The Principles of Creation in Art
Susanne K. Langer
In the study of music as a form of expression1
I came to the conclusion that music “expresses” feeling as words express
ideas, rather than as tears and laughter express emotions; that it is a
symbol whereby we understand the characteristic forms of
sentience, because the symbolic structure of sound articulates with
great precision the structure of feeling in its passage; and that it is
not necessarily a symptom showing that the performer has a
certain feeling, or that the composer had it when he invented the
expressive form.
The problem of symbolism and significance involved in such a thesis is,
of course, still open to debate, but I do not wish to re-iterate my
views on it here. Let us accept, for the moment, the notion that any
logical form, even other than what is known as “discursive” form, may
symbolize factors in experience wherein the same pattern can be
detected, and that music presents to us the life of feeling because
music and sentience have a similar structure, a common pattern. The
purpose of this essay is to set forth some ideas about art in general,
which follow from that assumption.
A theory of music is one thing, a general theory of art is quite
another. It is plausible enough to call musical form a direct
presentation of feeling, but what of the forms created in painting and
sculpture, which throughout the ages have been copied from animate or
inanimate nature, and thus appeared to present objects rather than
feelings? Furthermore, if we do extend the theory of “non-discursive
symbolization” to cover plastic art as well as music where does that
leave us in regard to literature, whlch uses the discursive medium of
language as its prime, if not sole, material? Shall we, like
Schopenhauer, interpose a realm of Platonic Ideas to overcome the
particularity of depicted objects, and make music an exception to the
scheme because it sets forth its vital import directly?
The best approach to all these problems is, I believe, a consistent
pursuit of the central idea of non-discursive symbolic form; and a
general solution results if we consider any and every art as the
making of the symbol. This is the principle of generalization,
which I propose to apply undistrac-tedly to the consecutive questions
that arise in the course of any complex problem. Most people can recall
the distress they suffered in school when faced with mathematical
questions, until they learned the most important lesson of elementary
mathematics—to trust the general principle, and always seek a
transformation of apparently recalcitrant instances that will make them
amenable to its use—in other words, make them “examples” of a known and
negotiable form. The principle here proposed is really very powerful to
distinguish and yet relate the several arts, and show them all equally
creative, equally important and original, equally intellectual,
emotional, and moral, yet each independent, and ultimately
self-sufficient.
A work of art is essentially an appearance, a “form” in the broadest
sense of that very broad word. I do not say a sensuous form, as most
aestheticians would, because in some arts, e.g. literature, the sensuous
element is variable and sometimes even negligible. But every art-work
is a perceptual form, addressed to some phase of direct perception:
sight, hearing, or their combination, or to that less-known organ of
direct intuitions, imagination, whereby we perceive separate events,
each under its own Gestalt, in the fluid welter of experience.
It is only by virtue of form that a work can have emotive import,
because its form is what makes it a possible symbol; so the artist’s
first aim is, necessarily, to make a form apparent, and indeed to make
the impression of form paramount.
In practical life we are only vaguely aware of perceptual forms while we
are dealing with real objects. Sensory impressions are mixed up,
abbreviated, half-noted, as we pass with the least possible effort from
them to our beliefs and interests in the object, or objects, which they
signify. It really is only when their pragmatic functions fail—that is,
when the expectations we normally base on them go unfulfilled—that we
note sense-data as sheer appearances instead of properties of
things; and then we call them “illusions.”
Every work of art has an air of being somehow an illusion. This is most
obvious, of course, in works that simulate the form of real objects or
events, like pictures or stage actions, which show us an image of
familiar experience even while we know that the scene exists only for
our contemplation and not for practical purposes. The fictitious nature
of such images is so striking that it has led many people to regard art
as essentially “make-believe,” escape from distasteful reality into a
better world of dream, a playful self -deception.
Yet this theory soon reaches its limits; for, although every work of art
is essentially an appearance, not every appearance is deceptive. A vase
does not make us believe in anything but a vase. A building does not
pretend to be a tree or a rocking-horse. Nevertheless, in so far as the
vase or the building is a work of art, it stands before us as an image,
because it addresses itself so forcibly to our vision that this appeal
makes all its practical properties and relations irrelevant; and in
receiving it as a completely visual thing we abstract its appearance
from its material existence. It does not need to fool us. It only has
to dissociate itself from the actual world (the world of our actions),
and present a coherent and entirely perceptual form to become, for the
beholder, an image.
