This article first
appeared in two parts in The Wanderer, August 13 and 20, 1981. An editorial
note reads: “This and some succeeding articles are based on a lecture
given at the Chesterton Conference on ‘Chesterton and Human Dignity’ held
at Fordham University [New York City] on April 25th.” The author was the
editor of
Christopher Dawson's The Dynamics of World History. (See Harry Elmer Barnes's
review of it.)
For a sketch of Mulloy's life, see
William Doino, Jr.'s essay.
I could
find online no images of Mulloy to post. I would be grateful to the
visitor who could provide a .jpg of Mulloy for use here.
Anthony
Flood
[Updated December
26, 2012]
Chesterton: Christian Response to Nietzsche
John J. Mulloy
It seems appropriate, in
a conference on “Chesterton and Human Dignity,” that one should speak of
Chesterton’s Christian response to Nietzsche. For it was by the dialectic
of challenge and response to anti-Christian ideas that Chesterton
developed some of his most striking testimony to the dignity of the
ordinary human being. If Nietzsche is the philosopher of elitist
aristocracy, Chesterton is the philosopher of Christian democracy. As
Chesterton wrote in Heretics in comment upon the democratic idea of
man:
It is a certain instinctive attitude which feels the things
on which all men agree to be unspeakably important, and all the things in
which they differ (such as mere brains) to be almost unspeakably
unimportant. The nearest approach to it in our ordinary life would be the
promptitude with which we should consider mere humanity in any
circumstances of shock or death. We should say, after a somewhat
disturbing discovery, “There is a dead man under the sofa.” We should not
be likely to say, “There is a dead man of considerable personal refinement
under the sofa” . . . . Nobody would say, “There are the remains of a
clear thinker in your back garden.” Nobody would say, “Unless you hurry
up and stop him, a man with a very fine ear for music will have jumped off
that cliff” (pp. 272-3).
All That Is Sound in Nietzsche
Now Friedrich Nietzsche
had his own idea of human dignity, and there is no doubt that his emphasis
on aristocracy was in considerable part a response to the leveling results
of the growth of capitalism, which submerged the individual in the crowd
and demanded a kind of herdlike response. Nietzsche was also reacting
against the stifling materialism of the 19th century, which reduced
everything to rational calculation, to a simple arithmetic of buying in
the cheapest market and selling in the dearest, and in public policy to an
automatic weighing of the amount of pains and pleasures which would result
from this or that course of action. Quantity, not quality, was the
criterion, and against this Nietzsche wished to reassert the qualitative
elements in life and human society. Chesterton remarks on this element in
Nietzsche in this passage from his book on George Bernard Shaw:
All that was true in his
teaching was simply this: that . . . the mere achievement of dignity,
beauty, or triumph is strictly to be called a good thing . . . it seems to
me that all that is creditable or sound in Nietzsche could be stated in
the derivation of one word, the word ‘valor.’ Valor means valeur;
it means a value; courage is itself a solid good; it is an ultimate
virtue; valor is itself valid. . . . Nietzsche imagined he was rebelling
against ancient morality; as a matter of fact he was only rebelling
against recent morality, against the half-baked impudence of the
utilitarians and the materialists. He though he was rebelling against
Christianity; curiously enough he was rebelling against the special
enemies of Christianity . . . .Historic Christianity has always believed
in the valor of St. Michael riding in front of the Church Militant; and in
an ultimate and absolute pleasure, not indirect or utilitarian, the
intoxication of the spirit, the wine of the Blood of God (pp. 197-8).
Now let us consider
certain basic facts about Nietzsche and his attack on the Christian
worldview. Nietzsche was born in 1844 and became insane in January, 1889,
so he was less than 45 years old when his writing career was over. He
published a number of important works on history, aesthetics, and
philosophy, with special emphasis on Greek culture, in the 1870s, but it
was not until the 1880s that his anti-Christian ideas reached their full
development. His first reference to the death of God is found in The
Joyful Wisdom of 1882, and in Thus Spake Zarathustra, written a
year or so later, he presents his idea of the development of the Superman
as a replacement for God, and his idea of eternal recurrence of the
universe as a replacement for immortality. As the decade progressed,
Nietzsche’s work became more and more stridently anti-Christian,
culminating in The Antichrist of 1888, which is one long diatribe
against Christianity.
