Statism and the State
A.
The Failure of Statism
It is time to
interrupt our visit to the city of statism. We certainly did not visit
every one of its houses and hovels; but we did stop at some of its
magnificent palaces. Everywhere we got the same message: neutrality is
not an objective of the state; on the contrary, the state’s ambition is,
or should be, to put an end to the metaphysical sickness of private
judgement, at least among its own personnel or with respect to all
politically sensitive actions, and ideally in all spheres of social
life. We know that Rousseau did not believe this ambition was worth
pursuing, except on those necessarily rare occasions, most of them in
the distant past, when all the conditions are favourable. We also know
that Plato was pessimistic about the chances that a wise ruler would
succeed in establishing a durable regime of loyal guardians contented
with an ascetic life of service.28
It seems to me that, before the nineteenth century, philosophical
statism was more often presented as an ideal solution that should guide
political reforms, but only if there was any chance of success;
however, as most of the time there is no chance of success, the counsel
of prudence is to shelve the statism and so stick to a conservative
programme of maintaining law and tradition.29
In retrospect,
and judged by its own criteria,30
the statist project has been a failure. The spectacular growth of the
state, especially since the last quarter of the nineteenth century, has
not been accompanied by the emergence of the sort of guardian of
society, citizen or New Man that Plato, Rousseau or Marx thought
necessary to legitimate the social chains of statehood. Instead we have
witnessed the emergence, acknowledged even by the social sciences, of
politicians, bureaucrats and rent-seekers. All the positions that
should have been occupied by dedicated, unselfish, even ascetic, civil
servants, are filled with precisely the sort of unreconstructed human
material the theory declared unfit for a well-ordered state.
The rhetoric of
guardianship and citizenship is still very much in evidence, especially
in the press and the other mass-media where it allows columnists to
produce “responsible comment” at low intellectual costs, and, of course,
in the schools. The rhetoric has a hollow ring: it provides a
convenient set of formulas for use in public discourse, but no one takes
it too seriously as a guide through the complexities of daily life.
Politicians, the masters of public discourse, appreciate it enormously.
If it is their mission, as guardians of the state, to recast the raw
human material in the mould of the citizen, they should not have any
scruples (other than those of electoral or financial expediency) about
using state power to make people behave. Most of the time, however,
when politicians use it, the rhetoric sounds like a pathetic complaint
about how “uncooperative” people are, especially when it comes to paying
taxes and complying with regulations. People never seem to get the idea
that a good citizen is really an unpaid civil servant. The citizens
themselves, mere human beings, also sing the praise of citizenship; only
to them it means no more than common decency. They think they behave
like a good citizen even as they move through life in almost complete
ignorance of or disregard for the multitude of regulations that apply to
them.
If we restrict
ourselves to the far less metaphysical theory of statism advanced by
Hobbes, the verdict of failure still stands. While the state is in a
sense more powerful than ever before, it is in control of very little.
Yet, effective control was the Hobbesian rationale for the
concentration of power in the hands of the state. The best we can say
is that an extraordinary amount of movement proceeds through the
sovereign. The sovereign should have been at the top of the
power-structure, occupying a place where everything comes together. In
reality hardly anything comes together.
Except for the,
in most cases, merely formal check at the time the budget is drawn up,
no procedure exists for co-ordinating policies. Interest-groups of
various colours and stripes are often successful in their attempts to
influence, even capture, political and administrative decision-making
processes. Dropping their specialists in every major party, they are
directly represented in parliament, in its committees, and often enough
in the cabinet. If they do not succeed in writing suitable regulations,
they still influence the implementation of policy. The name of the game
is getting the state to work for you at the expense of whoever happens
not to be watching. In Hobbesian terms, the war of all against all
continues to rage, except that it is now called “politics as usual.”
Why did philosophical statism fail when so many great minds have spent
so much energy in elaborating it? The easiest, and probably most
convincing, answer is that it built on the wrong foundations. In one
form or another the Hobbesian axiom, that war is the natural condition
of mankind, underlies all of the statist theories. There may be
reservations about whether this natural condition is also the original
condition, or whether mankind at some point became alienated from its
original nature, lost its innocence, and dissolved into a mass of
separate groups and individuals. Nevertheless, whether it postulates an
original long-lost unity or not, statism looks forward to unifying
society under a single rule of life. It aims at overcoming the
separateness of human persons and all it implies: independent
decision-making, diversity of opinion, rivalry, self-interest, and
ultimately all manifestations of individuality in social relations.