The word “image” is almost inseparably wedded to the sense of sight
because our stock example of it is the looking-glass world that gives us
a visible copy of the things opposite the mirror without a tactual or
other sensory replica of them. But some of the alternative words that
have been used to denote the virtual character of so-called “aesthetic
objects” escape this association. Carl Gustav Jung, for instance,
speaks of it as “semblance.” His exemplary case of illusion is not the
reflected image, but the dream; and in a dream there are sounds, smells,
feelings, happenings, intentions, dangers—all sorts of things
invisible—as well as sights, and all are equally unreal by the measures
of public fact. Dreams do not consist entirely of images, but everything
in them is imaginary. The music heard in a dream comes from a virtual
piano under the hands of an apparent musician; the whole experience is a
semblance of events. It may be as vivid as any reality, yet it is what
Schiller called “Schein.”
Schiller was the first thinker who saw what really makes “Schein,”
or semblance, important for art: the fact that it liberates
perception—and with it, the power of conception—from all practical
purposes, and lets the mind dwell on the sheer appearance of things.
The function of artistic illusion is not “make-believe,” as many
philosophers and psychologists assume, but the very opposite,
disengagement from belief—the contemplation of sensory qualities without
their usual meanings of “Here’s that chair,” “That’s my telephone,”
“These figures ought to add up to the bank’s statement,” etc. The
knowledge that what is before us has no practical significance in the
world is what enables us to give attention to its appearance as such.
Everything has an aspect of appearance as well as of causal importance.
Even so non-sensuous a thing as a fact or a possibility appears
this way to one person and that way to another. That is its
“semblance,” whereby it may “resemble” other things, and—where the
semblance is used to mislead judgment about its causal properties—is
said to “dissemble” its nature. Where we know that an “object” consists
entirely in its semblance, that apart from its appearance it has no
cohesion and unity—like a rainbow, or a shadow—we call it a merely
virtual object, or an illusion. In this literal sense a picture is an
illusion; we see a face, a flower, a vista of sea or land, etc., and
know that if we stretched out our hand to it we would touch a surface
smeared with paint.
The object seen is given only to the sense of sight. That is the chief
purpose of “imitation,” or “objective” painting. To present things to
sight which are known to be illusion is a ready (though by no means
necessary) way to abstract visible forms from their usual
context.
Normally, of course, semblance is not misleading; a thing is what it
seems. But even where there is no deception, it may happen that an
object—a vase, for instance, or a building—arrests one sense so
exclusively that it seems to be given to that sense alone, and all its
other properties become irrelevant. It is quite honestly there, but is
important only for (say) its visual character. Then we are prone
to accept it as a vision; there is such a concentration on appearance
that one has a sense of seeing sheer appearance—that is, a sense of
illusion.
Herein lies the “unreality” of art that tinges even perfectly real
objects like pots, textiles, and temples. Whether we deal with actual
illusions or with such quasi-illusions made by artistic emphasis, what
is presented is, in either case, just what Schiller called “Schein”;
and a pure semblance, or “Schein,” among the husky substantial
realities of the natural world, is a strange guest. Strangeness,
separateness, other-ness—call it what you will—is its obvious lot.
The semblance of a thing, thus thrown into relief, is its direct
aesthetic quality. According to several eminent critics, this is what
the artist tries to reveal for its own sake. But the emphasis on
quality, or essence, is really only a stage in artistic conception. It
is the making of a rarefied element that serves, in its turn, for the
making of something else—the imaginal art—work itself. And this form is
the non-discursive but articulate symbol of feeling.
Here is I believe the clear statement of what Clive Bell dealt with
rather confusedly in a passage that identifies “significant form” (not,
however, significant of anything) with “aesthetic quality.” The setting
forth of pure quality, or semblance, creates a new dimension apart from
the familiar world. That is its office. In this dimension, all
artistic forms are conceived and presented. Since their substance is
illusion or “Schein” they are, from the standpoint of practical
reality, mere forms; they exist only for the sense or the
imagination that perceives them—like the fata morgana, or the elaborate,
improbable structure of events in our dreams. The function of
“semblance” is to give forms a new embodiment in purely qualitative,
unreal instances, setting them free from their normal embodiment in real
things so they may be recognized in their own right, and freely
conceived and composed in the interest of the artist’s ultimate
aim—significance, or logical expression.
