Unabashedly theoretic, Anthony de Jasay’s analysis of human interaction
does not seek to create a technocratic framework within which
rulers-managers (or their academic surrogates) can find handles for
steering and manipulating the actions of other people towards some
preferred optimal state of society. There is no trace in his work of
the presumption that rulers and managers are, or can be, related to
society in the same way that an engineer is related to a piece of
machinery or an experimental biologist to the animals in his laboratory.
Jasay’s bottom line is that rulers and managers are part of the real
world of interacting agents that the theorist needs to analyse and
understand. His arguments against the supposed necessity or
desirability of the state derive much of their force from his refusal to
compromise on that proposition.
If Jasay’s analysis of the problems of conflict and order among humans
has not received the recognition that it deserves, the reason may be
that the entire classical liberal tradition, to which it so clearly
belongs, has been sidelined in contemporary debates and argu-mentation.
To understand the pertinence of his argu-ments, one has to grasp the
relevance of that tradition. That is no easy task for those—most of
us—who have been educated by the state to look at the world as if it
were inherently chaotic and in need of a firm government to protect it
from self-destruction. Many liberals today construe liberalism as a
scheme of organisation that can and must be imposed politically on
society by an enlightened government, as if the arguments by which some
intellectuals convince themselves of the superiority of the scheme would
make every person oblivious to the opportunities offered by the mode of
imposition itself. However, classical liberalism was not about imposing
freedom but about safeguarding it. Its premise was that the human world
has a natural law or natural order2 of its own, and that
respecting personal freedom is crucial to that order. Consequently, the
role of government, if it is to be lawful, must be restrained to
maintaining respect for the natural law of the human world. Many
authors in the classical liberal tradition accordingly devoted their
intellectual efforts to specifying “constitutional restraints” that
would keep the state within the bounds of law.
2 On the interpretation
of “law” as order, see Frank van Dun,
“The Lawful and the Legal,” Journal
des econo-mistes et des etudes humaines, 6/4 (1996): 555-79.
Although Jasay eschews any notion of natural law that cannot be
explicated in terms of his rational choice approach, he is fully
committed to the view that there is indeed a natural order of the human
world and that it will be attained most fully under conditions of lawful
anarchy, that is to say in a regime of full freedom and unrestricted
self-defence. Thus, he pushes the classical liberal argu-ment to a
radical conclusion: assuming that “rational choice” covers political man
as well as economic and indeed every other sort of man, there is no
reason to expect that it is possible to confine the government of a
state to its legitimate function. In a nutshell: granting the state the
monopoly power to maintain the law is to grant it the power to abuse the
law and, as Jasay famously asked, “What would you do if you were
the state?”3 What would you do if you had the power to abuse
the law without having to fear the one organization entrusted with
protecting the law? What protection does a constitution offer against
the state if the state is to be the guarantor of the constitution?
3 The first sentence of
his The State (Oxford, 1985)
The purpose of this essay is to give a logical assess-ment of the
classical liberal conception of law and order in the human world within
an analytical framework defined by the general conditions or causes of
conflict or disorder in human interactions. The first part
(Interpersonal conflict), surveys the main positions on conflict and
order in Western thought. Classical liberalism exemplifies one of those
positions. Part 2 (Types of order), juxtaposes the relevant concepts of
order and analyzes their constitutive relations. The analysis
highlights the differences, discussed in the third part (Conflicting
orders: liberalism and socialism), between the classical liberal concept
of the “convivial order” or “natural law” of human affairs and the
concept of “social order” that is central to all forms of philosophical
socialism. “Rational choice” in the convivial order and in political
society, the fourth and last part, concludes the essay with a short
discussion of the application of “rational choice” analysis, in
particular the prisoners’ dilemma model of interaction, to convivial and
social orders.
Part 1: Interpersonal Conflict
Causes
Let us consider the necessary and sufficient causes of interpersonal
conflict as well as its possible cures. We shall begin our inquiry on a
faraway island inhabited by only two persons, A and B. Because we are
interested in interpersonal conflict, there have to be at least two
persons. Evidently, this condition, which we shall refer to as
“plurality,” is a necessary condition or cause of interpersonal
conflict.
Obviously, plurality is not a sufficient condition. A and B must
exhibit some diversity. They must have different opinions, values,
expectations, preferences, purposes, or goals. If they were of one mind
in all respects, in immediate agreement on all questions, there would be
no possibility of conflict between them. Therefore, we should add
diversity as a necessary cause of conflict.
Plurality and diversity do not constitute a sufficient set to explain
significant conflicts other than mere differences of opinion. If
plurality and diversity were the only conditions that mattered, A and B
could easily agree to disagree and that would be the end of the matter.
However, agreeing to disagree is no solution if A and B have access to
some object M that is scarce in the sense that it can serve the purpose
of either but not simul-taneously the purposes of both of them. If A
succeeds in getting control of the object, then B must live at least
temporarily with the frustration of not being able to get what he
wants—and vice versa. There is at most one winner and at least one
loser. Therefore, we must add scarcity and free access to scarce means
to the list of causes.
Figure 5.1 Causes of conflict
We can visualize the situation on the faraway island in the
conflict-diagram, which depicts the separately necessary and jointly
sufficient causes of interpersonal conflict.
Cures
Given that each of the causes is necessary, it is sufficient to
eliminate only one of them to eliminate the possibility of interpersonal
conflict between A and B. Let us assume that we can tackle each of the
four causes independently. Then there are four pure strategies for
eliminating the possibility of interpersonal conflict. The first
involves replacing plurality with its opposite, unity; the second
replaces diversity with uniformity or consensus; the third eliminates
scarcity and gets us into a condition of abundance; finally, the fourth
introduces property, thereby getting rid of free access.
Confining ourselves to a “binary” classification that considers only two
possible states for a cause (either it is present or it is not), we see
that there are also eleven mixed strategies. Obviously, such a binary
classification is not adequate if we want to study the “dynamics” of
conflict and conflict-resolution, but for our analytic purpose it will
do. Questions about weakening the causes to various degrees, about how
much to invest in attempts to do that, about trade-offs between
different solutions, and so on, are not on the agenda here.
Figure 5.2 Solutions of conflict
Unity involves the merger of A and B into a single person or else the
reduction of a person (B) to the status of a mere means or an
unconditionally loyal subject of the other (A). In any case, only one
decision-maker or ruler remains. Consensus, on the other hand, requires
that a set of opinions, valuations, preferences and the like is
available in terms of which A and B can agree on the purpose for which
and the manner in which M will be used.
As the graphical representation makes clear, Unity and Consensus involve
the replacement of a plurality of independently chosen actions with one
common, collective or social action. They imply a subordination of the
actions of many to what has been called a “thick ethics,” one that
stipulates not just how but also which ends are to be pursued. In
particular, they subordinate “law” (which they typically interpret as
legislation or authoritative commands and regulations) to some ruling
opinion about what is good and useful. In the case of Unity, that is
the ruler’s opinion. In the case of Consensus, it is an opinion shared
by the people that matter. For this reason, we may label Unity and
Consensus “political solutions.”
Note the contrast with Abundance and Property. Neither of these
eliminates the plurality of independent actions. There is no single
“thick ethics” that guides the actions of all concerned. Nevertheless,
Abundance and Property are formulas of order. They subordinate any
person’s ethics to the requirements of law, which defines the boundaries
within which persons can seek to achieve their ends. Abundance and
Property thus leave the plurality of persons and the diversity of their
purposes intact. They only affect the scarce means. For that reason,
we may label them “economic solutions” of the conflict-situation.
Abundance is a condition in which it is possible for every person to do
and get whatever he wants, regardless of what anybody else might do and
therefore also without having to rely on anybody else’s co-operation or
consent. Property requires only that each person can know which parts
of the set of scarce means are his and which are another’s.
Each of the pure strategies has had its share of famous defenders in the
history of Western philosophy. Plato4 and Hobbes5
immediately come to mind as strong advocates of unity. Despite the fact
that we usually place them at the opposite poles of almost any dimension
of philosophical thought and method, for both of them unity and only
unity provides an adequate solution to the problem of interpersonal
conflict. Like Plato’s philosopher-king, Hobbes’s Sovereign has the
first and the last word on everything. Both argued forcefully that the
slightest fissure in the structure of unity would lead to a breach of
the political wall that protects the citizens from the ever-present
threat of conflict and war.
4 In his last work,
The Laws, Plato still defended unity, even if he appeared to have
given up the hope that it ever might be realized: “The first and highest
form of the state and of the government and of the law is that in which
there prevails most widely the ancient saying, that ‘Friends have all
things in common.’ Whether there is anywhere now, or will ever be, this
communion of women and children and of property, in which the private
and individual is altogether banished from life, and things which are by
nature private, such as eyes and ears and hands, have become common, and
in some way see and hear and act in common, and all men express praise
and blame and feel joy and sorrow on the same occasions, and whatever
laws there are unite the city to the utmost—whether all this is possible
or not, I say that no man, acting upon any other principle, will ever
constitute a state which will be truer or better or more exalted in
virtue. Whether such a state is governed by Gods or sons of Gods, one,
or more than one, happy are the men who, living after this manner, dwell
there; and therefore to this we are to look for the pattern of the
state, and to cling to this, and to seek with all our might for one
which is like this” (The Laws, Book 5, 739c,d).
5 “For by Art is
created that great Leviathan called a Common-wealth, or State (in latine
Civitas), which is but an Artificiall Man; though of greater stature and
strength than the Naturall, for whose protection and defence it was
intended; and in which, the Soveraignty is an Artificiall Soul, as
giving life and motion to the whole body” (Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan
(London, 1968), Introduction).
Aristotle based his political thought firmly on the re-quirement of
consensus. As he put it, political society (and its first imperfect
manifestation, the family) de-mands a consensus on what is good and
useful.6
6 See T. A. Sinclair’s
translation of Aristotle’s Politics (Book I, section 2),
1253a16-18: “[H]umans alone have perception of good and evil, right and
wrong, just and unjust. And it is the sharing of a common view in these
matters that makes a household or a city.”
