From Polity, Vol. XXII, No. 3, Spring 1990, 545-556.
Review-essay on Robert Proctor, Racial Hygiene: Medicine Under
the Nazis.
Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1988; Benno Müller-Hill,
Murderous Science: Elimination by Scientific Selection of Jews,
Gypsies, and Others,
Germany:
1933-1945.
Translated by George R. Fraser.
Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1988; and Robert Jay Lifton, The Nazi Doctors:
Medical Killing and the Psychology of Genocide.
New York:
Basic Books, Inc., 1986.
Nazi
Science
Hugh Murray
During World War I, Germans proudly wore on their belt
buckles the slogan, Gott mit uns; after World War II liberals
proudly proclaim, “science is in our side.” The first was clearly wishful
thinking; what about the second? Everyone recognizes that after a major
religious or ideological war, history is written by the victors. We fail
to recognize that science, too, may be written, and rewritten, by the
victors. These three books raise important questions about the
relationship of politics, science, and ethics both in Nazi
Germany then and in
liberal America today.
Who has not heard of the Dreyfus case, that
turn-of-the-century example of French anti-Semitism? The Jewish officer
was sentenced for treason to Devil’s Island, but to his defense came Emile
Zola, whose I, Accuse, along with protests by others, eventually
resulted in the acquittal of Capt. Dreyfus and the exposure of some of his
Christian colleagues. Zola has ever been praised amid the Pantheon of the
Left. Yet, Zola, in his desire to be scientific and in his success in
establishing the “naturalistic” novel, stressed the importance of
heredity. Zola declared, “I am a positivist, an evolutionist, a
materialist; my system is heredity.”1
He constructed a family tree for his 20-volume series, Les
Rougon Macquart. About the same time in the
United States there
were numerous scientific studies, some published by the Eugenic Society,
concerning generations of family degeneracy. Both Presidents Theodore
Roosevelt and Woodrow Wilson, progressive Republican and progressive
Democrat, were influenced by such notions.
But the leader in the sciences of heredity, genetics, and
racial hygiene, as in so many other fields at that time, was
Germany. What would
happen when these scientists, aided by the medical and anthropological
professions, would win powerful political allies and achieve power? That
is the theme of these three books, whose coverage is different yet
complementary. The most recent work is by Robert Proctor, who presents a
general overview of Nazi medicine with revealing illustrations, including
fascinating chapters on organic medicine in the Third Reich and the
opposition to the Nazis by the Association of Socialist Physicians.
Unlike Raul Hilberg,2
Proctor proposes a different logic, one that begins with studies of
heredity, genetic disease, and racial hygiene, yet culminates with doctors
selecting who would be gassed at
Auschwitz.
Benno Müller-Hill’s book is a short, personalized work with a helpful
chronology and documentary-type interviews he conducted with some of the
murderous scientists, their children, and their assistants. Robert Jay
Lifton’s book is the lengthiest and also based, in part, on interviews,
but he dilutes his material so it will fit the author’s narrow
preconceptions.
Proctor traces the development of medicine from the
turn-of-the-century racism that dominated science in every country, to the
growth of anthropology, race hygiene, and eugenics. All stressed racial
differences; all, the role of heredity in disease, crime, intelligence,
alcoholism, divorce, etc. After 1900, a debate ensued between the
followers of Lamarck and Mendel. The political Left, anxious to stress the
role of environment and education, generally favored Lamarck’s view of
acquired characteristics; the Right embraced Mendelian genetics with such
conclusions as these from a Nazi handbook: “Environmental influences have
never been known to bring about the formation of a new race. That is one
more reason for the belief that a Jew remains a Jew, in
Germany or any other
country. He can never change his race, even by centuries of residence
among another people” (pp. 37-38). Even before the Nazis achieved power,
“by 1932 . . . racial hygiene had become scientific orthodoxy in the
German medical community” (p. 38). Prof. Eugen Fischer, Director of the
prestigious Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Anthropology, Heredity Science,
and Eugenics from its inception in 1927, was chosen as Rektor of
the University of Berlin in 1933. In his inaugural address Dr. Fischer
declared, “What Darwin was not able to do, genetics has achieved. It has
destroyed the theory of the equality of man” (p. 345). As early as 1930
the Nazis sloganized, “National Socialism [is] the political expression of
our biological knowledge” (p. 28). Proctor adds, “One might even say that
National Socialism was itself progressive—if we mean by this that
application of science to social problems (in a particular ‘biologistic’
manner) was an important element in Nazi ideology.” Mendelian genetics was
hailed by the Nazis as proof that race was the key to history, not
environment, not class. Indeed, to prevent Mendelian genetics from
undermining egalitarian ideals in the
Soviet Union,
Stalin had the scientific opponents of Lamarck and Lysenko imprisoned or
murdered. But the Nazis were unlike the Communists; the Nazis encouraged
science and were supported by many scientists. In 1932, for example, the
largest political group of physicians in Germany was the Nazi doctors
organization. After 1933, they sought to expel their competitors from the
profession, Jews, Communists, and Socialists. As 13 percent of Germany’s
doctors nationally, and some 60 percent of those in
Berlin
were Jewish, the expulsion process took some time.