All forms in art, then, are abstracted forms; their content is only a
semblance, a pure appearance, whose function is to make them, too,
apparent—more freely and wholly apparent than they could be if they were
exemplified in a context of real circumstances and anxious interest. It
is in this elementary sense that all art is abstract. Its very
substance, quality without practical significance, is an abstraction
from material existence; and exemplification in this illusory or
quasi-illusory medium makes the forms of things (not only shapes, but
logical forms, e.g., proportions among the degrees of importance in
events, or among different speeds in motions) present themselves in
abstracto. This fundamental abstractness belongs just as forcibly
to the most illustrative murals and most realistic plays, provided they
are good after their kind, as to the deliberate abstractions that are
schematic representations or entirely non-representative designs.
But abstract form as such is not an artistic ideal. To carry abstraction
as far as possible, and achieve pure form in only the barest conceptual
medium is a logician’s business, not a painter’s or poet’s. In art,
forms are abstracted only to be made clearly apparent, and are freed
from their common uses only to be put to new uses: to act as symbols, to
become expressive of human feeling.
An artistic symbol is a much more intricate thing than what we usually
think of as a “form,” because it involves all the relationships of its
elements to one another, all similarities and differences of quality,
not only geometric or other familiar relations. That is why qualities
enter directly into the form itself, not as its contents, but as
constitutive elements in it. Our scientific convention of abstracting
mathematical forms, which do not involve quality, and fitting them to
experience, always makes qualitative factors “content”; and as
scientific conventions rule our academic thinking, it has usually been
taken for granted that in understanding art, too, one should think of
form as opposed to qualitative “content.” But on this uncritical
assumption the whole conception of form and content comes to grief, and
analysis ends in the confused assertion that art is “formed content,”
form and content are one. The solution of that paradox is, that a work
of art is a structure whose interrelated elements are often qualities,
or properties of qualities such as their degrees of intensity; that
qualities enter into the form and in this way are as much one with it as
the relations which they, and they only, have; and that to speak of them
as “content,” from which the form could be abstracted logically, is
nonsense. The form is built up out of relations peculiar to them; they
are formal elements in the structure, not contents.
Yet forms are either empty abstractions, or they do have a content; and
artistic forms have a very special one, namely their import.
They are logically expressive, or significant, forms. They are symbols
for the articulation of feeling, and convey the elusive and yet familiar
pattern of sentience. And as essentially symbolic forms they lie in a
different dimension from physical objects as such. They belong to the
same category as language, though their logical form is a different one,
and as myth and dream, though their function is not the same.
Herein lies the “strangeness” or “otherness” that characterizes an
artistic object. The form is immediately given to perception, and yet
it reaches beyond itself; it is semblance, but seems to be charged with
reality. Like speech, that is physically nothing but little buzzing
sounds, it is filled with its meaning, and its meaning is a reality. In
a “presentational” symbol the symbolic import permeates the whole
structure, because every articulation of that structure is an
articulation of the idea it conveys; the meaning (or, if that word is to
be reserved for the assigned signification characteristic of words, let
us say “the import”) is the content of the symbolic form, given with it,
as it were, to perception.
A work of art differs from all other beautiful things in that it is “a
glass and a transparency”—not, in any relevant way, a thing at
all, but a symbol. Every good philosopher or critic of art realizes, of
course, that feeling is somehow expressed in art; but as long as
a work of art is viewed primarily as an “arrangement” of sensuous
elements for the sake of some inexplicable aesthetic satisfaction, the
problem of expressiveness is really an alien issue.
What art expresses is not actual feeling, but ideas of feeling;
as language does not express actual things and events but ideas of them.
Art is expressive through and through—every line, every sound, every
gesture; and therefore it is a hundred per cent symbolic. It is not
sensuously pleasing and also symbolic; the sensuous quality is in
the service of its vital import. A work of art is far more symbolic
than a word, which can be learned and even employed without any
knowledge of its meaning; for a “presentational” symbol presents
its import directly to any beholder who is sensitive at all to
articulated forms in the given medium.