What he meant, obviously, was not the sort of ad hoc consensus that we
find in transactions on a market. The latter require no more than a
contingent agreement on such small things as a particular good, its
price and time of delivery. Nor did Aristotle mean a consensus on the
conditions that make such transactions possible.7
[7 Aristotle, Politics (Book III, section 9),
1280a31-1281al.]
While he agreed that justice in exchange is important, it was far from
him to accept it as a respectable solution to the problem of conflict.
What he had in mind was a sort of “deep consensus” to which the members
of a political society8 could always appeal to resolve their
initial disagreements—a consensus on fundamental values and opinions
that marked the very identities of the persons involved in it.
8 At least its more
notable members, those that fulfil the rather stringent conditions of
citizenship that made them fit to rule. Among the inhabitants of a city
that did not qualify as citizens Aristotle also counted the free men
that were engaged in manual labor, trade and making tools. Their part
in the political consensus of the city was minimal. It consisted in no
more than acknowledging the right to rule of the best citizens.
Such a consensus could not take root except in the soil of shared
experiences and longstanding affectionate and practical relationships.9
9 Although Aristotle
made much of the fact that the polis was a “moral” rather than,
like the family, a biological association, he insisted that it could not
function well unless it was composed of family-groups that “occupy the
same territory and can inter-marry” (Aristotle, Politics (Book
III, section 9), 1280b35).
It required common history, tradition and custom to ensure that all the
citizens would be educated to respect and esteem the same outlook on
life in its theoretical, practical and above all moral aspects.
Rousseau’s Du Contrat Social also exemplifies the
consensus-solution. However, unlike Aristotle’s, his consensus could not
be assumed to be historically given and transmitted almost as a matter
of course from one generation to the next. It had to be created ex
nihilo by skillful legislative and political manipulation on the
basis of no more than a formal agreement to agree. It was, at least
initially, an artificial construction of the sort that only an
exceptional political genius, working on a “young, not yet corrupted
people,” could hope to accomplish.
On a naive level of understanding, abundance merely involves a sort of
equilibrium of supply and demand in the sense that resources are
available in adequate quan-tities, so that everybody can satisfy his
wants with ease and without detriment to anybody else. Before the
technological and industrial revolutions of the nineteenth century,
abundance was associated mainly with asceticism. Regardless of changes
on the supply-side, there would be plenty for everybody if only people
would reduce their desires (“demand”). Philosophies of asceticism
stress control of desire and elimination of greed and covetousness.
They look forward to a harmonious order of human affairs that should
result from the adoption of a moral attitude of self-denial and
contentment with a simple and natural life. The Cynics come to mind as
proponents of this view, but we can give examples from more recent times
as well (such as some of the more fundamentalist factions of today’s
“Greens”). However, since the Enlightenment the idea of abundance rests
primarily on the prospect of an enormous increase in the productive
powers of mankind. Thus, abundance or liberation from wants and
frustration now is identified with satisfaction of all desires,
regardless of their number, quality or intensity. Many early
nineteenth-century utopian socialists already fitted this description,
but it was not until Marx had reinterpreted the old gnostic doctrine of
total spiritual liberation in terms of material and social conditions
that abundance came to mean the eradication of scarcity by the expansion
of productive power.10
10 In The German
Ideology, Part I, there is the famous statement that, under
communism, “I can do what I want, while society takes care of general
production.” That might mean that human life is split up in an
autonomous spiritual part (the gnostic’s divine self?) and a material
social part without any autonomy at all, which Engels described in his
essay “On Authority” (1872). However, in his early manuscripts, Marx
also hinted at true abundance with his vision of Man and Nature becoming
truly One—the final realization of the gnostic’s dream of recapturing
the original status of the true God, who knows himself to be All and
therefore wants nothing. “This communism . . . is the genuine
resolution of the conflict between man and nature and between man and
man—the true resolution of the strife between existence and essence . .
., between freedom and necessity, between the individual and the
species” (from the essay “Private Property and Communism” in
Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe, vol. I, 3, 114-15, Moscow 1932).
Property rests on the idea that the physical, i.e., finite or bounded,
nature of individual human beings, who are also rational agents and
producers, is the primary fact that needs to be taken into account in
any consideration of human affairs and relations. The objective or
natural boundaries that separate one person from another also entail
objective boundaries that separate one person’s words, actions and works
from those of another. What lies within a person’s boundaries is his
property. In so far as people respect each other’s property, there is
order and justice; in so far as they do not respect it, there is
disorder and injustice. Indeed, justice is respect for the natural
order, i.e. the natural law, of the human world. Thus, justice requires
human persons not only to respect other human persons but also their
rights to the extent that these do not upset the natural law nor result
from an infringement of it. For any person, these respectable rights
are the accomplishments of which he is the author—the things that come
into being under his authority, as his property. Being the rights of
natural persons acting within their natural boundaries, they properly
are called “natural rights.” In short, justice also requires
restriction of access to any scarce resource to those who are by natural
right entitled to it.
In Antiquity, the idea of Property apparently was taken up only by some
of the Sophists. Unfortunately, with few exceptions, their thoughts are
nearly inaccessible except through secondary and often hostile accounts.
Their better known opponents, Plato and Aristotle in particular, were
concerned primarily with the socio-political ordering of the city—with
the positions, roles and functions that define its organization, and the
selection of its officials. Thus, their city implied a radical division
between insiders and outsiders as well as between the higher and lower
orders of socio-political organization. They paid little or no
attention to human affairs and relations among persons in so far as they
were not defined in terms of social positions and functions. For them,
the city was to a large extent the measure of the human person. In
contrast, many of the Sophists apparently did develop a universalistic
human perspective.11 [11 Eric Havelock, The
Liberal Temper in Greek Politics (New Haven, 1957).]
For them, the concrete, historical, particular, finite natural human
beings are at any time and place the measure of all things, including
the city. They saw cities and other conventional social organizations
as no more than ripples or waves, continuously rising, falling, and
disappearing, on the sea of human nature. As the sea rarely is without
waves, so human history rarely is without social and political entities.
However, just as no single wave is permanent and no wave is the
fulfillment of the nature of the sea, no city or other socio-political
organization is more than a transient phenomenon, shaped by a fleeting
and contingent constellation of forces in human nature and its
environment. Human beings may be sociable by nature, but they are not
wedded by nature to any particular social order.12 12 Cf. their rational
capacities may be natural but no particular language is the natural
language of mankind.
Thus, for the Sophists, it was imperative to pierce “the corporate veil”
of the city. They were interested in what people really did to one
another, not in the conventional representation of their activities by
political, social or cultural authorities. For them, law was “a surety
to one another of justice,” and societies were “established for the
prevention of mutual crime and for the sake of exchange.”13
[13
Aristotle, Politics (Book III, section 9), 1280b11 and 1280b30. ]
Distant precursors of classical liberalism, they were not prepared to
sacrifice the law of natural persons on the altar of any political
organization, even one that was dedicated to the production of happiness
and virtue.
It was not until the spread of the biblical religion that the idea of
persons and their property acquired a fundamental significance in
western civilization. That religion presented the world as essentially
an interpersonal affair founded on mutual respect and covenant. It
posited a relationship between a personal God (whom orthodox Christian
doctrine eventually construed as a unified complex of three persons) and
the human world (also an interpersonal complex involving many separate
persons). According to its fundamental code, the Decalogue, the
principal source of order in the relations between God and the world and
in the relations among human beings is respect for the distinction
between “thine” and “mine.” Politics had no part in this. While Jesus
proclaimed that he had come to fulfill the Law (Matthew 5: 17), he
repudiated the offer of “all the kingdoms of the world, and the glory of
them” (4:8).14
14 “Il est impossible
qu’il y ait entente absolument cordiale . . . entre l’ Etat et les
chretiens . . . . [I]leur est même impossible de prendre l‘Etat et sa
raison tout a fait au serieux.” [It is impossible that there is
complete unanimity between the state and the Christians . . . . It is
not even possible for them to take the state and its Raison
completely seriously [my (i.e., van Dun’s) translation].] R.-L.
Bruckberger O.P., L‘Histoire de Jésus-Christ (Paris, 1965), p.
177. Of course, Bruck-berger was not referring to twentieth-century
European Christians, which he called “une collection de ballotins” (p.
176), a collection of empty paper boxes.
By the end of the seventeenth century, John Locke could give an account
of order in human affairs that was entirely based on an appreciation of
the human condition as an interpersonal complex, in which no person can
claim any naturally given social position, rank or privilege.
Understandably, a person’s property—the manifestation of his being,
life or work in the natural order of the human world—was seen as his
primary natural right, which reason could not but acknowledge as
eminently respectable. “Property” took on its classical liberal guise.
Ranking Solutions
Which type of solution one prefers depends on one’s opinions about the
feasibility and desirability of elimin-ating or attenuating one or
another of the causes of conflict. Few people believe that it is
possible to do much about scarcity, although, as noted before, there
have been those for whom it is really no more than an illusion, the
effect of a false consciousness. As for plurality, diversity and free
access, many people appear to believe that they are far easier to
manipulate than scarcity; however, they are also likelier to be
considered values in their own right.
As we have seen, Abundance and Property tackle scarcity in different
ways. Abundance refers to the elimination of scarcity in the
fundamental sense of intrapersonal scarcity. That sort of
scarcity refers to the fact that one can and therefore has to make
choices. One cannot eat an apple and use it to make apple pie;
therefore, one must choose what to do with it. Property leaves
intrapersonal scarcity intact but removes free access and therefore
interpersonal scarcity, which is the fact that one cannot have or
use exactly the same thing that another person has or uses. Both sorts
of scarcity imply the inevitable frustration of some wants, but only
intrapersonal scarcity implies frustration for which one cannot blame
another person. It depends solely on the variety of one’s goals and the
limitations of one’s options. Even Robinson Crusoe, during the first
lonely months on his island, had to face up to the intrapersonal
scarcity of resources and to make choices about their most advantageous
uses.