In 1933, Dr. Gerhard Wagner, the Nazi who became the leader
of the . entire German medical profession months after Hitler became
Kanzler, contrasted the National Socialist medical ideal with that of
its predecessors-now there would be an emphasis on health leadership
rather than health care, preventative rather than curative medicine,
racial rather than individual hygiene. And health leadership implied
distinguishing between valuable life and life “not worth living” (p. 73).
Most German doctors endorsed Dr. Wagner’s program and during the Hitler
regime “a higher proportion of
Germany’s top
university officers were held by medical doctors than at any time before
or since” (p. 94). In fact, as Proctor notes, “there is little evidence
that physicians ever refused to participate in Nazi programs. . . .
Physicians were never ordered to participate in these experiments; those
who participated did so because they were given the opportunity and
volunteered” (p. 220).
In July 1933, the Nazis enacted the Law for the Prevention
of Genetically Diseased Offspring. To prevent degeneration, about 400,000
Germans were sterilized between 1933 and 1939—feeble-minded, schizoid,
epileptic, alcoholic, manic-depressive, blind, deaf, and malformed,
overwhelmingly Aryan Germans (p. 108). Doctors directed this program,
which was so thorough that occasionally Nazis like Dr. Wagner and Heinrich
Himmler felt compelled to restrain the doctors, who, for example, sought
to sterilize an alcoholic in his seventies (pp. 114-15). Though Jews were
not particular victims of this program, blacks were. Hitler ordered the
sterilization of the 500 children of black French occupation forces in the
Rhine, usually referred to in the scientific literature as the “Rhineland
bastards” (p. 112).
The Nazis sought to restore family values. Women working
outside the home, they believed, had caused many of
Germany’s problems.
Proctor fails to mention the famous Nazi slogan for women, Kinder,
Kiiche, Kirche (children, kitchen, church), but he nevertheless
describes this ideal. In 1933, millions of German women were employed.
If women were to remain at home, men could take their jobs. And at home,
women could bear children, increase the low German birthrate, and care for
their larger families. The Nazi leadership presented medals to women with
many children, and government funds subsidized large families. Abortion
was judged “race treason,” and penalties for it were both increased and
strictly enforced. The liberal notion that one should control one’s body
was denounced as contrary to race hygiene. Dr. Wagner “declared the
nation’s stock of ovaries a national resource and property of the German
state” (p. 125). As a consequence of these Nazi pro-family policies, the
birthrate rose so that by 1938 it equalled that of
England
and France combined. Not all of the pro-family policies were carrots.
According to the Nuremberg laws of 1935 an unmarried German woman, like
Jews, lost her citizenship. And while Proctor is extremely negligent on
the Nuremberg
laws directed against homosexuals, he does relate that “in 1938 all public
officials (including professors) were required to marry or else resign. .
. . After 1938 couples married for five years who had not yet raised a
family incurred a penalty tax” (p. 121). These pro-family policies of the
Nazis are neglected in most histories.