A purely perceptual form, however, must be clearly given and understood
before it can convey any import, especially where there is no
conventional reference whereby the import is assigned to it as its
unequivocal meaning, but the congruence of the symbolic form and the
form of some vital experience must be directly perceived by the force of
“Gestalt” alone. Hence the paramount importance of
abstracting the form, banning all irrelevancies that might obscure
its logic, and especially divesting it of all its usual meanings so it
may be open to new ones. The first thing is to estrange it from
actuality, to give it “otherness,” “self-sufficiency”; this is done by
creating a realm of illusion, in which it functions as “Schein,”
mere semblance, free from worldly offices. The second thing is to make
it plastic, so it may be manipulated in the interests of expression
instead of practical signification. This is achieved by the same
means—uncoupling it from practical life, abstracting it as a free
perceptual figment. Only such freed forms can be plastic, subject to
deliberate torsion, modification, and composition for the sake of
expressiveness. And finally, it must become “transparent”—which it does
when insight into the reality to be expressed, the Gestalt of
living experience, guides its author in creating it.
“Expression” in the logical sense—presentation of an idea through a
formal symbol—is the ruling power and purpose of art. And the symbol
is, from first to last, something created. The illusion, which
constitutes the work of art, is not a mere arrangement of given
materials in an aesthetically pleasing pattern; it is what results from
the arrangement, and is literally something the artist makes. It comes
with his work and passes away in its destruction.
To produce and sustain the essential illusion, set it off clearly from
the surrounding world of actuality, and articulate its form to the point
where it coincides unmistakably with forms of feeling and living, is the
artist’s task. To such ends he uses whatever materials lend themselves
to technical treatment—tones, colors, plastic substances, words,
gestures, or any other physical means. If we look, first of all, to the
plastic arts, we find from the very beginning the making of a semblance,
more general and thorough-going than any counterfeiting of objects: the
appearance of purely visual space, divorced from the space of actuality,
which is largely tactual or even conceptual (geometrically constructed).
This is a more fundamental aim than imitation; picturing things is only
one way of creating spatial forms for the eye alone, but the semblance
of space thus created is involved in any plastic work whatever, from
textile patterns to portraits and battle-scenes. The patterns, indeed,
have an interest of their own, because their motivation is primarily
artistic, whereas representative forms hide their true credentials
under the cloak of another office.
In all folk art, savage or civilized, there is a heritage of purely
decorative forms, two-dimensional, clear in outline, either in two
tones, or painted with simple, solid colors that fill the outlined
shapes. The immediate effect of such devices is to simplify perceptual
space by reducing it to only two dimensions. This simplification is the
primary education of artistic vision; it achieves the abstraction of
visual space from the confused actual realm by making the plane surface
paramount. The aim of decoration is to deploy definite forms and colors
in such a way that the eye is “satisfied,” i.e., that it accepts the
established two-dimensional space as sufficient and has no tendency to
go beyond it. The flowing lines, complementary areas clearly divided,
and contrasting, pure colors that are typical of decorative art all
serve this main purpose.
Decoration is, above all, an invitation to pure seeing.2 It is, therefore, a
natural preparation for drawing and painting, which—despite all common
factors—are something different. For graphic ornamentation aims merely
to simplify, and thus abstract, the visual character of space, by
projecting vision fully and freely in two dimensions; but genuine
pictorial art seeks to fill the illusory realm with expressive forms,
symbols of vital feeling, and often finds itself pushed far beyond the
elementary stages of space creation.
Yet even in the motifs of pure decoration—zigzags and S-curves,
parallels and spirals and loops—we find the basic principles of
expressiveness, forms that seem to “have life” not because they
represent anything living, but because they symbolize directly the
sense of life, which underlies all our feelings. In a little book
on design3
I find the following statement, made by the artist-author with perfectly
literal intent and evidently no consciousness whatever of using
metaphor: “Borders must move forward, and grow as they move.”