A person confronts intrapersonal scarcity when he becomes aware that
whatever choice he makes has opportunity costs. Either he does a
and gets whatever the consequences of doing a are, but then he
cannot do b and therefore must forego its consequences; or else
he does b at the cost of giving up whatever benefits doing a
might produce. Choice and opportunity costs are inextricably linked.15
15 Only he that has no
choices faces no costs. No matter what he does, it is the best because
the only possible course of action. Hence the Stoics’ prescription for
happiness: Renounce the illusion of freedom of choice, accept whatever
happens as what is inevitably fated to happen, and so eliminate the risk
of frustration and disillusionment. That, of course, is a classic
ascetic version of the abundance-solution.
The cause of the inability to do a and b simultaneously
may be in the nature of the person himself (his physical constitution)
or in the nature of the external means at his disposal. The latter
aspect—one cannot have one’s cake and eat it too—need no further
comment. However, the physical constitution of the person is equally
relevant. Human persons are finite beings, not only because they are
mortal but also because at any moment their capacity for consumption is
limited just as their productive capacity is limited. Consequently, a
person, even one with infinite productive powers, or with immediate
access to boundless supplies of consumption goods, would have to make
economic choices. Unless he was completely indifferent with respect to
all possible sequential orderings of enjoyments, he still would face the
risk of getting much less out of life by choosing the wrong sequence of
acts of consumption. Apparently, only a person with infinite capacities
of consumption in an environment of superabundant consumption goods of
every kind would be free from want and frustration.
Now, contemplate the co-existence of two or more persons, all of them
with abundant material resources. From any person’s point of view, all
others are external resources that can be put to many uses. Therefore,
to the extent that one has desires and ideals that can be satisfied or
realized only if others are or do what one requires of them, scarcity
persists despite the abundance of other, non-human resources. True
abundance, then, is a tall order. However, if it were possible,
abundance would have nothing to fear from plurality, diversity or free
access. The disappearance of intrapersonal scarcity takes the sting out
of those other causes of conflict.
Compared to Abundance, the other solutions, Unity, Consensus, and
Property, are less fantastic. However, they are not equal. Unity seems
to be a more demanding condition than Consensus and the latter a more
demanding condition than Property. Unity implies that diversity and
free access have been eliminated as causes of conflict. The single
remaining decision-maker has privileged access to all scarce resources
and sets priorities for their use. Unity, however, may break down under
the stress of scarcity. The decision-maker could make the wrong choices
and thereby undermine his position, leaving him with too few resources
to maintain his command amidst general dissatisfaction with his rule. On
the other hand, if he could maintain unity, then, in a worst-case
scenario, all of his subjects would perish with him if he made the wrong
choices.
Consensus implies that scarce resources will not be accessed by anyone
in a controversial way. In other words, it implies the elimination of
free access. However, like Unity, it is vulnerable to the problem of
scarcity. It could be a consensus on choices that are unsatisfactory in
their effects and so provide incentives to defect to those people on
whose consensus it relied. Alternatively, the consensus may hold but at
the cost of collective disaster. Moreover, given that Consensus leaves
plurality intact, it must invest in strategies that will ensure that the
consensus does not become spurious. Thus, Consensus is always threatened
by scarcity and by plurality.
Property, finally, only solves the problem of free access. Compared to
Abundance, Unity, and Consensus, it is very nearly merely a technical
matter. We may presume that most people will rise to the defence of
their property as soon as they begin to understand how it can be taken
away from them; and we may presume also that there is no iron law giving
the advantage to the aggressors rather than the defenders. Thus, the
property-solution appears to require no more than an adequate
organization of self-defence. However, Proper-ty is vulnerable to the
effects of scarcity, plurality and diversity, which it does not
eliminate but merely accom-modates.
Because of such considerations, we can rank the different pure solutions
on a single scale (see Figure 5.3). The ranking turns on the fact that a
solution may imply the neutralization or elimination of more than one
cause of conflict. Thus, Abundance requires the elimination of scarcity
and implies the neutralization or elimination of all conditions under
which Plurality, Diversity, and Free Access would give problems. If it
were possible, it would also, for that very same reason, be the most
complete solution to the problem of interpersonal conflict. With
Property, the reverse is true. It requires elimination of free access
but does not imply a reduction of plurality, diversity, or scarcity.
Because it requires little tampering with the conditions of human
existence, it is also the most vulnerable solution.
Figure 5.3 Ranking solutions
Utopianism
Abundance and Unity are more likely to be referred to as “utopian
solutions” than either Consensus or Property. Marxian communism, with
its prospect of a radical liberation from scarcity, fits the utopian
idea very well. So does Plato’s idea of Unity.16
16 See the quotation
from The Laws, Book 5, in note 4 above. Note, however, that in
his better-known Republic (Book II, 369-75) Plato appears to
argue that Unity should be restricted to the political sphere (the
state) as the preferred way to eliminate uneconomic (violent, warlike)
attempts to satisfy wants and desires. In other words, Unity is a way
of sanitizing politics so that it will not interfere with the natural
economic order of the supposed primordial “Golden Age.” In this
interpre-tation, Plato should be seen as the first theoretician of the
nineteenth-century’s political liberals’ ideal of a “constitutional
state” with its radical separation of economics (“private law”) and
politics (“public law”). Needless to say, nineteenth-century
constitutionalism failed to heed Plato’s warning that the “guardians of
the state” (civil and military servants) should be separated from the
economic order of society not only physically, by being confined to
barracks, but also psychologically, by being subjected to an educational
regime aimed at eradicating every trace of personal interest or
affection for anything not ordained by the state. Interestingly,
Aristotle’s idea of a political constitution differs from Plato’s
precisely by not envisaging a separation of political and economic
power. Aristotle’s political citi-zens were the heads of the society’s
economic units (households). This may be seen as a prefiguration of the
modern corporate state, where the heads of significant interest groups
(“corporations”) are the politically relevant (ruling, policy-making)
citizens.
While Hobbes is rarely charged with utopianism, there nevertheless is a
strong utopian undertone in his work. His definition of war as
consisting “not in actuall fighting; but in the known disposition
thereto, during all the time there is no assurance to the contrary,”17
[17 Hobbes, Part I,
chapter 13.]
leaves us with a definition of peace that is distinctly utopian.18
18 Leibniz noted this in
his “Caesarinus Fürstenerius,” in Patrick Riley (ed.), Leibniz:
Political Writings (Cambridge, 1988). Against “the sharp-witted
Englishman,” Leibniz argued that “no people in civilized Europe is ruled
by the laws that he proposed; wherefore, if we listen to Hobbes, there
will be nothing in our land but out-and-out anarchy” (p. 118).
According to Leibniz, Hobbes’s argument was a fallacy: “[H]e thinks
things that can entail inconvenience should not be borne at all—which is
foreign to the nature of human affairs . . . [E]xperience has shown that
men usually hold to some middle road, so as not to commit everything to
hazard by their obstinacy” (p. 119).
His Commonwealth—“a reall Unity of them all, in one and the same Person”19—[19 Hobbes, Part II,
chapter 17.]
is supposed to be the necessary condition of that utopian peace.20
20 Eric Voegelin, “The
New Science of Politics,” in M. Henningsen, The Collected Works of
Eric Voegelin, vol. 5, Modernity without Restraint (Columbia
and London, 2000), p. 218 also notes the gnostic-utopian theme in
Hobbes’s argument.
If Consensus in its classical Aristotelian version cannot plausibly be
charged with utopianism, the modern version, epitomized by the writings
of Rousseau and other apologists for the sovereign republican State,
does have a pronounced utopian streak. It derives from the idea that
the republican state requires that human nature be changed.21
[21
J.-J. Rousseau, Du Contrat Social, Book II, chapter 7.]
The actual transformation of human beings into “true citizens” is
necessary to produce a genuine political consensus without which the
“general will” cannot but remain a lifeless legal fiction (and an easy
target for the analytical attacks of rational choice theorists).
It was Plato who first adumbrated the theme of the transformation of
human nature as a prerequisite of a just political order with his
detailed description of the process by which natural human beings must
be transformed into guardians of the city. Rousseau, an admirer of the
Greek’s theory of political education, also shared his notion that among
human beings the state cannot be justified. That idea, that human
nature rules out a justification of the state, is the foundation of
individualist anarchism,22 but Plato and Rousseau turned it
into the proposition that to justify the state one should replace human
nature with something that is by definition compatible with the
state-“guardianship” or “citizen-ship.”
22 Referring to the
theory of rational choice, Anthony de Jasay’s The State and
Against Politics (London, 1997) offer many detailed arguments for
that proposition. It has been a constant theme in the work of, among
others, the late Murray N. Rothbard, e.g.
The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic
Highlands, NJ, 1982).
However, states did not begin to control formal education on a scale and
with a determination approaching the requirements of Plato’s or
Rousseau’s program until the twentieth century. Whether openly
proclaiming their utopianism or disguising it as piecemeal social
engineering, modern Western states embraced the notion of a “revolt
against nature,” sweeping away much of Europe’s Christian and classical
liberal heritage.
Arguably, Property is immune to the charge of utopianism. Neither the
Sophists nor those in the modern Lockean tradition are prominent figures
in the literature on utopian thought. Descriptions of what a liberal or
libertarian world might be under ideal conditions fail to give an
impression of utopianism. Even with the problem of free access solved
and property as secure as it can be, people still are left to their own
resources, or dependent on the charity of others, to make something of
life. Indeed, those “ideal conditions” merely ensure that nobody has any
guaranteed immunity from the slings and arrows of life. It is no wonder
that Property gets short shrift in an age dominated by utopian hankering
after guaranteed satisfaction of wants, except perhaps in the “ersatz”
form of allegedly market-friendly government-imposed pro-growth
policies—that is to say, as a means to approach the Abundance solution
to the problem of order. Incisive and logically compelling as they are,
Jasay’s arguments for the virtues of anarchy as a principle of order
cannot but fail to strike a chord among those who have been
indoctrinated with the notion that partisan politics—the art of
externalizing costs—can be universalized into the art of eliminating
costs.