In the fall of 1935, Proctor relates, Hitler signed a
series of anti-Jewish
Nuremberg laws, which
defined Jews racially and forbade them to marry non-Jews. The German
medical journals applauded these “health measures.” And though fewer Jews
were allowed to practice medicine, nevertheless, the number of doctors in
Germany rose, in part due to an increase in women doctors, who, despite
Nazi ideology, returned to the workplace in increasing numbers as Nazi
prosperity supplanted the depression. Proctor notes, “Medicine prospered
under the Nazis, as Germans under Nazi guidance became increasingly
obsessed with marital, racial, and physical fitness” (p. 141).
While much of the story of anti-Semitism has been told
before, Proctor is good at relating how the ever more restrictive laws
reduced the percentage of Jewish doctors in
Germany from 13 percent
in 1933 to the point where no Jewish doctor was permitted to service a
non-Jew by 1938. What Proctor adds is the hardships inflicted on Jewish
doctors in nations surrounding Germany, like the anti-Jewish policies in
Austria
instituted by the Roman Catholic Doctors’ Association in 1934. There were
also laws enacted against Jewish doctors or refugee Jewish doctors in
Italy, Bulgaria, Hungary, France, Mexico, and elsewhere.
Shortly before outbreak of war in 1939 the Nazis planned to
progress from sterilization to euthanasia, beginning with children under 5
and newborns with Mongolism, deafness, blindness, etc. Doctors selected
the unfit to be killed. Some doctors were squeamish and simply allowed
their patients to starve to death. The euthanasia program was quickly
applied to mental patients, who, in hospitals, were told to disrobe for
showers, where they were gassed. In August 1941, Hitler ordered an end to
this general policy, after some 70,000 had been killed. Euthanasia would
continue on a more individual hospital basis thereafter, continuing even
during the American occupation. All this killing was conducted exclusively
by medical personnel, and there were even little parties to celebrate the
one thousandth patient. A month after Hitler launched his attack on the
Soviets, he ordered transfer of personnel and technical facilities already
developed to the East, to be used against Jews, Gypsies, and others. The
Jews were judged a diseased race. Dr. Wagner observed “that Jews showed a
higher rate of sexual deficiency, expressed, in the blurring of secondary
sexual characteristics” (p. 195). He stressed “not only the higher
incidence of homosexuality among the Jews but also the prominence of
female Jews in ‘masculine pursuits’ such as revolutionary political
activism” (p. 196). Walled into ghettoes in
Poland after the German
victory, Jews began to die of disease and starvation. Proctor regards
that the German commissioner of the
Warsaw
ghetto blocked shipments of food and medical supplies to the city. Proctor
fails to record that during the wave of typhus in the ghetto, the Germans
removed medicine-from ghetto clinics. Writes Proctor, “Science thus
conspired in the solution to the Jewish question: . . . To be Jewish was
to be both sick and criminal; Nazi medical science and policy united to
help ‘solve’ this problem” (pp. 204-05). Finally, at the Wannsee
conference of early 1942, the Nazis decided on the “final solution” of the
“Jewish problem.” A medical doctor was among those in attendance.
Proctor is weakest in his discussion of Hitler’s war
against homosexuals. He omits mention of Dr. Magnus Hirschfeld and his
famous institute for the study of sex. Proctor and, to a lesser degree,
Lifton, rely on Frank Rector’s flawed account on homosexuals and Nazis,
and neither seems to have consulted the important work by Richard Plant.
Proctor is wrong when he asserts that the killing of Roehm during the
Night of Long Knives bloodbath “marked only the first phase of the Nazi
persecution of homosexuals” (p. 214). Hitler’s movement was, after all,
pro-family. Less than a month after his appointment as Kanzler, Hitler had
homosexuals’ bars closed, their publications banned as pornography, their
organizations proscribed, and in May 1933, the irreplaceable library of
Hirschfeld’s Institute of Sexual Science burned.3
In time, thousands of homosexuals would be incarcerated, castrated, and
killed by the Nazis.
And if Proctor is deficient in discussing homosexuals,
Müller-Hill is worse. Müller-Hill’s book was originally printed in
Germany in 1984, and the title indicates how the author conceives Nazi
policy. Homosexuals fell into Müller-Hill’s category of “others.” Indeed,
as he concedes in a footnote Müller-Hill had virtually completed his book
before he realized that homosexuals had been singled out for persecution
by the Nazis! Though Lifton mentions homosexuals, Gypsies, Blacks,
alcoholics, and others killed by Nazis, his main focus is on the murdering
of Jews.