His Most Effective Writing
Gilbert K. Chesterton was
born in 1874, a generation or so after Nietzsche, and his first work was
published in 1900. The books in which he especially deals with
Nietzsche’s ideas are Heretics, published in 1905, consisting of a
number of essays on leading writers of his day or of the preceding
generation, and Orthodoxy, appearing in 1908. This is a book of
Christian apologetics which shows how Christianity fulfills the
psychological needs of human nature. Orthodoxy is probably
Chesterton’s most brilliant book, and Heretics is not far behind.
In addition, Chesterton deals briefly with Nietzsche in his book on Shaw
in 1909, and again, a quarter of a century after Orthodoxy, in
St. Thomas Aquinas, published in 1932.
It is my belief that some
of Chesterton’s most effective writing was devoted to refutation of one or
another key idea of Nietzsche. Even in passages where Nietzsche is not
mentioned, it is often his ideas that are Chesterton’s target. The fact
that George Bernard Shaw, with whom Chesterton was so often in friendly
controversy, had taken up ideas of Nietzsche, like that of the Superman
and the worship of the life force, made Chesterton especially aware of
Neitzsche’s worldview.
Joy and Gratitude
What was the nature of
Nietzsche’s attack on Christianity? Nietzsche’s charge against the
Christian Faith is that it is anti-human and anti-life. He reiterates
this charge through a large number of denunciations of particular
Christian positions. Thus, Christianity, by teaching mankind of Almighty
God and His power and wisdom and control of the universe, diminishes the
importance of man, and makes him unable to control his own destiny.
Christianity, by its absolute moral principles, cripples man and prohibits
him from realizing the proper development of his powers. Christianity, by
its negative attitude toward sexuality and creative violence, makes man
psychologically sick and distrustful of life. Christianity, by teaching
of a life beyond the present one where alone true happiness is to be
found, leads man to despise the present life and turn away from it.
Christianity, by teaching of the equality of all men before God, wars
against all noble instincts and all that is heroic in life, and leads to
social leveling and spiritual mediocrity. Christianity, by exalting the
poor and the lowly, inculcates envy and resentment against the upper
classes and all natural nobility. (Notice that this is the opposite of
the charge leveled against Christianity by Karl Marx -- that Christianity
is the opiate of the people and leads them to accept willingly and
submissively the exploitation of an upper class.)
Now over and above the
specific replies which Chesterton makes to Nietzsche concerning
Christianity, it is the whole of Chesterton’s life and work which is a
standing refutation of Nietzsche’s charge that Christianity is anti-human
and anti-life. This great Christian apologist, the “defender of the
Faith,” as Pope Pius XI called him in a telegram to the people of England
upon Chesterton’s death, shows that it is an exultant joy and gratitude
for life which are fundamental to the Christian worldview. Chesterton
also demonstrates that Christianity fulfills the deepest needs of human
nature, in contrast to the disappointment and frustration which result
from a merely naturalistic view of life. In Orthodoxy he pointed
out the basic difference between Christianity and all those philosophies
which confine man to this life alone. He might well have had in mind
Nietzsche’s declaration when speaking of the Superman:
I beseech you, my
brothers, remain faithful to the earth, and do not believe those
who speak to you of otherworldly hopes. Poison-mixers are they, whether
they know it or not. Despisers of life are they, decaying and poisoned
themselves, of whom the earth is weary: so let them go (Thus Spake
Zarathustra, part one, section 3).
Here is the Chesterton passage:
But all the optimism of
the age had been false and disheartening for this reason, that it had
always been trying to prove that we fit in to the world. The Christian
optimism is based on the fact that we do not fit in to the world.
I had tried to be happy by telling myself that man is an animal, like any
other which sought its meat from God. But now I was really happy, for I
had learnt that man is a monstrosity. I had been right in felling all
things as odd, for I myself was at once worse and better than all things.
. . . The modern philosopher had told me again and again that I was in the
right place, and I had still felt depressed, even in acquiescence. But I
had heard that I was in the wrong place, and my soul sang for joy, like a
bird in spring (Orthodoxy, pp. 146-7).