Part 2: Types of Order
Social Order and Convivial Order
Unity and Consensus, as political solutions, require social
organization: a social order or society, with a structure of command and
obedience, and a hierarchical stratification of rulers and subjects,
leaders and followers, directors and members or employees. Abundance and
Property, on the other hand, as economic solutions, require no such
thing as a society in that sense. The order they constitute is a
convivial order,23 in which people live together regardless
of their member-ship, status, position, role or function in any, let
alone the same, society.
23 From the Latin
convivere, to live together. I use “conviviality” primarily because
its literal meaning is the same as that of the Dutch “samenleving”
(literally, living together), which stands in contrast to “maat-schappij”
(the Dutch word for society).
A society is an economy in the classical sense of “a household.” It is
also a teleocracy (a system of rule aiming to achieve a particular set
of ends, which may fixed by the society’s constitution, or left to the
discretion of its leading organ). However, many societies have more or
less extensive nomocratric24 sectors, which are defined by
general rules of conduct rather than end-specific rules.
24 As far as I know
Michael Oakeshott (Rationalism in Politics and Other Essavs
(London, 1962) introduced the terms “teleocracy” and “nomocracy.”
For example, in modern politically defined or state-dominated societies
of the Western type, “private law” (le droit privé, the
regulation of the so-called private sector and the interactions of
private citizens) often is nomocratic.
A family, a club, a ranch, a firm, a corporation, a church, a criminal
gang, a state, or a state-like concoction such as the European
Union—these are all examples of societies in the sense that is relevant
here. At this point in the argument our interest is in the difference
between the social and the convivial types of order per se; it is
not in the manner in which order is achieved or maintained. Therefore,
we need not consider here the obvious differences between, say, a
criminal gang or a state, on the one hand, and, on the other hand,
societies that pursue their economic, religious, cultural or
recreational goals in peaceful ways, without resort to violence,
coercion or fraud.
Because of their teleocratic structures and the unity of their planned
collective actions, it makes sense to personify societies and to regard
them as artificial or conventional persons defined by their constitution
and social decision-rules. It does not make any more sense to personify
a convivial order or to ascribe plans, opinions, values, decisions or
actions to it, than it does to ascribe such things to its opposite, war.
Thus, it makes sense to ask whether and how a particular society
participates in the convivial order; but there is no sense in asking
about the participation of the convivial order in a social order.
A convivial order is not a society. It is a catallaxy, an order of
friendly exchange among independent per-sons.25
25 On the distinction
between “economy” and “catal-laxy,” see F. A. Hayek, “The Confusion of
Language in Political Thought”, in F. A. Hayek, New Studies in
Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas (London
and Henley, 1978), pp. 90-92.
We can find examples of convivial order in daily life, especially in the
relations among friends and neighbors, among travelers and local people,
and among buyers and sellers on open markets. We find them, in fact,
wherever people meet and mingle and do business in their own name,
whether or not they belong to the same or any social organization.
There is no need for them to be aware of each other’s social
affiliation or position, or of any teleocratic or nomocratic regulations
that might be imposed by some society or other. Dealings between a
natural and an artificial person (a society or one of its officials) or
between two artificial persons may be said to be convivial by extension
and analogy if they conform to the patterns (or laws) of friendly
exchange among independent persons. However, the paradigm of
conviviality is a relation between natural persons.
Although a convivial order is not a teleocracy and is an order
maintained by adherence to general rules of conduct, it would be unwise
to refer to it as a “nomocracy.” The latter term, like “autocracy,”
“democracy,” and “aristocracy,” suggests a system of rule, government
and administration, which does not apply to the convivial order.26
26 For this reason,
Hayek (in Hayek, “The Confusion of Language in Political Thought”)
preferred “nomarchy” to “nomocracy.”
A simple example of a nomocracy would be a soccer game. It is played
according to a set of rules that apply equally to the competing teams
and do not aim at a specific outcome of the game but nevertheless are
eminently artificial and imposed legal rules. Similarly, a
state-imposed nomocracy, for example in the form of “competition law,”
is the implementation of a policy by the social authorities. Nomocracies
are social constructs just as much as teleocracies are.27
27 Historically, the
demise of teleocratic central planning in the last quarter of the
twentieth century was not followed by the catallactic order of
conviviality (the free market in the libertarian sense) but by more or
less nomocratic forms of socialism (“the mixed economy,” “the third
way,” “the active welfare state”).
In contrast, conviviality is an objective condition of interaction.
Like its opposite or negation, which is war (disorder or confusion in,
or a breakdown of, convivial relations), its presence or absence can be
ascertained without reference to the rules of any organization, system
of government or administration. Consequently—to use what once was a
commonplace among lawyers—the laws of conviviality must be discovered;
they need not be invented. From the point of view of political science,
the convivial order is anarchical, maintained by a variable mixture of
prudence, common decency, informal pressure, and (where not
criminalized) investments in means of self-defence.
Figure 5.4 A social order or society
Significant Differences
To appreciate the differences between a social and a convivial order, we
can draw a diagrammatic representa-tion of a social order (see Figure
5.4).
Students of legal systems, business administration, public
administration, and social systems in general, are familiar with this
type of organigram. From the family to the state, from the small
entrepreneurial firm to the large corporation, the army or the church,
every society can be represented by a more or less complex variation of
the diagram. Indeed, a society is a system of social positions, each
with its proper function, role, duties or entitlements—its
proper “legal competence.”
A representation of the convivial order differs marked-ly from a social
organigram. The figure gives us a snapshot of multifarious relations
among many persons. Some of those relations are affective, others
professional or commercial; some are fleeting, others durable; and so on
and so forth. In the convivial order there is no formally fixed
hierarchy of pre-defined positions, roles or functions. The fact that
some people are more prominent or influential than others does not
entail any difference in their status under the laws of conviviality.
Figure 5.5 The convivial order
Natural persons participate in a society as performers of one or more
social functions or roles, as occupants of one or more social positions,
each of which has a socially defined utility function attached to it.
Moreover, as participants in a society they move in a world that is
characterized by clearly defined positions, rewards, and punishments,
and hence more or less fixed relations between actions and consequences.
Thus, like the players of a game, they are inclined, indeed expected,
to have a strictly utilitarian attitude towards decision-making.
However, unless they are fully socialized, having internalized their
“social identity,” there is no guarantee that they will abstain from
seeking to use their position for purposes that are not part of, or may
be at odds with, their social function. That is why societal organizers
face the familiar problems of monitoring and controlling people to make
them observe their “social responsibilities.” Apart from the societal
organizers, the people in a society are no more than human resources,
which—like other sorts of resources—have to be managed in the service of
the goals set for the organization. In their endeavors to control the
“human factor,” societal organizers may well try to eliminate it
altogether, for example by training animals, or introducing machinery
and computers. Where elimination is not possible they will resort to
indoctrination or set up systems of incentives, rewards and punishments,
or rigorous and easily monitored step-by-step procedures and ergonomic
micro-management to provide motivation and to ensure efficiency. Human
resources management is an integral part of social existence.
In a convivial order, in contrast, people appear only as themselves,
doing whatever they do under their own personal responsibility. There
is nothing like a social responsibility in the convivial order. No
society takes the blame or appropriates the praise for any individual
person’s acts and no person can get away with any kind of mischief
merely by noting that he is only doing his job. While one person may
agree to assume a larger or smaller part of the responsibilities and
liabilities of another, every act remains someone’s responsibility.28
28 For a discussion of
the implications of this for so-called “limited liability corporations,”
see Frank van Dun, Personal Freedom versus Corporate Liberties
(London, 2006, forthcoming). [Since 2009, available
here.--A.F.]
In contrast, many societies have systems for passing on social
responsibility that lead to nowhere, for example by placing ultimate
responsibility with an inaccessible deity, an anonymous “public” or
“people,” or an abstraction such as “society itself.” Such arrangements
are inconceivable in a convivial order, where there is no corporate veil
and responsibility is necessarily personal, not diluted by organization.
Indeed, people may be held responsible—asked to justify themselves—by
anybody, even a complete stranger, who is affected by their words or
actions. Hence, to maintain themselves in the convivial order, people
have to acquire an ethics of responsibility rather than an ability to
prove that they are maximizing some “given” utility function.
Among other significant differences between a society and a convivial
order, we note the conditions of mem-bership. A society necessarily has
clear boundaries that separate its members from non-members because it
is essentially an organization of men and resources that aims at some
unique common goal or set of goals, which it tries to achieve by
suitably co-ordinated collective or common action. To reach those
goals, a society develops a strategy, assigns tasks and allocates
resources to its officers and members.
All societies must work out the problem of securing enough income to pay
for their expenses, and many face the additional problem of distributing
a part or the whole of the social income among the society itself, its
ruling members and its “rank and file.” A society does all of those
things according to its customary, constitutional, statutory or legal
rules, although contingency measures and the dictates of crisis
management occasionally override their application. In any case, it
must know who is a member of the society and who is not; what the
members do and contribute and on what conditions they participate in
social action. Formal and exclusive membership is a necessary condition
of social existence.
A convivial order has no membership in that sense. It does not organize
any collective or common action; it does not generate, let alone
distribute, any social income. People can live convivially without
being card-carrying members of the same club or association, without
engaging in common pursuits or having a common leader, director, or
governor. Whereas in a nomocracy such as a soccer game or a state’s
private sector, people need some sort of certificate of registration or
license to be permitted to play, they need no such thing in a convivial
order. Conviviality requires no papers.
Elements of Order: Lex and Ius
Societies or social orders and convivial orders differ in their
constitutive relations of order. Social orders essen-tially are lex-based
or legal orders. The term “lex” refers to the Latin verb “legere” [to
choose; to pick]. It denotes a relationship in which a person holds a
position that entitles him to choose or pick others to do what he
commands them to do. Its original meaning was the act of calling men to
arms or to report for military duty.29
29 “Lex” is related to “dilectus,”
(military) mobiliza-tion—confer the Roman “legions.”