In the name of racial hygiene thousands of Gypsies were
also rounded up and sent to extermination camps. The Nazis discussed
killing thousands of tubercular patients. They conducted medical
experiments in concentration camps using inmates as guinea pigs. Lifton
describes in dreadful detail how many experiments were concerned with
developing means of mass sterilization, but some, Proctor emphasizes, were
made to contribute directly to the Nazi war effort—to discover how much
salt water a pilot might drink before dying, or how long one could survive
in icy waters, or in low pressure. Scientists conducted these
experiments, presented papers to other scientists about them, and
sometimes published on them. Proctor adds some significant sentences:
“It is curious that, immediately after the war, people were eager to argue
that Nazi medical experiments ‘were not even good science.’ . . .
‘insufficient and unscientific,’ ‘a ghastly failure, as well as a hideous
crime.’ . . . And yet the cruelty of an experiment is not lessened by its
scientific value” (p. 220). Proctor might have revised his sentence to,
“the scientific value of an experiment is not lessened by its cruelty.”
Proctor includes a fascinating chapter on organic medicine
under the Nazis. Hitler was a vegetarian and neither smoked nor drank
alcohol. The Nazis opposed cruelty to animals, denouncing kosher
slaughter practices. The Nazis discouraged eating of meat, encouraged
more fruits and vegetables. They promoted whole-grain bread and
discouraged smoking, alcohol, asbestos, DOT, and X-rays. Natural healers
competed with medical doctors in
Germany,
both before and after Hitler. The Nazis promoted midwivery and, in 1939,
enacted a law that midwives had to assist all German births. However,
orthodox medicine and science alone were permitted to determine questions
of racial hygiene, i.e., who was a Jew, a homosexual, a Gypsy, an
epileptic, who would be sterilized, castrated, who would live or die. But
interest in natural medicine was widespread and the SS organized farms for
cultivating herbs at Auschwitz and other camps.
In his revealing chapter on medical resistance to the
Nazis, Proctor stresses the role of the popular-front Association of
Socialist Physicians (VSA). Before 1932 the VSA had deemed the Nazi views
on race too absurd to evoke a response. In 1932, it began to answer. The
socialists also had developed an alternative view of medicine, stressing
the whole man, the right to abortion, social medicine, factory safety and
health, and inexpensive mobile clinics. But by January 1933, even before
Hitler became Kanzler, only 1,500 doctors were members of the VSA,
while 3,000 doctors had already enrolled in the Nazi medical organization.
After Hitler came to power, the VSA was outlawed, its
members silenced, arrested, or exiled. Reconstituted by exiles in
Prague as the
International Association of Socialist Physicians, the group published
attacks on the Nazi medical policies and urged a boycott of German
pharmaceuticals. The IASP also aided Republican forces during the Spanish
Civil War. But as the Reich absorbed
Austria,
the Sudetenland, and finally Prague itself, the anti-Nazi physicians fled
and their organization disintegrated.
The last two chapters are among the most important in
Proctor’s powerful book. One challenges the orthodox liberal
interpretation of Nazi science. For decades one has read and heard how
irrational the Nazis were, and some of this view may be traced to “the
stereotype of Nazi science as mystical or irrational [that] may have grown
in part from reports to this effect issued by émigré physicians attempting
to discredit Nazi science and medicine” (p. 265). Proctor adds that the
émigrés “exaggerated” the hostility of the Nazis to scientific medicine
(p. 265).
And though Proctor records the forced emigration, and murder, of leading
scientists and doctors from Nazi
Europe, he also
concludes that it is misleading to label National Socialism as
anti-intellectual.
“Academics in every field gave support to the Nazi regime.
The Nazis, in return, provided support for various forms of intellectual
endeavor. . . . Certain fields, such as psychology, anthropology, and
human genetics, actually expanded under the Nazis. . . . [The Reich
provided] substantial support for research in fields such as criminal
biology, genetic pathology, and comparative physical anthropology. . . .
More than a dozen new medical journals were founded in the Nazi period. .
. . The Nazis expanded
Germany’s public health
facilities and state health offices” (p. 283).