A Chorus of Giants
The vision of reality
which inspires all of Chesterton’s work and thought, which he tells us he
arrived at before he became a Christian, but which he found pre-eminently
expressed in Christianity, is given in the following passage from
Chesterton’s book on Chaucer:
There is at the back of
all our lives an abyss of light, more blinding and unfathomable than any
abyss of darkness; and it is the abyss of actuality, of existence, of the
fact that things truly are, and that we ourselves are incredibly real. it
is the fundamental fact of being, as against not being; . . . (Chaucer)
was the immediate heir of something like what Catholics call the Primitive
Revelation; that glimpse that was given of the world when God saw that it
was good; and so long as the artist gives us glimpses of that, it matters
nothing that they are fragmentary or even trivial. . . . Creation was the
greatest of all revolutions. It was for that, as the ancient poet said,
that the morning stars sang together; and the most modern poets, like the
medieval poets, may descend very far from that height of realization and
stray and stumble and seem distraught; but we shall know them for the sons
of God, when they are still shouting for joy. This is something much more
mystical and absolute than any modern thing that is called optimism; for
it is only rarely that we realize, like a vision of the heavens filled
with a chorus of giants, the primeval duty of praise” (pp. 26-27).
And it is upon this
primeval duty of praise for the wonder of existence that Chesterton’s
critique of Nietzsche is largely based. This, of course, reverses the
charge that Christianity is anti-life and implies that it is really
Nietzsche who is stricken by that disease. Let us consider, for example,
Nietzsche’s conception of the Superman, or the Ubermensch, more
properly translated as the Overman. Here is Nietzsche’s expression of
this idea as given in Thus Spake Zarathustra:
I teach you the overman.
Man is something that shall be overcome. What have you done to overcome
him?
All beings so far have
created something beyond themselves, and do you want to be the ebb of this
great flood and even go back to the beasts rather than overcome man? What
is the ape to man? A laughingstock or a painful embarrassment. and man
shall be just that for the overman: a laughingstock or a painful
embarrassment (Portable Nietzsche, p. 124).
Now Chesterton’s response to this has several different
approaches. One of these is to point out that Nietzsche substitutes
metaphor for moral reality:
So, when he describes his
hero, he does not dare to say ‘the purer man,’ or ‘the happier man,’ or
‘the sadder man,’ for all these are ideas; and ideas are alarming. He
says, ‘the upper man,’ or ‘over man,’ a physical metaphor from acrobats or
alpine climbers. Nietzsche is truly a very timid thinker. (Orthodoxy,
pp. 192-3).
A second approach is to
note that Nietzsche’s calling upon men to labor to produce the Superman
and strive to “create something beyond themselves,” is really unnecessary
if the Superman or Overman is to be the inevitable product of evolution
anyway. And if men are to be the agents for his coming, rather the forces
of nature, then what are the criteria by which they are to know toward
what model they are to direct their efforts?
If the Superman will come
by human selection, what sort of Superman are we to select? If he is
simply to be more just, more brave, or more merciful, then Zarathustra
sinks into a Sunday-school teacher; the only way we can work for it is to
be more just, more brave, or more merciful; sensible advice, but hardly
startling. If he is to be anything else than this, why should we desire
him, or what else are we to desire? These questions have been many time
asked of the Nietzscheites, and none of the Nietzscheites have even
attempted to answer them (George Bernard Shaw, pp. 199-200).
But Chesterton’s more
fundamental answer to Nietzsche and the Superman, and to Nietzsche’s
scorning ordinary human beings as “a laughing stock and a painful
embarrassment,” is to emphasize the wonder and the miracle of what man as
such really is. In a passage in Heretic in which Chesterton is
responding to Shaw’s promotion of this idea of the Superman, Chesterton
writes:
“But the sensation
connected with Mr. Shaw in recent years has been his sudden development of
the religion of the Superman. He who had to all appearance mocked at the
faiths in the forgotten past discovered a new god in the unimaginable
future. He who had laid all the blame on ideals set up the most
impossible of all ideals, the ideal of a new creature. . . .