Later, “lex” came to denote any general command issued by a politically
organized society, one that is capable of enforcing obedience to its
commands by military force. Eventually, the word acquired the meaning of
a directive or rule of conduct that is generally accepted within a given
society as being applicable and enforceable in some way by the social
authorities, even if the society is not political. Calling a legal
order “a social order” serves to highlight the fact that acceptance of
and obedience to the legal rules is to a large extent a matter of habit
or custom.30
30 “Societas” is related
to “sequi” [to follow]: a society involves people who follow the same
rules. In the representation of the solutions of the problem of
interpersonal conflict, we see the lex-relation most clearly in
the unity-solution, where A occupies the position of the legislator and
B the position of the subject. In the consensus-solution, both A and B
occupy the legislative position but only in so far as they are
representatives of the consensus that supposedly defines the social
order.
Thus, a social order implies the existence of a system of rules that
define positions of “authority” or “command” to which other positions
are subordinated. It is customary to personify such positions and to
refer to them as to artificial persons, for example “ruler,”
“legislator,” “director,” “rector,” “senate,” “general assembly,”
“secretary,” “subject,” “employee,” “ser-vant,” “private citizen.” It
is no more a matter of empirical science to determine what those social
personages can or cannot do than it is an empirical question what the
King, the Queen or a Knight in chess can or cannot do. To answer such
questions, one should consult the appropriate legal texts or rulebooks,
or people (legists) that possess expert knowledge of the
applicable rules. Of course, one should take care to consult the right
books and experts. A Queen in chess is not the same thing as a Queen in
bridge; the rules defining the French Presidency do not define the
American Presidency; and what a Belgian citizen can or cannot do may
differ widely from the legal competence of an Austrian citizen. Every
society, whatever its size, form or function, has its own legal system,31
which supplies the criteria for determining whether an act is legal or
illegal.
31 Here we can see why
legal positivists—for whom “law” denotes the legal system of a
(state-dominated) society—must end up with empty-shell characterizations
of “law,” such as Kelsen’s “dynamic system of norms that derive their
validity from a single presupposed merely formal Grundnorm”
[approximately foundational norm] and Hart’s “union of primary and
secondary rules.” As for substance, “[positive] law can be anything,”
‘‘there is no logical connection between law and justice,” and so on.
Maintaining social order, therefore, is largely a matter of preventing
or suppressing illegal activity, or else of changing the rules to
legalize activities that, for one reason or another, are deemed
acceptable by the current social authorities.
In contrast to social orders, the convivial order is ius-based.
The word “ius” refers to the Latin verb “iurare,” which means to swear,
to speak solemnly; to commit oneself toward others. The ius-relation
implies no positions of authority or command, but direct personal
contacts resulting in agreements, covenants and contracts, in mutual
commitments, obligations or iura. Strictly speaking, the ius-relation
can exist only between natural persons, as they are the only persons
that are naturally capable of independent speech and action. It does
not hold between a natural person and something that is not a person.
In particular, it does not hold between social positions.32
32 By extension and
analogy, it can be applied also to any two personified objects, such as
mutually indepen-dent societies, provided that these are represented or
operated by natural persons.
Unlike the lex-relation, the ius-relation holds between
persons who need not be members or subjects of the same society. It
holds between persons who are independent of one another, at least in
the sense of not being related to one another as a superior to an
inferior or as subjects of the same superior in any social organization.33
33 Referring to the
types of order discussed in part I: the ius-relation most clearly
finds a place in the property-solution. Neither A nor B having any say
or authority over the other, any interaction between them must be
justified in terms of their mutual respect, consent and contractual
obligations. There is no other lawful way in which either of them could
gain access to the means controlled by the other to reach ends that are
beyond the powers embodied in his own means. Theoretically, we also
could subsume the relations between A and B in the abundance-solution
under the ius-relation, but there would be no point in doing so.
Neither A nor B could gain anything from taking on obligations in a
world without scarcity.
What natural persons can or cannot do is not defined by any set of legal
rules. It is defined by their nature, which we have to accept as “a
given” and to study accordingly. Moreover, we do not have to know any
legal rules to determine which acts are injurious to natural persons or
which acts are infringements of the order of conviviality among such
persons. To make such determinations, we must study what really
happened, what real people really did to one another, taking into
account their mutual commitments and obligations—their iura. In
short, we must study the world as jurists, not as legists,
because the objective here is to determine whether an act was just (in
accordance with ius), not whether it was legal or illegal in some
society. Admittedly, iura can be as varied and diverse as legal
systems are, but compared to the myriad of forms, sizes and functions of
social entities human persons are remarkably similar beings.
The jurist as such is not concerned with legal rules but with rules of
law. The latter, in the strict sense, are deductions from the
conditions that constitute the convivial order of beings of the same
natural kind. Thus, they are implied in the ius- or
speech-relation itself, which requires the speakers to be “free and
equal” in their exchanges of questions and answers, arguments and
counter-arguments, proposals and counter-proposals, in order to
communicate to one another what their commitments are. Obviously,
physical intimidation and threats, lies and deliberately misleading
utterances, and the like, defeat the purpose of entering into a
speech-relation. One who engages in such things places himself outside
the law because he willfully upsets the order of ius-based
interaction by failing to deal with another as a free and equal person.
In short, he is a criminal, one who does not respect the relevant
distinctions (discrimina) that define conviviality.
In a wider sense, the concept of a rule of law also covers rules of
justice, “technical determinations” of just and efficient ways to
maintain or to restore the convivial order in a given historical
context, where linguistic and other conventions enter into the
understanding of human actions. One can easily recognize here the basic
intuition of the theory of natural law—before it was derailed by
attempts to derive the constitution of an ideal society from nature—that
the fundamental patterns of order, the natural laws, of human relations
are implicit in the rational nature of the physical human animal: its
capacity of speech (ratio, logos) and its ability to act in
accordance with such rationally undertaken commit-ments.
The study of “legal systems” and the “legal persons” they define is
poles apart, with respect to its object as well as its methods, from the
study of the ius-based convivial order among natural persons.
The “law” (leges) of the legal positivists can be anything
whatso-ever, but the jurists’ law, the ius-based order of
convivi-ality, is in its principles the same always and everywhere. The
same act may be legal in one society and illegal in another; but we need
no legal reference to say that it is just, or unjust. Likewise for
distributive justice: it primarily concerns a distribution of burdens or
benefits according to principles on which the parties had agreed as a
ius established among free and equal persons, regardless of any
socially imposed rules. With respect to distributions within a social
setting, “distributive justice” stands for a distribution based on an
appreciation of merit (which necessarily must be relative to some task
or purpose). In contrast, social justice—the satisfaction of every
member’s wants by society, according to a socially defined ranking of
either wants or membership status—is independent of agreement or merit.
It brings to mind the Marxian illusion that we all can and are entitled
to do and have what we want while society takes care of production.34
34 See note 10 above.
Conviviality, Natural Law, and Justice
From the above considerations, we can induce the basic structure of law.35
35 The argument and a
detailed analysis can be found in
“The Logic of Law.”
It is an interpersonal order that is ius-based. It com-prises at
least two independent and autonomous36 persons.
36 On the technical
meaning of “autonomy” in this context, see the text referenced in note
35.
Paradigmatically, they are natural persons, each of them exercising
legislative power over his own property—the means of action, which may
be material things or non-autonomous persons, that belong to him. If we
assume the existence of only one autonomous person, the formal structure
of law is reduced to a lex-based order. Simple as it is, the
schematic representation of the ius-based interpersonal order has
many interesting properties, but this is not the place for a detailed
formal analysis.
From a philosophical point of view, the analysis is of interest
primarily when we consider how human persons fit into the scheme,
leaving aside all kinds of artificial and supernatural persons and
piercing through the “corporate veil” of social constructions. At least
at the moment of first contact, before either one has had a chance to do
anything to the other, two natural persons can stand only in the ius-relation
to one another. They are, at that moment, two independent (free)
persons of the same natural kind, neither one being subordinated to the
other. Of course, in this case, ex hypothesi, there can be no
subordination in consequence of some pre-existing iura or of some
previous injustice committed by one of them against the other. They are
in a Lockean “state of nature,” which is the convivial order by another
name. Their relation is according to the natural law. In terms of a
once current definition of law, it is a relation characterized by
freedom and equality.37
37 For my reservations
about the use of “equality” in this context, see the paper cited in note
2.
Law is a condition of freedom among likes, that is rational agents of
the same natural kind.
Justice, or ius-titia, is that which is instrumental for bringing
about or maintaining the condition of ius. It comprises all
actions that effectively aim at keeping human relations within the order
of speech among free and equal persons. Thus, its main function is to
prevent disorder or confusion from affecting the convivial order of
natural persons. Injustice is first of all the result of not respecting
another natural person as a free and equal person, for example by
confusing him with something that is not a person at all but, say, a
material object, animal, or a social construct. Other significant types
of injustice result from confusing one natural person with another,
especially when such confusion leads to rewarding or praising, punishing
or blaming, one person for the words or actions of another. Such
confusions, whether deliberate or not, whether rectifiable or not,
betray an inability to abide by the conditions of conviviality.
Thus, with respect to the convivial order, “justice” has a clear and
unambiguous objective meaning. Jasay rightly criticized the efforts of
political and social theorists to appropriate the term “justice” while
obfuscating its true meaning with various attempts to define justice as
“something else.”38
38 Jasay, “Justice as
something else,” which is the pivotal text in his beautiful collection
of essays: Justice and Its Surroundings (Indianapolis, Ind.,
2002).
Obviously, justice has no place in the legal-positivistic view that
“law” is the legal system of one or another society. Maintaining social
order or upholding the prevailing conditions of legality has no logical
or other necessary connection with maintaining the ius-based
order of conviviality. Who will deny that “There is no logical
connection between lex and justice” sounds more plausible than
“There is no logical connection between ius and justice?”
Part 3: Conflicting Orders: Liberalism and Socialism
The convivial order requires no social organization, only friendly,
peaceful interpersonal relations. In that sense, it is a universal
natural condition, the existence of which we can identify whenever and
wherever there are contacts between people. In the same way we can
identify its “negation,” which is war, or disorder or confusion in human
affairs. Like that between life and death, the difference between
convivial order and war comes, as it were, with the very nature of
homo sapiens and his world. In contrast, societies are local,
temporary and contingent constructions. There is no such thing as
natural society. Nevertheless, awareness of the net advantages of
co-operation and organization leads people to adopt a social mode of
existence, to form or join one or more societies on the expectation that
they will improve their quality of life or their chances of achieving
cherished goals. This raises questions about the compatibility of
social and convivial orders.
