At the fourth meeting of the New York University Institute of
Philosophy in 1960, Father Clarke contributed critiques of fellow
symposiasts, Paul Ziff, Reinhold Niebuhr, and Paul Tillich. Sidney
Hook, who organized the symposium, edited the proceedings for
publication in 1961 as
Religious Experience
and Truth: A Symposium,
New York University Press, arranging Clarke’s critiques as three
sections of Chapter 28, “On Professors Ziff, Niebuhr, and Tillich”
(224-230). The following remarks on a paper by
Paul Ziff
appear on pages 224-226.
Anthony Flood
May 10, 2010
On Professor Ziff’s Paper, “About ‘God’”
W. Norris Clarke, S.J.
One of
the special merits of Professor Ziff’s paper, and even more, of his
remarks in the discussion, was his care in not closing off prematurely
the possibility of meaningful discourse about God by adducing
oversimplified linguistic impasses of all sorts, as has so frequently
been done by other analytic philoso-phers. In so doing he has rendered
a distinct service to philosophical maturity and refinement of concepts
in dealing with this difficult problem.
There
are two criticisms, however, which I should still like to make
concerning his position as expressed in the paper. The first concerns
how the term “God” functions in religious discourse. (I accept his
distinc-tion between religious language and religious dis-course as
exact and well-taken for the English lan-guage.) For Professor Ziff, it
functions as a proper name, and, therefore, presumably not as a
descrip-tion. In the case of other ordinary terms in the language, one
must indeed choose between these two uses. But it is just one of the
unusual features of this most unusual of terms, “God,” that it combines
the two functions indissolubly. In would say that, in view of its
actual use down the ages in Western reli-gious discourse (monotheistic
for many centuries), it functions primarily as a description; but, since
one of the notes of the description is that it can be verified by only
one referent (“God” means the one infinite Creator of all other
things), this particular descriptive term can also be, and
traditionally has been, used as a direct form of address or as a proper
name. Some-thing of the same thing has happened in the case of terms
like “Love,” “Truth,” etc. though not in so firm-ly crystallized a
manner as with “God” (it could hap-pen also with a term like “Sun”), so
that one can or could say in the direct address of prayer: “O Love,” “O
Truth,” (or O Sun”), like “O God.” In the case of “God,” it seems to me
that any adequate analysis of the role played by the term must
indissolubly join these two uses: description and proper name.
The
second point concerns section 23 [of Pro-fessor Ziff’s paper], on the
impossibility of the plain man’s conception of God being compatible with
the requirements for omnipotence. “It is a tenet of pre-sent physical
theory that no physical object can at-tain a velocity greater than the
speed of light. Con-sequently, according to present physical theory, no
being has it in its power to transport a stone from the earth to the sun
in one second. But this is to say that no omnipotent being exists.
Hence, according to present physical theory, nothing answering to the
plain man’s conception of God exists.”
The
difficulty here is that the requirements laid down for omnipotence
applied to actions in the physical world contain a hidden analytical
contra-diction, which rules out a priori any possible meaning or
verification for the term “omnipotence.” Such a contradiction does not
exist, however, either in the conception of the genuine “plain man,” nor
in that of the careful theologian or theistic philosopher. In effect,
the conditions laid down by Professor Ziff come to this: God could not
transport a stone a certain distance both according to the laws
of an Einsteinian universe (which He himself, according to the
supposition, has freely set up and freely maintains) and at the same
time in contradiction to those same laws. Obviously He could
not, since it would involve His simultaneous ratification and violation
of the same laws with respect to the same object. But I believe it is
quite easy to show that not only the theologian, but even more the plain
man, understands omnipotence in such a context as signifying the power
of God to suspend or change at will the physical laws He
himself has set up, in order to effectuate some good. In other words, a
physical impossibility is always a conditioned one, the condi-tion being
the continued free willing of the present system of physical laws by
God—a condition revocable by the same will; a logical or metaphysical
impossibility would alone be an unconditioned one, whose violation would
be impossible even to God and would involve no genuine limitation in
order of real being or real perfection, since it would imply the
positing of an internally contradictory nonbeing.
Clarke Page