Now, what does it mean to say a border moves? The border is a
mark on a contrasting ground, perfectly stationary. When we draw it,
the pencil moves, the line or series of forms actually grows in one
direction. But suppose it is not even made in this fashion; suppose it
is made all at once, by block-printing. And perhaps we do not see it
made at all. Still the border “runs” along the edge of the tablecloth or
around the margins of a page. If it is supported by short tangential
lines the apparent movement is very much enhanced.
There are, of course, classical explanations of this phenomenon in terms
of eye-movements: the eye, it is said, is “carried” along a line as it
is in following a moving object, such as a mouse running across the
floor, and the association of our eye-movement with moving objects
prompts us to impute movement to the line. It is not unlikely that
eye-movements do play some part in the illusion, but they do not account
for it, for if they were always thus associated we could never
appreciate as stationary anything too big to be seen at the focal
center, i.e., without moving the eyes. Everything else should appear to
shift or mill around. Quite to the contrary, however, we are just as
likely to think of actual motion in terms of a fixed form. The mouse
running across the floor seems to cover a path that remains there, an
imaginary line.
The real connection between lines and motion is, I believe, that an
uninterrupted line serves us as a symbol of motion, and conveys
the idea of it exactly as any symbol conveys its message. In the
direct, intuitive appreciation of what may be termed “natural symbols,”4
the import is received like something inherent in the symbol; therefore
the running mouse seems to cover a path lying on the floor, and the
still, painted line seems to run. The reason is that both exemplify the
abstract principle of direction, by virtue of which they are
logically congruent enough to be symbols for one another; and in the
ordinary, intelligent use of vision, we let them stand proxy for each
other all the time, though we do not know it. This is not a function
that is first discursively conceived and then assigned a possible
symbol, but is non-discursively exhibited and then perceived long before
it is acknowledged in a scientific device (as it is in the language of
physics, where vectors are conventionally indicated by arrows). Motion,
therefore, is logically related to linear form, and where a line is
unbroken, and supporting forms tend to give it direction, the mere
perception of it is charged with the idea of motion, which shines
through our impression of the actual sense-datum and fuses with it in
apperception. The result is a very elementary artistic illusion (not
delusion, for, unlike delusion, it survives analysis), which we call
“living form.”
This term takes us back to Best-Maugard’s supposedly simple statement
(it is addressed to children!) : “Borders should move forward, and grow
as they move.” What does “grow” mean in this context? The border does
not grow bigger in design. No, but it seems to grow longer, for in its
seeming motion it does not vacate the places where it was before; like
the imaginary path of the mouse, it covers the ground, but continues in
one direction; and an ornamental border design appears to do this by a
law of its own.
Artistically, all motion is growth; not growth of things or creatures,
but of lines and spaces. The spiral—one of the simple motifs—is a
“dynamic” or progressing line, but what really seems to grow is a space,
the two-dimensional area it defines. This intimate relation between
movement and growth is what makes design—the grammar of visual
semblance—“living form,” in a perfectly intelligible sense. It is also
the surest refutation of any theory that reduces the experience of
movement in design to motions connoted by stimulation of tiny
muscular actions in the eye. The term “living form” is justified by a
logical connection that exists between a half-illusory datum—the
“growing” line or space—and the concept of life, whereby the former is a
natural symbol of the latter; for “living form” directly exhibits what
is the essence of life—incessant change, or process, articulating a
permanent form.
The path of a physical motion is an ideal line. In a line that “has
movement,” there is ideal motion. In the phenomenon we call “life,”
both continuous change and permanent form really exist; but the form is
made and maintained by a complicated disposition of mutual influences
among the physical units (atoms, molecules, then cells, then organs)
whereby changes tend always to occur in certain pre-eminent ways.
Instead of a simple law of transformation such as one finds in
inorganic change, living things exist by a cumulative process; they
assimilate elements of their surroundings to themselves, and these
elements fall under the law of change that is the organic form or
“life.” This assimilation of factors not originally belonging to the
organism, whereby they enter into its life, is the principle of growth.
A growing thing need not actually become bigger; since the metabolic
action does not stop when a non-living substance has been assimilated
and become alive, but is a continuous process of oxidation, separate
elements also resign from the organic pattern; they break down again
into inorganic structures, i.e., they die. When growth is more vigorous
than decay the living form grows larger; when they are balanced it is
self-perpetuating; when decay occurs faster than growth the organism is
decadent. At a certain point the metabolic process stops all at once,
and the life is finished.