Statism is at
bottom a revolt against nature, a refusal to accept what to others is
simply an unalterable fact of nature. In this alternative view,
originally elaborated by the Sophists and other radical naturalist
philosophers of the fifth century BC, human beings survive in this very
real world by means of their social skills, their ability to instill
respect for the requirements of society by appeals to the sense of
honour and shame (aidoos) and by insisting on the need for
negotiations, arbitration and impartial judgement (dikè). That
is to say, people learn to develop rules and conventions for living
with and alongside one another, without sacrificing their
individuality. The secret of social order is accommodation, not unity.
Accommodation takes place in a horizontal plane, where people meet one
another, exchange goods and ideas, and then move on to other meetings,
other exchanges. Every meeting is a local and temporary affair,
preceded and followed and surrounded by countless other meetings
involving countless other people. Only memory and anticipation can
integrate these meetings into recurring flexible patterns of social
behaviour. There is no point above the horizontal plane of human action
from which everything can be seen in its totality, let alone controlled.
Unity, in contrast, presupposes a vertical dimension, it presupposes
just such a point above the plane from which everything, no matter when
or where, can be seen, comprehended, and controlled. As long as people
thought this point above the plane was reserved for the gods, it
symbolised man’s humility and fallibility in the face of an unobtainable
scientia divina. The pretence to rise above the plane of human
existence could only be interpreted as self-defeating hubris.
However, the metaphysical strands in Western philosophy as well as some
forms of religious mysticism taught man would not be complete unless he
attained that position. The knowledge of all things would then be his,
and as it is the same for all, it would unify mankind and end all strife
and rivalry. Statism, I submit, is but a translation of this teaching
into the language of action and power.
The failure of
statism leaves us with a state that embodies all that the statist
philosophy abhors.31
That state is not a unity made possible by an integration along a
vertical axis, because no such axis exists or can exist. Rather, the
state exists, like all human things, in the horizontal plane. The
appearance of verticality is illusory. What creates the illusion is the
psychological need to come to terms with the state’s ability to do with
complete legal impunity and as a matter of daily routine what would
immediately be stigmatised as criminal if a “private person” or
“ordinary citizen” were to attempt it. This ability is a direct affront
to the common principles of law. These have their origin in the
requirements of life in the horizontal plane. Consequently, there is no
way in which to look upon the state as part of a just order, other than
to suppose that it answers to a higher law (i.e., to an order of
existence which is not bound to the natural conditions of human
existence). On the other hand, if the state is viewed as part of life
in the horizontal plane, it appears as nothing more than a particular
organisation for satisfying human needs and desires. Far from
delivering mankind of the curse of private, and therefore incomplete and
unreliable judgement, it makes private judgement the source of “public
action.” Public action is action that is not bound by the common
principles of law. For the statist, such action would be proper only if
it issued from a “public judgement.” It does not.
B.
The Corrupted State
The
consequences are grave. The rise of the state has made it possible for
an ever increasing number of persons to accomplish their ends without
regard for law. The requirements of society count for very little in an
intellectual climate dominated by the belief that there is no such thing
as natural society. So all attention is diverted to the requirements of
particular societies (states), that is to say, to setting collective
goals and mobilising the means to attain them, regardless of law.
Leaving aside what the ideal but non-existent guardians, civil servants
or New Men would do with such a formidable tool, there is little doubt
that to ordinary people it is a standing invitation to try to put the
machinery of the state and its enormous “public powers” at the service
of their own interests. Who can afford to decline the invitation? Who
can afford to be left behind in the political rat-race?
Modern
apologists of the state like to invent one social dilemma after
another to vindicate their belief that people in society are impotent to
solve their problems of co-ordination and cooperation.32
The apologists think they have proven their case when all they have
demonstrated is that, if he were to exist, their fictional “mortal god”
would solve the problems. The real state, however, exists in the
horizontal plane and has no advantage except force. There is nothing
magical about this force: it is force supplied by people and used by
people against people in order to get what they want at the expense of
the less powerful. If the power grows to be effective, everybody will
want his piece of the action; but if everybody does, no one will like
the outcome. This is the “social dilemma” all over again, only this
time it does not prove the impotence of lawful society, but of the state
itself. It creates the very nightmare statism was designed to ward off.
The apologists are blind to fact that the mere existence of the state
multiplies and intensifies their vaunted social dilemmas.33
The process
generated by this political dilemma exhibits a perverse dynamic
of social destruction, a steady depreciation of the social skills.
Respect for law forces people to co-operate, to assume full
responsibility for their actions, to face the risks and costs their
decisions entail. The “need” for political power, on the other hand, is
never greater than when the objective is to get what one cannot get
lawfully. It is never greater than when the objective is to get out
from under one’s lawful obligations and to shift one’s responsibilities
onto unsuspecting others. The “legitimacy” of the use of state power
sanctions any “winning coalition,” no matter what it wants, as long as
it is smart enough to conjure up a “crisis.” Any crisis will do. The
perverse dynamic ensures that crises are never in short supply.
