynamism of the negative theology
whose need Professor Tillich has so clearly seen, and this precisely
because it includes within its very meaning-structure the expression of
the mind’s own act of transcending all possible finite experience.
It may
still be objected that, however, we have no positive idea of what, for
example, a beyond-finite, or beyond-human, love might be; it might no
longer be love at all but something quite different. The answer here is
two-fold. First, through the causal argument to the dependence of the
finite on an infinite Source, combined with reflection on our own
exigencies of intellect and will, we can say this much with certainty
about what we call “infinite Love”: it cannot fall below the core
of positive perfection, goodness, being, etc. which we have found in the
finite participant within our experience, but must be at least all of
that and could be, still better, incal-culably more. In other words,
when we apply the attribute love to God we are using it, not as a
“ceiling-concept” limiting its content to what our experience of love
is, but as a “floor-concept,” so to speak, indicating at least
all this positive value and whatever else is better, as long as it does
not negate or evacuate the positive content of the authentic value we
have experienced in human love. Secondly, we must be careful before
applying any concept of God (intrinsic analogy applies not only to terms
but to their conceptual content) to see if it can sustain “purification”
from imperfection or limit as an essential and irreducible part of its
meaning. Thus love would meet this test, not sexual love;
so would intellectual knowledge, but not knowledge by
inference, and so forth. I trust this may help somewhat to show how
sense can be made out of analogical language applied to God.
Clarke Page