Permanence of form, then, is the constant aim of living matter; not the
final goal (for it is what finally fails), but the thing that is
perpetually being achieved, and that is always, at every moment, an
achievement, because it depends entirely on the activity of “living.”
But “living” itself is a process, a continuous chance; if it stands
still the form disintegrates—for the permanence is a pattern of
changes.
Nothing, therefore, is as fundamental in the fabric of our feeling as
the sense of permanence and change and their intimate unity. What w
call “motion” in art is not necessarily change of place, but is
change made perceivable, i.e., imaginable, in any way
whatever. Anything that symbolizes change so we seem to behold it is
what artists, with more intuition than convention, call a “dynamic”
element. It may be a “dynamic accent” in music, physically nothing but
loudness, or a word charged above others with emotion, or a color that
is “exciting” where it stands, i.e., physically stimulating.
A form that exemplifies permanence, such as a fixed line or a delimited
space (the most permanent anchors of vision), yet symbolizes
motion, carries with it the concept of growth, because growth is the
normal operation of those two principles conjoined in mutual
dependence. Therefore Best-Maugard’s metaphorical statement: “Borders
should move forward, and grow as they move,” is perfectly rational if we
consider that, and why, they seem to do these things. But why
“should” they be drawn to seem like that? Because this illusion, this
seeming, is the real symbol of feeling. The elementary pattern of
feeling expressed in such world-accepted forms symbolizing “growth” is
the sense of life, the most primitive “fulfillment”; and it is
not mirrored in the physical lines, but in the created thing, the
“motions” they have. The dynamic pattern, which is actually an
illusion, is what “copies” the form of vital feeling. It is in order to
be expressive that borders should move and grow.
Very early in the evolution of design we meet the great principle of
graphic expression: the possibility of picturing things. A simple
circle decorated with surrounding secondary forms, half-circles,
zigzags, or what-not, immediately yields a flower-shape—fantastic,
schematic, but exactly the sort of flower pattern one finds in Persian
shawls and French hour-books and on Mexican pots. The astounding thing
is that these shapes are so unmistakably flowers. The same convincing
representational function gives us birds, beasts, men, moon and stars.
The principle of representation serves to organize forms and makes much
greater elaboration possible without confusing the eye. The forceful
implication in the essentially decorative character of primitive art and
folk-art, and in the fact that naturalism grows with sophistication,
seems to me to be that graphic representation does not spring from
copying of direct visual impressions which are then “composed” into
design but, on the contrary, arises from ornamental forms that are seen
to have representative powers. It is formulation, shaping, defining of
the impressions themselves, and is not copying at all, but symbolizing
from the outset. In short, form is first, and pictorial meaning is
read into it.5
The higher principle of organization, however, becomes dominant as the
artist’s imagination produces more involved, asymmetrical, and subtle
forms, created not only by obvious means like outlines and pure colors,
but also by illusions of receding space and the orientation of units of
design toward each other. The interpretation of such units as forms of
objects is an inestimable aid in the creation of new spatial
relationships, in distributing centers of interest and composing them
into a visual unity. For centuries art evolved mainly on
representational guidelines; and, as in decorative design we speak of
zigzags and circles as “motifs,” so now we apply “motif” to what is
pictured in the forms.
But no matter how many possibilities are opened to the artistic
imagination by the power of representing things, imitation is never the
main device in organization. The primary interest is always design, and
the very measure of an artist is his instinct for transforming his
actual perceptions into wholly plastic elements as he works with them.
As we pass from the study of naive design to a more ambitious literature
of aesthetics, dealing with the highest art-forms we meet almost at once
the same fundamental principle—the primacy of form. Adolf Hildebrand,
for instance, in the first paragraphs of his brief but significant book,
The Problem of Form in Painting and Sculpture, distinguishes
between natural perception and artistic, or, as he calls it,
“architectonic” perception, which “enables us to realize a unity of form
lacking in objects themselves as they appear in Nature.” What he calls
the “architectonic process” is the transformation of natural appearances
into pictorial ones, or design in a broad sense; and this process
is as old as art itself.