The political
merry-go-round never stops, it goes faster with every spin. Critics may
explain the “atomisation of society,” the emergence or re-emergence of a
“dual society,” by referring to the regulatory labyrinth of the welfare
state, its incomprehensible tax laws and catch-as-catch-can fiscal
policies, its jealously guarded monopolies over monetary and jural
institutions.34
They may point out that, when business finds itself between the anvil
of consumer choice and the hammer of discretionary regulatory and fiscal
powers, economic competition is bound to become ugly. However, rather
than face up to the realities of what Ludwig von Mises called “the
hampered market,” we are incited to complain that the hammer is not
heavy enough and pour money into smoke-screens such as “business
ethics.” Whatever message the critics send, the message received will
be interpreted as a call for new and vigorous political action by the
wise guardians of the state. Every critique of present conditions is
automatically translated into a call for more guardians and better
citizens. The axiom of statism, that left to itself society will
disintegrate, allows no other conclusion.35
Conclusion
Where do these
considerations lead us? The state, especially the welfare state, is not
neutral to personal moralities. There is no doubt about that. Should
the state be neutral to personal morality? A timid answer would be;
that it should if it could, but that, as it can’t, we should not
insist. However, we saw that a number of the greatest thinkers in the
statist tradition denied that there was any value in personal
moralities. They wanted the state to be a condition of life in which
the need for a personal morality would not arise—a condition in which
one will, one judgement, would direct all activity. While statism,
considered as a programme for state builders, has unquestionably failed,
the rhetoric of statism (and its corollary: citizenship) continues to be
a strong and intimidating force in public affairs. It is still used to
urge people to measure themselves and each other against the mirage of
the true guardian, the true citizen, the true Social Man.36
It is utterly naïve to expect neutrality from the state.37
So where do the
misgivings about a lack of neutrality come from? Neutrality, I argued,
is a characteristic of law. I also argued, that “law” and “state” stand
for completely different conceptions of human society. It seems
reasonable to conclude, therefore, that misgivings about the lack of
neutrality in the welfare state betray a deep sense of uneasiness about
the present form of organised lawlessness. If law is indeed the
requirement of social existence, that uneasiness is eminently justified.
Notes
1. The author
would like to thank Prof. Erik Schokkaert of the Catholic University at
Louvain who commented on the paper at the Hayek Symposium in Ghent
(March 17, 1995), and kindly made his comments available to him in
writing. Some of his comments as well as replies to them are included
in the notes.
2. This question
was the title of the second section of the Hayek Symposium (held at the
University of Ghent, March 17, 1995). Since I do not believe that the
question of moral neutrality arises only or in a special sense with
respect to the welfare state, I shall not pretend that it does.
3. The phrase “a
personal morality,” as used here, refers to a personal commitment to
some vision of what makes one’s life good and worthwhile, a code of
conduct, or a particular set of values. I make no a priori
assumptions about the sources of this commitment, nor about the
particular content of the morality in question. However, it is
necessary to assume that a personal morality does not require the person
holding it to [attempt to] force others to accept it. Erik Schokkaert
comments that he is “afraid that in this definition there is no room for
values of ideas about the basic institutions of society.” (On the
contrary, the definition leaves plenty of room for such views and plenty
of scope for voluntary institutions—or are we to understand that basic
institutions must be coercive?) Schokkaert continues: “conflicts
between private moralities are unavoidable . . . The whole point of
politics is to try to find agreement about these matters without
necessarily resorting to violence.” However, the point of the state is
that one solution should be forcibly imposed, even if there is no
agreement. Remarkably, Schokkaert then says that he does not “see [a]
problem with the introduction of, e.g., a collective insurance system,
if this would be unanimously accepted, i.e., is a Pareto-improvement in
my preferred jargon.” However, all insurance systems are collective,
even if they are not all coercively imposed. In a free market an
insurance scheme is unanimously accepted by all participants, and is
therefore likely to be a Pareto-improvement to them. That is not true
for an imposed system which permits one party [the government] to
unilaterally change the terms of insurance afterwards, and, more
importantly, to enforce a no exit clause (which no reasonable
person would accept in the first place, especially if he had any regard
for his children or the next generation).
4. The
contributions of professors Theeuwes, Naert and Habermann to the
Symposium deal with redistributive coalitions and rent-seeking in a more
direct manner.