“For the truth is that
Mr. Shaw has never seen things as they really are. If he had he would
have fallen on his knees before them. . . . It is not seeing things as
they are to think first of a Criareus with a hundred hands, and then call
every man a cripple for having only two. . . . And it is not seeing things
as they are to imagine a demi-god of infinite mental clarity, who may or
may not appear in the latter days of the earth, and then to see all men as
idiots. And this is what Mr. Shaw has always in some degree done. When
we really see men as they are, we do not criticize, but worship; and very
rightly. For a monster with mysterious eyes and miraculous thumbs, with
strange dreams in his skull, and a queer tenderness for this place or that
baby, is truly a wonderful and unnerving matter. It is only the quite
arbitrary and priggish habit of comparison with something else which makes
it possible to be at our ease in front of him. A sentiment of superiority
keeps us cool and practical; the mere facts would make our knees knock
under with religious fear. It is the fact that every instant of conscious
life is an unimaginable prodigy. It is the fact that every face in the
street has the incredible unexpectedness of a fairy-tale” (pp. 63-64).
The Process of Secularization
A second striking
challenge to the Christian worldview is Nietzsche’s proclamation of the
death of God, first set forth in The Joyful Wisdom of 1882. The
death of God implies, of course, that God has never really existed, but is
simply a creation of man’s imagination. So that when man stops believing
in this subjective fantasy, God ceases to exist. But since the
individual’s experience of God as a living reality may differ from that of
Nietzsche or that of the secularized world which Nietzsche saw coming into
being, why should a person accept the view that God is dead? Nietzsche,
although he pretends to be appealing to the insight of the prophetic
individual, is instead appealing to the sociological process of
secularization. Man becomes enslaved to society rather than being able to
transcend it in true individuality.
Here is Nietzsche’s
proclamation of the death of God:
“Whither is God?,” the
Madman cried. “I shall tell you. We have killed him -- you and I. All
of us are his murderers. . . . Is not the greatest of this deed too great
for us? Must not we ourselves become gods simply to seem worthy of it?”
And writing four years
later, in 1886, in an addition to the same volume, Nietzsche wrote:
Indeed, we philosophers
and “free spirits” feel as if a new dawn were shining on us when we
receive the tidings that “the old god is dead”; our heart overflows with
gratitude, amazement, anticipation, expectation. . . . All the daring of
the lover of knowledge is permitted again; the sea, our sea, lies open
again; perhaps there has never yet been such an “open sea.”
A Small World and a Little Heaven
Chesterton’s response to
this, I believe, is to be found in the chapter in Orthodoxy called
“The Maniac.” Although the subject deals with a number of different
matters which involve the rejection of God, it seems that it is especially
a response to Nietzsche’s idea that the death of God opened up the way for
“philosophers and ‘free spirits’“ to become gods themselves. Notice that
in Nietzsche’s account the tidings are brought to mankind by a madman,
although Nietzsche sees the madman as possessed of a perception which
ordinary humanity does not yet have. Chesterton’s chapter, “The Maniac,”
appears to be a definite takeoff from this image. But where Nietzsche
proclaims the superiority of the madman’s insight, Chesterton contrasts
his narrow and concentrated reasoning with the healthy sanity of ordinary
mankind. Nietzsche implies that the madman is the only one who sees
things clearly; Chesterton says that that kind of clarity can only be
achieved by forgetting a large part of what constitutes reality.
It is this ignoring of
reality which leads on to that state of mind in which the individual
thinks he has become God and has created everything else. Chesterton says
there is no reasoning with such a position, that the only hope is to jar
it out of the insane groove in which it has become fixed. The response
which Chesterton gives to the madman applies also to Nietzsche and his
idea that he and a few other free spirits -- Nietzsche later confessed
that the others never really measured up to his own standard -- will
“become gods” now that God is dead. Here is Chesterton’s reply to the
madman:
If we said what we felt,
we should say, “So you are the Creator and Redeemer of the world: but what
a small world it must be! What a little Heaven you must inhabit, with
angels no bigger than butterflies! How sad it must be to be God; and an
inadequate God! Is there really no life fuller and no love more marvelous
than yours; and is it really in your small and painful pity that all flesh
must put its faith? How much happier you would be, how much more of you
there would be, if the hammer of a higher God could smash your small
cosmos, scattering the stars like spangles, and leave you in the open,
free like other men to look up as well as down!”
Notice the direct
contrast between Nietzsche’s seeing the death of God as leading men to an
open sea, a sea that has never been so open before, and Chesterton’s
portraying the man who thinks himself God as imprisoned within a very
narrow universe. In fact, later on Chesterton compares this narrowing of
reality to a madman’s cell:
The starts will be only
dots in the blackness of his own brain; his mother’s face will be only a
sketch from his own insane pencil on the walls of his cell. But over his
cell shall be written, with dreadful truth, “He believes in himself” (pp.