Elsewhere he notes the expansion of day care centers for
working women, and he should have also included a chapter on the expansion
of sport and sports’ medicine.
Proctor records a view disturbing to liberals, “Nazi racial
theory and practice were not the product of a tiny band of marginal and
psychotic individuals. Nazi racial hygienists were among the top
professionals in their fields. . . . Racial hygienists like Lenz, Fischer,
and Verschuer were not men whose scientific or medical credentials could
be questioned” (p. 284). “Racial science was ‘normal science’ in the sense
that Thomas Kuhn has given the expression. . .” (p. 285). And “Nazi
medical philosophers defended their revolution as one in accord with the
latest results of science” (p. 293). Hitler himself had declared that
National Socialism was “no mystical doctrine, but rather a realistic
doctrine of a strictly scientific nature” (p. 294). Proctor summarizes
his attack on the liberal consensus, “One could well argue that the Nazis
were not, properly speaking, abusing the results of science but
rather were merely putting into practice what doctors and scientists had
themselves already initiated. Nazi racial science in this sense was not
an abuse of eugenics but rather an attempt to bring to practical fruition
trends already implicit in the structure of this branch of science” (p.
296). And “It is probably as fair to say that Nazi racial policy emerged
from within the scientific community as to say it was imposed
upon the scientific community” (p. 297).
Proctor’s last chapter, the Epilogue on what happened after
World War II, and the restoration of some of the Nazi scientists to
professorships, power, and prestige is short, but the topic is better
covered in Müller-Hill’s volume. The main fault of Proctor’s final chapter
is his near omission of post-war exposes, trials, and attitudes toward the
Nazi scientists in the Soviet zone and later
East Germany.
Müller-Hill is less
interested in the broad area of Nazi medicine and concentrates on narrow
disciplines. The translator’s Preface states that the book is unique in
examining
the history of
science which involved some of the leading figures in the German
academic establishment, especially in the fields of anthropology
(including human genetics) and psychiatry. These individuals aided and
abetted the racial policy of the Nazi state. They provided the
intellectual and scientific basis for assumptions of racial and genetic
inferiority (and, . . . superiority) and they helped to build up the
legal infrastructure of the mechanisms which were put into place to give
expression to those ideas in the form of mass murder, genocide, and
sterilization. This book attempts to trace the action of many of these
persons, which included actual participation in mass murder in the guise
of scientific and medical experimentation, and to provide some
understanding of the motivation of these individuals. (p. ix)
Unfortunately, this excerpt provides an example of the
translator’s style, one that is compounded by repetition throughout the
book. And the work is weakened by a poor index.
But there are advantages to Müller-Hill: (1) it is short;
(2) there is a chronology of the policies of murder; (3) a third of the
book consists of interviews conducted by the author with some of the old
scientists, their children, or their assistants. These interviews have the
feel of a documentary film. Furthermore, Müller-Hill’s text is only 70
pages, yet he occasionally includes more or different tales than does
Proctor, as, for example, regarding Max Planck or the Rockefeller
Foundation support for German scientific institutes.
Müller-Hill, unlike Proctor, still very much upholds the
liberal view of Nazi science. He sees the Nazi era as “an aberration in
the history of science” (p. ix), and the Nazi scientists “showed
themselves traitors to their science” (p. 101). “If injustice becomes
monstrous, reason and science perish together. . .” (p. 82). Similarly
Robert Lifton’s book on Nazi medicine is also distorted by a
“how-could-they?” attitude. At one point, however, Müller-Hill’s does
break out of the liberal straightjacket: “Science espouses objectivity and
spurns value judgements. But pure objectivity leads to regarding
everything as being feasible. The killing of mental patients? . . . why
not?” (p. 89). Yet overall, Müller-Hill, despite his title, does not view
science as murderous, except in the wildly aberrant Nazi form. By
contrast, Proctor detects a logic in science that led from
Darwin to Mendel to
Auschwitz.
The Lifton book, though published only in 1986, has been
greatly superseded because of the power of Proctor’s logic. In his
500-page text, Lifton discloses enormous amounts of vivid material, but he
shrinks it, attempting to force facts and interviews into his psychiatric
categories. Worse, Lifton dismisses the chief assumptions of the Nazi
physicians whom he seeks to describe.