“Reviewing the artistic production of earlier times,” he says, “we find
that the architectonic structure of a work of art stands out everywhere
as the paramount factor, whereas mere imitation is a thing which has
only gradually developed. Its is, in fact, instinctive with us to
combine the piece-work of perception into an ideal whole.”
The great difference between the common form of perception and the
“architectonic” or artistic is that the former is a product of all our
senses working together, and aided, furthermore, by memory and
inference, whereas the latter must be achieved solely by one organ, the
eye. If we want to make a semblance that shall address itself to sight
alone we must, therefore, have visual substitutes for
everything that other kinds of experience usually supply. The
“architectonic process,” then, is the construction and ordering of
forms in space in such a way that they define and organize the space.
But a perceptually defined space is a shape: so the complete shaping of
a given visual field is a work of pictorial art. Design, therefore, is
the essence of drawing and painting, and as simple decorative forms are
its lowest terms, composition in color and depth is its highest
evolution. For the true aim of plastic art, as Hildebrand conceives it,
is to make space visible, and its unity and continuity sensible.
Here we seem, however, to encounter a philosophical difficulty; for
space, as we know it in the practical world, has no shape. Even in
science it has none, though it has “form.” There are spatial relations,
but there is no concrete totality of space. Space itself is amorphous
in our active lives and purely abstract in scientific thought. It is a
substrate of all our experience, but it is never an entity. How, then,
can it be “organized,” “shaped,” or “articulated”? We meet all these
terms in the most serious literature of aesthetics.
The answer is, I think, that the space in which we live and act is not
what is treated in art at all. The harmoniously organized space in a
picture is not experiential space, known by sight and touch, by free
motion and restraint, far and near sounds, voices lost or re-echoed. It
is an entirely visual affair; for touch and hearing and muscular action
it does not exist. For them there is a flat canvas, relatively small, or
a cool blank wall, where for the eye there is deep space full of shapes.
This purely visual space is an illusion, for our sensory experiences do
not agree on it in their report. Pictorial space is not only organized
by means of color (including black and white and the gamut of grays
between them), it is created; without the organizing shapes it is simply
not there. Like the space “behind” the surface of a mirror, it is what
the physicists call “virtual space”:—and an intangible image.
This virtual space is the primary illusion of all plastic art.
Every element of design, every use of color and semblance of shape,
serves to produce and support and develop the picture-space that exists
for vision alone. Being only visual, this space has no continuity with
the space in which we live; it is limited by the frame, or by
surrounding blanks, or incongruous other things that cut it off. Yet
its limits cannot even be said to divide it from practical space; for a
boundary that divides things always connects them as well, and between
the picture space and any other space there is no connection. The
created virtual space is entirely self-contained and independent.
This is the fundamental reason why everything that is relevant and
artistically valid in a picture must be visual, and everything visual
serves “architec-tonic” purposes. In the virtual space of a picture
there are only images, and if these are to symbolize objects of our
actual world we must have imaginal equivalents for the things that are
normally known by touch, movement or inference. That is why a direct
copy of what we see is not enough. The copy of things seen would need
the same supplementation from non-visual sources that the original
perception demanded. The visual substitutes for the non-visible
ingredients in space experience make the great difference between
photographic rendering and creative rendering; the latter is necessarily
a departure from direct imitation, because it is a construction of
spatial entities out of color alone (perhaps only varying shades of one
color), by all sorts of devices, in order to present at once, with
complete authority, the primary illusion of a perfectly visible and
perfectly intelligible total space.