45-46)
Isolated and Disembodied
Another challenge which
Nietzsche flings at Christianity is made through comparative religion. As
an element of this strategy, Nietzsche attacks Christianity from the
vantage point of the Oriental world religions. Thus he has some good
words to say for the Hindu Laws of Manu, which set forth the basis of the
caste system. But his preferred adversary to Christianity among the
religions of the world is Buddhism. Although Nietzsche is opposed to all
religions that involve asceticism and that do not find their center of
gravity in the worship of the forces of natural vitality, he manages to
develop quite a defense of Buddhism when comparing it to Christianity.
Most of all he likes the fact that Buddhism rejects the idea of a personal
God and thus makes its efforts center on man’s own ability to escape from
pain and sorrow in life.
One of the elements of
Chesterton’s response to Nietzsche in this matter is to suggest that the
founders of the Oriental world religions were theorists and speculators
who had lost their roots in the life of the common people, and were
isolated and disembodied in the kind of religious systems they produced.
As a result, they could disregard the conditions of reality, both physical
and religious, when they were devising their explanations of the meaning
of life and the universe. This is a counterattack on Nietzsche by
outflanking him. For Nietzsche is always claiming for himself and those
ideas he favors -- and this includes Buddhism -- the fact of their facing
up to reality, while Christianity he denounced as escapist and turning
away from life. No, says Chesterton, when one looks at the history of the
Oriental world religions, with their contradiction of the fundamental
principles that govern all existence, one finds men who have lost touch
with reality. The Oriental world religions have no sense of the
restraints imposed upon thought by really existing things, and thus are
free to indulge themselves in whatever ideas happen to appeal to them.
Humanity and
Liberty and
Love
In Orthodoxy
Chesterton compares Christianity with Buddhism to show that Christianity
is on the side of life and love, while Buddhism is on the side of
withdrawal from life and concentration on the world within. Chesterton
writes:
Students of popular
science, like Mr. Blatchford, are always insisting that Christianity and
Buddhism are very much alike, especially Buddhism. This is generally
believed, and I believed it myself until I read a book giving the reasons
for it. The reasons were of two kinds: resemblances that meant nothing
because they are common to all humanity, and resemblances which were not
resemblances at all.
After examining a number of both kinds of these alleged
resemblances, he concludes:
I do not think that there
are two institutions in the universe which contradict each other as flatly
as Buddhism and Christianity.
And he sees this illustrated by the religious art of the
two religions, in the contrast, for example, between a Christian saint in
a Gothic cathedral and a Buddhist saint in a Chinese temple. He observes:
The Buddhist saint has a
sleek and harmonious body, but his eyes are heavy and sealed with sleep.
The medieval saint’s body is wasted to its crazy bones, but his eyes are
frightfully alive.
He finds the reason for
this contrast in the Christian emphasis on the importance of personality
and the personal relationship between God and man. Consequently:
It is just here that
Buddhism is on the side of modern pantheism and immanence. And it is just
here that Christianity is on the side of humanity and liberty and love.
Love desires personality; therefore love desires division. It is the
instinct of Christianity to be glad that God has broken the universe into
little pieces, because they are living pieces. It is her instinct to say
‘little children, love one another,’ rather than to tell one large person
to love himself. This is the intellectual abyss between Buddhism and
Christianity; that for the Buddhist or Theosophist personality is the fall
of men, for the Christianity it is the purpose of God, the whole point of
His cosmic idea . . . . We come back to the same tireless note touching
the nature of Christianity; all modern philosophies are chains which
connect and fetter; Christianity is a sword which separates and sets
free. No other philosophy makes God actually rejoice in the separation of
the universe into living souls (Orthodoxy, pp. 240-3, 245-6).
Thus Chesterton throws
back into the teeth of Nietzsche the latter’s oft-repeated charge that
Christianity is opposed to life and reality. It is the egoism of
Nietzsche which prevents him from seeing the psychological reality of love
which is at the heart of Christianity, and which is also at the heart of
humanity in its deepest and truest meaning.
Posted March 1,
2008