A convivial order conceivably may disappear when too many individuals
start making war on one another, although it is difficult to see how
such criminality could become infectious without being socially
organized. As the word is used at present, war is pre-eminently a
social phenomenon in that it involves high degrees of social
organization and mobilization. Indeed, societies may be outlaws from
the point of view of conviviality because of the way in which they treat
their members or outsiders or both. Many societies thrive by perfecting
the art of disturbing the conditions of conviviality by invasive actions
of lesser or greater magnitude, from occasional raids to legalizing
crimes or making lawful activity illegal39 to all-out war.
39 Prominent examples
are the “underground economy” and other “victimless crimes.”
Although societies can be formed and operated on principles that are
compatible with the convivial order, social orders are not necessarily
compatible with the convivial order.40
40 “Society” is not the
same as “community.” The latter term denotes a categorization of people
with some common property or relation: locality, nationality, language,
occupation, religion, and so on. Thus we have local, national,
linguistic, religious, artistic, cultural, academic, criminal and many
other communities. There is even a human community, a community of the
living, and a community of the dead. Members of a society usually have
a community of interests, but the community of people with a common
interest need not be socially organized. Indeed, they may be only dimly
aware of one another’s existence. Community leaders typically are
strong personalities, not occupants of some predefined position—but many
such leaders aspire to organize or “socialize” their community. A
community has no “collective decision rules.” It need be no more than a
segment or aspect of the convivial order. It is not a type of order
distinct from either the convivial or the social order.
To some extent, all societies put the convivial order at risk. They
imply some degree of hierarchical organization and mobilization—a
concentration of power over men and resources that they can use for
their particular social purposes. Moreover, societies tend to subvert
the attitude of freedom among likes that characterizes conviviality.
They offer rewards not just in the form of the accomplishment of their
purpose or an occasional bonus or token of appreciation. They also
offer differentiated social positions, which carry different sets of
powers, privileges, immunities, perks of office, or financial benefits.
Unlike the convivial order, where the concept does not even make sense,
societies offer “career opportunities” and feed particular ambitions and
rivalries regarding social position and rank. On the other hand,
societies may languish, perish even, when they cannot adequately control
the human factor. An atmosphere of either conviviality or war may
pervade the social structure; the members may deal with one another as
free and equal persons or alternatively as enemies. The social
enterprise becomes pointless as the convivial attitude of live and let
live or its warlike antithesis takes root to the detriment of social
efficiency.
When there is incompatibility between social and convivial order, the
question arises which type of order is more basic or worthy of respect
than the other is. With regard to this question, classical liberals and
philoso-phical socialists take radically opposed positions.
Philosophical socialists assert that social order trumps the natural law
of freedom among likes. They focus on social orders, in which people
occupy positions and perform roles and functions in the pursuit of some
social goal. Consequently, efficiency in the pursuit of that goal
trumps interpersonal justice, even if the goal is called “social
justice.” For a socialist, human individuals are social resources or
recipients of social benefits, in any case socially constructed “legal
persons” with socially defined claims (“rights”) and duties. Hence,
philosophical socialists face the task of socializing human beings to
make them internalize the demands of society. In contrast, for a
classical liberal, societies are human constructs, and human nature and
natural conviviality trump social order. His task is to humanize
societies to make them compatible with the natural law of conviviality.
The main thrust of Jasay’s work is, that it is vain to expect the state
to be of any help in that task. However, neither his nor anybody else’s
critiques appear able to stop the relentless drive towards displacement
of convivial modes of interaction by social forms that has characterized
so much of recent history. If being reduced to a mere placeholder in a
scheme of social organiza-tion—a resource to be managed—is the true mark
of servitude then we are now very close to reaching the goal of what
Aldous Huxley, not too long ago, called the “most important Manhattan
Project of the future . . . vast government-sponsored enquiries into
what the politicians and the participating scientists will call “the
problem of happiness”—in other words, the problem of making people love
their servitude.”41
41 Aldous Huxley,
Brave New World (New York, 1953), p. xii (foreword).
Natural Law and Its Politically Motivated Denial
A person’s freedom under the natural law comprises any action that is
compatible with the natural law of conviviality. It includes taking on
obligations towards other persons and by implication entering into
society with them provided the society in question is itself compatible
with natural law. It does not include coercing others into submission
either to him or to a society of which he is a member. It does not
include coercing other persons who are in society with him, except to
enforce in the agreed manner the rules according to which they had
consented42 to behave and to act.
42 Obviously, “consent”
does not refer to something outside the ius-relation. It refers
to consent by a free rational agent, not to coerced or fraudulently
obtained acceptance of conditions.
Nor does it include coercing others who are in society with him by
taking anything from them that they had not agreed to invest in that
society. In justice, withholding the benefits of membership is the only
proper way in which to enforce social rules and regulations. The
ultimate sanction is expulsion if that option has not been foreclosed at
the constitutional level. Most societies can live with those
limitations, but political societies, states in particular, obviously do
not. Consequently, propo-nents of political social orders face the
problem of justifying the very existence of political societies—the
problem of debunking natural law.
Logically promising strategies for addressing that problem involve the
rejection of freedom or equality, either of which is a necessary
condition of natural law. Such rejections have been based on one of two
arguments: one is that the condition (freedom or equality) is a true but
undesirable and possibly dangerous state of affairs; the other is that
the condition is no more than an illusion. Thus, Plato insisted that
politics must resort to “a shameful lie.” All citizens must be taught
that they are children of their country (and therefore brothers and
sisters), but also that they are by divine ordinance destined
individually for unequal social ranks.43
43 Plato, The
Republic, Book 3, 413c-415c.
That indoctrination is necessary to ensure that they remain unaware of
their natural condition and to make them accept social inequality.
Similarly, Hobbes argued that equality was the root of all the evils of
the “natural condition of mankind”44 and that only an
absolute political inequality45 offered any hope of peaceful
co-existence.
44 Hobbes, p. (part I,
chapter 13).
45 Hobbes, p. (Part II,
chapter 17).
Aristotle, on the other hand, went to great lengths to prove that social
position is merely a reflection if not a fulfillment of natural
endowment. The doctrine of “the slave by nature” was only the most
telling illustration of his belief in natural inequality. For
Aristotle, the freedom of the elite of noble citizens rested on their
command over the lesser breeds of men. The natural inequality among
human beings was his justifying ground of the socially necessary
hierarchy and its division of human beings into free citizens and unfree
subjects.
Until far into the eighteenth century, most attacks on natural law (in
the sense of order among natural persons) were indeed attacks on
equality. Later, the focus of the attacks shifted to freedom. Rousseau
maintained that he could justify the fact that, although they are born
free, people everywhere are in chains.46
46 Rousseau, Book 1,
chapter 1.
Natural freedom is a fact, but it also is dangerous to human existence;
that is why it should be replaced with civil liberty, which is obtained
when every citizen becomes one with all the other citizens and therefore
with the state. Civil liberty, then, requires the transformation of the
human being from a natural, independent person into an artificial or
“moral” person, the citizen. The latter is everything a natural human
being is not. Above all, the citizen is only a part of a larger whole,
and a part that is impotent without the assistance of the rest.47
47 Rousseau, Book 2,
chapter 7.
A person’s natural freedom, his capacity for independent action and
thought, must be eliminated if a state is to be legitimate and equality
is to be instituted. Of course, that equality is no longer a
qualitative sameness or likeness of natural kind, but a quantitative
equality of rank and power in political society. Karl Marx went one
giant step further by arguing that the particular individual’s freedom
is an illusion—a reflection of his false consciousness. It will remain
so until that individual is transformed into a true species-being and as
a universal individual absorbs in himself the whole of humanity. Only
then human society will become a universal society without
differentiation of class or rank—a society of equals.
Figure 5.6 Purpose of Force
The vigorous currents of egalitarian and collectivist thought in the
twentieth century and the strident rhetoric of “solidarity” indicate the
enduring popularity of that mereological conception of the human person
as an integral and dependent part of a larger whole.48
48 On the interpretation
of those mereological ideas as reflecting a religious paradigm shift,
see Frank van Dun,
“Natural Law, Liberalism, and Christianity,” Journal of
Libertarian Studies, 15/3(Summer 2001): pp. 1-36.
So does the conception of his liberty as equal participation in the
“democratic self-determination” of that whole. It obviously does not
bear any resemblance to a person’s freedom within the natural law. As
far as a seemingly overwhelming majority of Western intellectuals is
concerned, the idea of justice as freedom among likes holds no
attraction at all. Despite Anthony de Jasay’s demonstrations of its
vacuity, even many “liberals” cannot break free from the modern
conception of liberty and equality as nomocratic legal constructs that
must be democratically validated, regulated and enforced.
Ordered
Anarchy Natural Order, the Problem of Adequate Defence
The peculiar problem of the natural law theorist is the vulnerability of
the property-solution that we noted earlier. To put it differently, it
is the problem of the adequate defence of every person against
aggression and coercion—in particular against organized aggression and
coercion, against aggressive and coercive societies. Statistically, in a
man-to-man confrontation, the defender stands at least an equal chance
against the attacker. Against an organized attack, he is nearly
helpless unless he can organize an adequate force in defence of his
property. However, it is in the nature of things that defensive force
is reactive, organized to be effective against known threats. The
initiative lies with the aggressors. Innovative aggressive techniques
and organizations, against which no adequate defence has yet been
developed, provide a window of opportunity for aggressors.49
49 Politically
noteworthy examples are the invention of firearms and the organization
of standing armies towards the end of the middle ages, and the
development of powerful techniques of “rational administration” and of
vast public bureaucracies and police forces in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries.