Lifton, a psychiatrist, tries to camouflage his personal
value judgements as scientific judgements, labeling what he does not like
as “pseudo.” Thus, the Nazis engaged in “pseudo-speciation,” indulged in
“pseudo-ethics,” and enshrined “pseudo-science.” Lifton assures readers
that eugenics had no scientific standing, was a mystic science for
half-educated men based on “false racial theories” (p. 432).
If one denies the scientific assumptions of the Nazi
doctors, then of course they become monsters, Faustian figures embracing
or choosing evil, in a new “diabolical” and “demonic” venture. They were
so evil they had to “double,” like Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde, killing at
Auschwitz, while
healing in the pre-Hitler and post-Hitler eras, and even to a small extent
at Auschwitz, itself.
Lifton stresses how these Nazi doctors violated their
Hippocratic Oath to help patients so that they could uphold their Hitler
Oath to kill patients and non-patients. Lifton’s picture of the fit Dr.
Pfannmüller proudly displaying to visitors an infant that he held in his
hands, whom he was in the process of starving to death, is only one of his
many gruesome portraits.
But Lifton distorts his material. He simply refuses to
acknowledge that racial science was considered “science” at that time, and
not only in Nazi
Europe. The Nazis thought they were purifying
Europe and protecting
Aryans from pollution through the process of exterminating Jews,
imbeciles, epileptics, etc. When SS Doctor Klein was asked how he could
kill Jews after taking the Hippocratic Oath, he implied that Hippocrates
would do the same. Klein contended he was removing Jews, a gangrenous
appendix, from the body of Europe. Klein could have noted that if not
Hippocrates, then most ancient Greek doctors practiced infanticide to
remove the deformed from Greece, and that they were supported in doing so
by such philosophers as Plato.
What Proctor reveals is that the Germans were engaged in
“science,” not “pseudo-science.” By stressing racial and genetic
differences, they sought to expand Aryan and diminish non-Aryan influence
and population. Auschwitz was not a necessary outcome of such scientific
principles applied by an efficient and powerful nation, but it was a
possible outcome.
Nazi doctors were shocked upon arriving at Auschwitz, but
most were “selecting” thousands for the gas chambers within a month.
Lifton labels this “doubling,” like Mr. Hyde. But the Nazis saw the
process differently. They viewed
Auschwitz
as a “sewerage project,” a “dog pound,” the “anus mundi,” and they saw
themselves as heroic, medicalized soldiers engaged in an unpleasant task.
Some sincerely believed that he who loves humanity hates Jews. But it was
not necessary to believe that.
It is possible that Dr. Mengele did not view Jews as
inferior to Aryans, but merely as different, competitors. Germany,
degraded in the 1920s and early 1930s, seemed to rise as Jewish influence
diminished under Hitler. Many began to believe the slogan on Der
Stürmer, “The Jews are our [Germany’s]
misfortune.” At Auschwitz Mengele was simply protecting his Vaterland
by eliminating competition. And this is what Konrad Lorenz was
writing about in 1940 in Nazi Germany, and what he and Desmond Morris
discussed, in subdued tones, in best-selling books in the West after World
War II. They stress the inherent nature of aggression, combat, and war.
“Highly important to the German-Nazi ethos was the claim of
logic, rationality, and science” (p. 439). From the rational science of
the 1930s a logic ran to the death camps. This Lifton admits himself,
between lines cluttered with denials. Finally, when Lifton does concede
that the Nazis were following a rational policy, he seeks to minimize his
concession. Was it not rational? No! Lifton claims the Nazis may have
been logical, but logic can be paranoid. Of course, Lifton never reveals
which logic is paranoid and which not. Apparently, Lifton labels logic an
exercise in paranoia when he dislikes its conclusions. And what is
Lifton’s solution? The Nazi doctors could avoid the evil of doubling by
having integrity. Lifton is absurd. Hitler had integrity. Dr. Mengele had
integrity, was even admired for his integrity by his fellow SS doctors.
“Integrity,” “doubling,” labeling “pseudo” and “paranoid” is no way to
analyze Nazi medicine.