Virtual space—the primary illusion of pictorial art—is a creation, not a
recreation. There are no natural objects in it, but only semblances,
which characterize it and make it an articulate total shape, free frm
all practical functions, and therefore capable of functioning as a
symbol. There are no degrees of illusoriness or expressiveness among
different art-genders, but only degrees of achievement among individual
works. From the first line of decorative drawing to the works of
Raphael, Leonardo, or Rivera, the same principle of pictorial art is
wholly exemplified: the creation of virtual space, and its organization
by forms (be they lines, or volumes, or intersecting planes, or shadows
and lights) that reflect the patterns of sentience and emotion. The
picture-space, whether conceived in two dimensions or in three,
dissociates itself from the actual space in which the canvas or other
physical bearer of it exists; its function as a symbol makes the objects
in a picture as unlike normal physical objects as a spoken word is
unlike the sounds of footsteps, rustlings, clatter and other noises that
usually accompany and sometimes drown it. The faint little sound of a
speaking voice arrests the ear in midst of the medley of mechanical
sounds and is something altogether different, because its significance
is of a different order; similarly the space in a picture engages our
vision completely because it is significant in itself and not as part of
the surrounding room. Just establish one line in virtual space, and at
once we are in the realm of symbolic forms. The mental shift is as
definite as that which we make from hearing a sound of tapping,
squeaking, or buzzing to hearing speech, when suddenly in midst of the
little noises surrounding us we make out a single word. The whole
character of our hearing is transformed. The medley of physical sound
disappears, the car receives language, perhaps indistinct by reason of
interfering noises, but struggling through them like a living thing.
Exactly the same sort of reorientation is effected for sight by the
creation of any purely visual space. The image, be it a representation
or a mere design, stands before us in its expressiveness: significant
form.
The primary illusion of any art-gender is the basic creation wherein all
its elements exist; and they, in turn, produce and support it. It does
not exist by itself; “primary” does not mean first-established, but
always established where any elements are given at all. There are
numberless ways of making space visible, i.e., virtually
presenting it.
What are the “elements” of a work of art?
Elements are factors in the semblance; and as such they are virtual
themselves, direct components of the total form. In this they differ
from materials, which are actual. Paints are materials, and so are the
colors they have in the tube or on the palette; but the colors in a
picture are elements, determined by their environment. They are warm or
cold, rich or frugal, they advance or recede, enhance or soften or
dominate other colors; they create tensions and distribute weight in a
picture. Colors in a paintbox don’t do such things. They are
materials, and lie side by side in their actual, undialectical
materialism.
Choice of materials may, to be sure, affect the range of available
elements. One can not always do the same things with diverse materials.
The translucency of glass allows the making and use of special color
elements that paint on a wooden ground could never create; therefore
glass painting and wood painting set the artist different problems and
suggest different ideas to be brought to expression. It is sometimes
said that glass and wood have “different feelings.” They permit, and
even command, quite distinct forms, and perhaps equally distinct ranges
of vital import.
All the discernible elements in a picture (that is, the factors analysis
may reveal) are secondary illusions. They support the primary
illusion, which is invariant, while the forms that articulate it may
vary indefinitely. The primary illusion is a substrate of the realm of
virtual forms; it is involved in their occurrence.
The whole problem of the unity and diversity of the arts hinges, I
believe, on this concept of illusion, or created form. The deepest
distinction among them is that of having different primary illusions;
this distinction obtains, for instance, between the visual arts and
music, or between music and literature. Between painting, sculpture and
architecture the distinction is less radical, for it rests only on a
difference among modes of virtual space. With a really potent
principle of analysis one need not defend the unity of art by belittling
or denying the fact that there are several major art-forms, and
insisting that between music and sculpture there is no “real”
difference. The method here used is to push all differences as far as
they will go. There is a definite point where, suddenly, no important
distinctions can be made any more. Everything we can say of anyone art,
on that level, holds for all. There is the unity. Knowing this,
I shall set forth in a subsequent essay what gives the muses their
individuality, and let their family solidarity take care of itself.
(The Hudson Review will publish a second related essay by Mrs.
Langer, “The Primary Illusions and the Great Orders of Art,” in an early
issue.)
1
See Philosophy in a New Key, ch. 8.
2
Cf. Albert Barnes: “The appeal of . . . decorative beauty is probably to
be explained by its satisfaction of our general need of perceiving
freely and agreeably.” (The Art in Painting, p. 29).
3
Adolfo Best-Maugard, A Method for Creative Design.
4
See Philosophy in a New Key, ch. 4.
5
Leonardo, in his Treatise on Painting, advises students to look at
chance forms like cracks in plaster and knots in boards and try to make
figures out of them, i.e., to read shapes of people and things into
them. This, he says, is, very good for the painter’s imagination. It
sounds silly: but was Leonardo silly? Or did he also feel that visual
“reality” is made out of basic organizing forms, as truly as scientific
“reality” is made out of the forms of rational discourse?