We can approach the problem of the instability of the convivial order by
considering Figure 5.6. It represents the types of outcome that we can
expect from different regimes concerning the availability of organized
force. Each regime is characterized by a position on the organizational
dimension (from monopolistic to competitive supply of force) and by the
prevalence of force used for either defensive or aggressive purposes.
Under a regime where the defensive use of force prevails and where
defensive force is supplied competitively (that is, where people
actually can choose with whom they will contract for defence), the
likely outcome is “ordered anarchy.”50
50 See for example
Jasay’s essays in Against Politics, especially
“Self-contradictory contractarianism,” and “Conventions: some thoughts
on the economics of ordered anarchy.”
Such a regime is the individualist-anarchist’s ideal of a pure rule of
law. A competitive supply of adequate defensive force may give a person
all the assurance he needs, but it is vulnerable to innovative
aggression. Moreover, competitive rivalries among organized forces may
degenerate into war, the same outcome as under a regime of competing
suppliers of aggressive force.51
51 Just as there are
individual rogues, so there may be rogues among the suppliers of
organized force. If history shows one thing, it is that protection
rackets can be very lucrative, durable and eventually successful in
securing territorial monopolies of force. The develop-ment of a system
of territorial monopolies may result in a sort of international ordered
anarchy, in a war, or in the creation of a larger monopolistic political
society. Most modern states are a “unification” of diverse small, often
non-political societies. The contemporary tenden-cy towards interstate
co-operation and the formation of supranational political entities (and
pressure groups) moves in the same direction.
In any case, it may not be easy for an individual to switch at short
notice to another supplier of defensive force if he gets into a conflict
with his current supplier and the latter does not want to let him go.
Which other supplier will be willing to take on an organized force
merely to gain a customer, who so far has not yet made a single payment
or contribution?
The logical opposite of the rule of law is the police state.52
52 I use the term
“police state” here in its original meaning of a state organized to
mobilize men and resources for the purpose of implementing its external
and internal (social) policies.
It is a monopoly of force engaging in organized aggression possibly
against outsiders but in any case against its subjects to raise revenue
and to force them to implement its policies (which to some degree may be
paternalistic, “for the good of the subjects”). Defensive force
supplied monopolistically incorporates its “clients” willy-nilly into a
single defensive organization (as in a Rechtsstaat). However, if
a person is dependent on one supplier of defensive force, he is
virtually at the latter’s mercy and may end up as his subject. There is
little he can do against that organization, whether it sticks largely to
a defensive function or—as according to Anthony de Jasay it is wont to
do—proves itself a budding police state. In any case, the individual
will find himself involved with an organized society specializing in the
use of force and consequently with its political life.
In virtually every society there is a significant amount of politics.
There are people jockeying for position, trying to make a career,
quarrelling over rewards and disciplinary measures and the distribution
of the social income. Almost everybody will use all sorts of pressure
and influence (perhaps fraud and occasionally violence and force) to
sway its officials’ decisions or to build coalitions. In societies
where the use of force is monopolized, those activities are likely to be
far more intense than in other social contexts. That is because in such
political societies the stakes are not limited to what people are
willing to pay but extend to what they can be made to pay, short of
driving them to open revolt or other persistent illegal activity.
Amazingly, many people continue to believe that the risk of abuse of
power can be averted by defining rules for its proper use. That belief
was characteristic of nineteenth-century political liberalism and its
commitment to a formal constitution: some exercises of power are simply
“not done,” regardless of the observance of formal and procedural
niceties, because they are incompatible with the requirements of
justice, and consequently fall outside the range of things to which
people may be presumed to agree. However, as Rousseau had already
pointed out, the “real” constitutional consensus is ‘‘not graven on
tablets of marble or brass, but on the hearts of the citizens.”53
53 J.-J.Rousseau, The
Social Contract, trans. G. D. H.Cole (London, 1993), Book 2, chapter
12. As Joseph Servan de Gerbey put it, “An imbecilic despot may be able
to constrain slaves with chains of iron; but a true politician binds
them more effectively with the chains of their own ideas . . . [T]he
soft matter of their brains is the firm basis of the mightiest Empires.”
My translation from the quote in L. Jerphagnon, Le divin Cesar;
Etude sur le pouvoir dans la Rome Imperiale (Paris; 1991), p. 1.
His problem was that citizens as such—being no more than artificial
persons defined by the legal and constitutional rules of society—have no
heart. Human beings do; hence, they must be cajoled into identifying as
perfectly as possible with the role of the citizen they are supposed to
perform. This was Rousseau’s substantial political point: either
politics is successful indoctrination of the ideology of citizenship or
it is no more than the usual clash of particular interests. That leaves
us with the question: “Who is supposed to do the engraving? Who should
supply the constitutional ideology?” Where there is no consensus on the
answer to these questions, the “real constitutional power” is probably
the most obstinately contested scarce resource in the political arena.
That is particularly true when the consensus is not the living soul of
a homogeneous local community but some presumed thing that must again
and again be discovered by the ritual of complex procedures of social
decision-making with unpredictable outcomes. As Jasay has argued, “It
is a strange supposition that politics goes on within constitutional
constraints, but that the constraints themselves are somehow above
politics, determining it without being determined by it like any other
product of collective decision-making.”54
54 Anthony de Jasay,
“The rule of forces, the force of rules,” in Anthony de Jasay,
Against Politics (London; 1997), p. 137.
Part 4: “Rational Choice” in the Convivial Order and in Political
Society
Which Game Shall We Play?
In a political society, individuals continually face the familiar
dilemma of “asking what I can do for my country” or “asking what my
country can do for me.” We may expect that the second alternative would
end up as the dominant strategy for most people. In a politically
developed society, filled to the brim with vote-seeking politicians,
pressure groups, lobbies, consumer advo-cates and consultants, that
expectation is eminently reasonable. The “good citizens” are sure to
get the “sucker’s payoff.” However, the outcome of almost everybody
trying to become a rent-seeker and a tax-consumer is likely to be what
Anthony de Jasay called “the churning society.”55
55 Anthony de Jasay,
The State.
The irony of this “game” is that unless there are people choosing the
second strategy the others will get no answer to the question, what they
can do for their country. The country asks nothing but what it is made
to ask by those who are in charge of its vocal organs. The obvious way
in which to interpret J. F. Kennedy’s call “Ask not what your country
can do for you, ask what you can do for your country” is “Don’t tell us
what to do, we’ll tell you.”
Do individuals prefer living in a country that asks nothing to living in
a churning society? If they do, political society puts them in a
classic prisoners’ dilemma. However, it is one that is likely to
maintain its character even if it is played an indefinite number of
times. Indeed, the benefits generated by those who do not ask what
their country can do for them often can be appropriated by those who are
continuously looking for new answers to that question. It is not part
of the game that the “good citizens” can securely accumulate the gains
(if any) from their public-spirited actions in any round. On the
contrary, those gains become part of the stakes in the next round. That
is why in politics the key players never tire of exhorting their less
sophisticated fellows to ever higher degrees of good citizenship.
Indeed, the “good citizen” must be thoroughly naive if he believes that
his politically active fellow citizens will leave him free to invest his
resources, which he did not spent on rent-seeking, and to walk away with
the payoff. The same is true if he believes that the politically active
citizens will solve the political prisoners’ dilemma by enforcing “good
citizen” behavior on themselves. Their role in public life is to
translate into policy what they and their clients ask their country to
do for them.
There is, then, a significant difference between prisoners’ dilemmas in
a convivial order and in a political society. In a convivial order, the
co-operative strategy in a game G that prima facie looks like a
prisoners’ dilemma usually has opportunity costs in the form of benefits
forgone by not participating in other games. The co-operative option
may imply making a contribution to the production of a particular
“public good.” However, making that contribution entails that fewer
resources are available for investment in the production of other goods,
be they private or public. On the other hand, the option of not
contributing to the public good that is at stake in G keeps those
resources available for other uses. When the benefits forgone are
entered, as they should be, in the calculation of the payoffs for
co-operative action, then G may turn out not to be a dilemma of any
kind. “Non-co-operation in G” often is a misnomer for co-operation in
any number of other games. Looking at G as if it were the only game in
town misses the point of living in a convivial order, where people
usually can choose which games they will play. It follows that there
may be far less prisoners’ dilemmas in a convivial order than the
literature suggests. It also follows that enforcing co-operation in a
game such as G, on the hypothesis that it is a prisoners’ dilemma, may
result in a significant loss of utility—even if the subjects are
indifferent between being coerced and being asked politely to
contribute. In a political society, on the other hand, the games of
politics are not optional. The benefits forgone by adopting the
“co-operative” strategy of asking what you can do for your country are
the benefits that come from asking what it can do for you. If such a
game looks like a prisoners’ dilemma, it does so because it probably is
one. Eventually, even the “good citizens” will become wise to the
realities of politics.
Of course, the standard application of the prisoners’ dilemma in
political theory is to prove that people in a convivial order cannot
solve the problem of the production of public goods. Anthony de Jasay
has done more to dispel that myth than anybody else has. Organized
societies, in particular political societies, produce their own
prisoners’ dilemmas. If the argument above is sound, they are of a more
perverse character than such dilemmas are likely to be in a convivial
order.
An Encounter in the Woods
Anthony de Jasay also has pointed out, pertinently, that we often have
reason to rejoice when some groups do not succeed in solving their
public goods problem either through “rational negotiation” or because
they understand the benefits of co-operation in an indefinitely repeated
prisoners’ dilemma super-game.56
56 Or because they are
“constrained maximisers,” as David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement
(Oxford, 1986) would have it. On the fallacy involved in that
“solution” of the prisoners’ dilemma, see Anthony de Jasay, Against
Politics, pp. 26-7. Michael Taylor, Anarchy and Cooperation
(New York; 1976) introduced the prisoners’ dilemma supergame. However,
it is a completely static analysis. Before the first round starts, each
player is supposed to choose a strategy that will determine his move in
every succeeding round (no matter what his circumstances may be in a
particular round, no matter which other “games” might come to his
attention in the mean time). That is perfect for playing computer
tournaments (Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Co-operation (New
York, 1984)), but not particularly illuminating for analysing the
historical existence of the species.