Lifton denies that eugenics, racial hygiene, certain forms
of physical anthropology, heredity, and criminology were “science.” There
are many, however, who would question if Dr. Lifton’s brand of psychiatry
is a “science.” Certainly, in the 1930s and 1940s, the former had more
“scientific” credentials than the latter. Indeed, is it not the defeat of
the Nazis that altered the evaluations of these “sciences”?
The major problem with Lifton’s book is that he assumes
liberal ethics and liberal science to be the only ethics, the only
science. He assumes that science is liberal, ethics is liberal. But
Lorenz once assumed that science was in accord with Nazi principles, and
that any ethics derived from science also would be in accord with Nazi
principles. I ask, is science liberal? Nazi? Or anything else? And
equally important should ethics be derived from science? Science may help
to delineate the line between an animal and a human, a foetus and a child,
a Jew and a German, an epileptic and a non-epileptic, etc., but science
cannot tell us to draw a line between those groups, or which lines should
be significant. Certainly, science cannot tell us which lines will divide
those who should live and who should die. These decisions must be based on
ethical views, some of which may be in accord with science, some neutral
toward science, and some counter to science.
Two of the books under consideration are reluctant to admit
that the Nazis were scientific. Proctor is courageous in revealing the
scientific ideal of Nazism. However, none of the three books is willing to
stress that there may be conflicts between the ethical and the scientific.
And if there are conflicts, where should one stand? Liberals have
glorified Galileo for remaining loyal to science and challenging the
church. Liberals have laughed at William Jennings Bryan who quoted the
Bible and denied evolution during the Scopes trial in Tennessee. But what
if the latest scientific findings were to conflict with certain liberal
tenets? Should liberals remain true to liberalism, or to science?
Lifton and many liberals seek to evade the problem by
calling Nazi science “pseudo-science.” But since all science is incomplete
and subject to altered interpretations in the future, then all science
might be labeled “pseudo.” Proctor reveals that the Nazis were leaders in
certain fields of “science.”
There is a major point fully developed by none of these,
books. Proctor writes regarding political philosophies of science. “In the
liberal view, predominant in twentieth-century liberal democracies,
science is political only in its applications. Science in this view is
(ideally) neutral or value free, and becomes ‘tainted’ when politics
directs the course of intellectual inquiry” (pp. 289-90). How, then, can
Proctor account for the fact that it is often liberals who will prevent
scientific research for political reasons? Dr. Wolfgang Abel in the 1930s
had been involved in identifying for sterilization the “Rhineland
bastards,” and became Professor of Anthropology and Race Biology at the
University of Berlin, 1943-45. When asked a few years ago by Professor of
Genetics Müller-Hill, “What significance did anthropology and human
genetics have for Nazi policies?” Abel replied, “ ‘None at all,’ . . .
[Prof. Eugen] Fischer often said, ‘Politics destroys science for us.’ “
But then Abel took the offensive against his younger inquisitor, “In
short, you say that the inheritance of mental traits cannot be proved. . .
. You use your argument as a protective shield, but what will you do if
the inheritance of mental traits is demonstrated?” (p. 138). Is this not a
forbidden area of research in the East? And in the West, at least since
WWII?
It is comforting, flattering, to think of the West as
scientific, the Nazis as irrational, mystical, murderous. But to what
extent was their murderous policy the outcome of scientific inquiry? In
the Soviet Union under Stalin, when Mendelian genetics seemed to imply the
inequality of man, the Mendelians were eliminated or killed, the
Lamarckian thesis imposed through the domination of Lysenko. In Stalin’s
empire the equality of man could not be questioned, even by scientists
using scientific methods. Can it now be questioned any more effectively
in the West, even by scientists using scientific methods? And should it be
questioned? These are some of the questions that flow from the books under
discussion. The questions flow from, but are too little part of these
otherwise interesting books.
Notes
1 Bettina L. Knapp, Emile Zola (New York: Frederick Ungar
Publishing Co., 1980), p.37.
2 In Raul Hilberg, Destruction of the European Jews (New York:
Harper and Row, 1961).
3 See Richard Plant, The Pink Triangle: The Nazi War Against
Homosexuals (New York: A New Republic Book, Henry Holt and Co., 1986),
pp. 209-210.