For themselves, rival gangs could probably reach a Pareto-superior
outcome, relative to the usual gang war, by co-operating in setting up
and maintaining a consensus-based syndicate or uniting into a single
commonwealth of gangsters. The question is, do we want them to succeed
and to become more efficient in looting us? Hobbes’s answer, of course,
was that we should want that commonwealth if we did not have it already.
That answer still carries enormous prestige, especially among those who
have substituted the sovereign legislative power of a democratic
republic for the original Hobbesian absolute monarch.
Underlying Hobbes’s answer, there is the assumption that if there might
be one real psychopath at loose in the world, the rational course for
every other person would be to act like a psychopath. After all, he
might be the next person coming up the road—so better beat him at his
own game by striking first. In any case, the next person coming up the
road is likely to think that you are that psychopath—and that again is
reason enough to strike him down first. If we pursue that kind of
reasoning, we get a good view of the sort of world Hobbes held to be
inevitable if there were no state, but also of what Leibniz referred to
as Hobbes’s fundamental fallacy.57
57 See note 18 above.
Let us simply ask, what will happen if two strangers, each of them
carrying a sword and some valuables, meet on a narrow path in the middle
of a dense forest? Put the question to a dozen novelists, and you will
get at least twelve different stories. However, when we put it to a
twentieth-century academic, he is likely to insist that the scene be
interpreted as a prisoners’ dilemma illustrating life in Hobbes’s
“Naturall Condition of Mankind.”
Table 5.1 Hobbesian encounters
A conventional representation of the scene as such a dilemma is given in
the table above. The Hobbesian thesis is that the men have no rational
option but to attack one another, given that there is no effective
police power to safeguard each traveler from an attack by the other.
For each of them, the dominant “strategy” is to attack the other, no
matter what the other’s intentions might be. A battle between them is
then the inevitable outcome—the equilibrium—solution of the
game-theoretical representation of their encounter. It is, of course, a
Pareto-inferior outcome relative to the outcome that would have resulted
if each of them had laid down his sword. That we are dealing with a
dilemma becomes clear once we note the assumed (and indeed reasonable)
preference orderings of the travellers:
Victory > Guaranteed Peace > Battle > Peace
Lest we think that this story has an unavoidably bloody outcome, we
should note that Hobbes himself pointed the way out of the
dilemma-indeed, out of the misery of the natural condition of mankind.
A “nice” bloodless solution is likely when one of the travelers
realizes in time that he is no match for the other, throws his weapons
down and offers to become the other’s faithful servant. He thereby puts
himself at the mercy of the stronger one, but then he has at least a
chance that the other accepts his offer and, being able to enforce his
will, agrees to let him live. Let us assume that the other does not
disappoint him. The scene ends with both of them walking away as a
small company, their forces united. The next man they meet sees that he
is no match for the two of them and joins their little band. Before
long, not only no solitary traveler but also no small company of
travelers will dare to resist the group. All will make haste to join
it, flattering its leader with the solemn declaration that they have no
trust in those that do not trust him. The virgin forest gives birth to
a sovereign and his state. The rest is politics and, as Hobbes would
have it, comfort, convenience, and commodious living for all.58
58 The same outcome
could be assured even when the parties are approximately equal in
strength prior to the battle. It is in the nature of combat that a
single blow can upset that balance and force one party to unconditional
surrender and submission (Hobbes, p. Part 2, chapter 20).
Let us return to our question, “What will the travelers do?” This time
we put it, say, to a seasoned trapper who has had many encounters with
strangers in the woods. “What normally happens when I run into a
stranger in the woods,” he answers, “is that we approach one another,
watching the other’s every move, holding one hand close to our weapon
but taking good care not to do anything provocative. In short, we are
on our guard. That’s how we survive.”
Each traveler now has three strategies: “Disarm,” “Be vigilant,” and
“Attack.” We must consider, therefore, nine possible combinations of
strategies. In addition to the four outcomes that we know already from
the Hobbesian interpretation, there are five new ones of three different
types. (1) One traveler is vigilant while the other disarms—the result
being that one is strong and the other weak. (2) One of them attacks
while the other remains vigilant—the encounter turns into a
confron-tation between an aggressor and a defender. (3) Both remain
vigilant, making as it were an armed peace as they walk by each other.
That is a far more complicated scheme than the Hobbesian one. We may
think of it as depicting encounters in the Lockean “state of nature”
where every person “hath a Right to punish the Offender, and be
Executioner ofthe Law ofNature.”59
59 John Locke, Second
Treatise of Government, Chapter II, par. 8, in fine. Locke s
state of nature was not a “state of war.” It was, arguably something
very close to the middle road of “Armed peace.”
Table 5.2 Lockean encounters
There is no obviously reasonable order of preference among the various
possible outcomes, even if we leave the preference ranking of the
outcomes of the first Hobbesian representation as they were. However,
there are preference rankings that do not affect the Hobbesian outcome.
For example, any ranking that satisfies the following conditions leaves
us with “Battle” as the equilibrium outcome:
Victory>Strength>Guaranteed peace
Aggression> Armed peace> Weakness
Battle> Defence> Defeat
Assuming, reasonably, that “Guaranteed peace” or even “Armed peace” is
preferred to “Battle,” the equilibrium-outcome is still
Pareto-inferior—no escape from the Hobbesian dilemma here! Note,
however, that it is not evidently reasonable to prefer being an
aggressor to enjoying an armed peace. Nor is it evidently reasonable to
prefer to rush into an open battle rather than to take a defensive
position and try to hold it.60
60 It might be rational
to act as an aggressor if there were some assurance that aggression
pays, but that it does is no law of nature. See Anthony de Jasay,
Against Politics, p. 199.
Let us suppose that the preference rankings satisfy the following
conditions
Victory>Strength>Guaranteed peace
Armed peace> Aggression> Weakness
Defence> Battle> Defeat
Then the equilibrium-outcome is “Armed peace” (exactly as the trapper
told us to expect). We still might have a dilemma if “Guaranteed peace”
is preferred to “Armed peace”—but that would be a dilemma of an entirely
different sort than the Hobbesian one. In fact, in the setting of our
story, there is no obvious reason to prefer “Guaranteed peace” to “Armed
peace” since the former involves losing one’s weapons. Thus, there are
no a priori reasons why “Armed peace” should be Pareto-inferior.
Hobbes, not one to let facts get in the way of theory, circumvented
this result by defining “Armed peace” to be a manifestation of war.61
61 See his definition of
war (quoted in the text to note 17above). Hobbes assumed that “Attack”
in any case dominates “Be vigilant”: “there is no way for any man to
secure himselfe, so reasonable, as Anticipation; that is . . . to master
the persons of all men he can” (Hobbes, Part I, chapter 13).
With no more to go on than one of his innovative definitions, Hobbes
made it appear as if life under an armed peace is just as “solitary,
poore, nasty, brutish and short” as it is in an actual war-zone. No
wonder Leibniz was unimpressed.62
62 Locke also was
unimpressed. Hobbes had maintained that only a fully assured peace is
not a state of war. However, he also had maintained that the pax
victoris that results from the unconditional submission of many to
one is really the only way to achieve a victoria pacis. However,
as Locke noted, the pax victoris need mean no more than the end
of actual fighting; in other respects, it still is war by another name.
Locke, for example chapter II, para. 137.
Of course, we should not attach too much weight to game-theoretical
models. “Modeling” the human world is a tricky business. Moreover,
models are cheap. With a little ingenuity we can make them produce any
desired result. In any case, real situations do not come with labels
like “This is a prisoners’ dilemma” attached to them. The mere fact
that one does not see people in a convivial order produce what one has
determined for oneself to be a public good, is no indication that those
people are trapped in such a dilemma. They may have other priorities.
What else can we expect in a world of endemic plurality, diversity and
scarcity?
References
Aristotle, Politics.
Axelrod, Robert, The Evolution of Co-operation (New York: Basic
Books, 1984).
Bruckberger, R-L., O.P., L‘Histoire de Jesus-Christ (Paris:
Editions Bernard Grasset, 1965).
Gauthier, David, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1986).
Havelock, Eric, The Liberal Temper in Greek Politics (New Haven,
1957).
Hayek, F. A., “The Confusion of Language in Political Thought,” in F. A.
Hayek, New Studies in Philoso-phy, Politics, Economics, and the
History of Ideas (London and Henley: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978).
Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan (London: Penguin, 1 968).
Huxley, Aldous, Brave New World (New York: Bantam Books, 1953).
Jasay, Anthony de, The State (1985; Indianapolis: Liberty Fund,
1999).
-----, “The rule of forces, the force of rules,” in Anthony de Jasay,
Against Politics (London: Routledge; 1997),p. 137.
-----, Against Politics (London and New York: Routledge, 1997).
-----, “Justice as something else,” in Jasay, Justice and Its
Surroundings (Indianapolis, Ind., 2002).
Jerphagnon, L., Le divin Cesar; Etude sur Ie pouvoir dans la Rome
imperiale (Paris: Tallandier, 1991).
Locke, John, Second Treatise of Government.
Oakeshott, Michael, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays
(London: Methuen, 1962).
Plato, Republic.
-----, The Laws.
Rothbard, Murray N., The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands,
NJ: Humanities Press, 1982).
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, Du Contrat Social, Book 1, chapter 1.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Social Contract, trans. G. D. H. Cole
(London: Everyman’s Library, 1993).
Taylor, Michael, Anarchy and Cooperation (New York: Wiley, 1976).
Van Dun, Frank,
“Natural Law, Liberalism, and Christian-ity,”
Journal of Libertarian Studies, 15/3 (Summer 200l):pp. 1-36.
-----,
“The Lawful and the Legal,”
Journal des economistes et des etudes humaines, 6/4 (1996):
555-79.
-----,
Personal Freedom versus Corporate Liberties
(Lon-don: Libertarian Alliance, 2006, Philoso-phical notes no. 76).
Voegelin, Eric, “The New Science of Politics,” in M. Henningsen, The
Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, vol. 5, Modernity without
Restraint (Columbia and London, 2000).
van Dun page