5. John Locke,
Two Treatises of Government, II, Chapter 2, paragraph 4. Locke
explains what he means by “the bounds of the Law of Nature” in paragraph
6 of the same chapter. His “Law of Nature” is an amalgam of
naturalistic and theological ideas. Locke’s naturalism refers to the
natural fact of the separateness of persons, all of whom are equally
human (“furnished with like Faculties”). The Law of Nature requires men
to recognize this fact and to accept its implications: “being all equal
and independent, no one ought to harm another in his Life, Health,
Liberty, or Possessions,” “[no one may] unless it be to do Justice on an
Offender, take away, impair the life, or what tends to the Preservation
of the Life, the Liberty, Health, Limb or Goods of another.” His
theology supports the other part of the Law of Nature: “[Man] has not
Liberty to destroy himself, or much as any Creature in his Possession,
but where some nobler use, than its bare Preservation calls for “Every
one is bound to preserve himself, and not to quit his Station wilfully;
so by the like reason when his own Preservation comes not in
competition, ought he, as much as he can, to preserve the rest of
Mankind. This part of the Law of Nature refers to God’s proprietary
rights as Creator or Maker of the natural world and of every human being
in it. Locke recognised that natural law, be it ever so evident in its
principles, has to be applied and enforced under conditions where its
implications may not be clear. His naturalism led him to leave these
problems to the practical social skills of people in finding mutually
acceptable solutions; his theology led him to entrust them to a worldly,
yet “sacred,” institution: the state. The state should ensure that
people continue to serve God, even when they have no direct interest in
doing so.
6. The term
“liberalism” can be applied to a wide variety of ideas. I shall use it
only to refer to what in the Anglo-American literature is usually called
“Classical Liberalism.” Some of Locke belongs to that tradition, and,
so does some of Hayek. Following Eric Havelock (The Liberal Temper
in Greek Politics, London: Jonathan Cape, 1957), Karl Popper (The
Open Society and Its Enemies, Part I, London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, many editions), and others, I think (but shall not argue here)
that it can be traced back to the Sophists’ naturalistic and historical
teachings on human society. I shall use a stricter conception of
liberalism than that of most classical liberals to highlight the
contrast with the philosophy of statism discussed later on in the text.
7. On the
terminological and conceptual issues discussed in this paragraph, see
Frank van Dun (1995),
“The Lawful and the Legal,” in VI (4) Journal des
économistes et des études humaines, pp. 555-579.
8. Examples are
societies for the Protection of Animals, for the Advancement of the
Arts and Sciences, The Society of Friends, and such like, business
corporations (sociétés anonymes), but also
nation-states. All of these need a well-specified criterion for
distinguishing members from non-members, for the purpose of collecting
dues and allocating tasks as well as for the purpose of distributing
income within the society.
9. Cf. open
society (Popper), great society (Hayek), general society.
In Dutch there is a clear distinction between “maatschappij” (company,
exclusive society) and “samenleving” (inclusive society). Law, as I use
the term, belongs to inclusive society (“samenleving”), which is not
a membership organisation; everybody who lives according to law is, by
that fact alone, in society. One who does not, is by that fact alone an
outlaw. Note that there is no sense in supposing inclusive society to
be unlawful; on the other hand, societies-as-companies can be, and often
are, unlawful in many respects. In this paper “society” refers to
inclusive society unless another sense is specified by an explicit
qualification.
10. This concept
of natural law belongs to a naturalistic philosophy; it should not be
pressed into the service of some grand metaphysical or theological
scheme.
11. Because of the
diversity of human characters and external conditions, and because life
is nothing apart from the experience of living, abstract theorising
about the content of “personal morality” is mostly barren. It may be
possible to identify some intrinsic goods on the basis of a general
consideration of human nature, but any proposition about their relative
values or priorities in particular circumstances is extremely
speculative.
12. Jeffrey
Friedman, “Accounting for Political Preferences,” in Critical Review,
volume V, number 3, 327. For a more extensive criticism of Friedman’s
argument, see Frank van Dun,
“Hayek and Natural Law: The Humean
Connection,” in J. Birner & R. van Zijp (eds), Hayek: Coordination
and Evolution. His Legacy in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the
History of Ideas. London, Routledge and Keegan Paul, 1994, 269-286.
13. See Frank van
Dun (1995),
“The Lawful and the Legal,” in VI (4) Journal des
économistes et des études humaines, pp. 555-579. “Lex”
appears to be originally a military term; it is related to “dilectus,”
which refers to the act of calling people to arms or drafting them into
an army. Hence the general meaning: general command given by the
highest authority. There is no connection with “law” (order).
14. Of course, it
may depend on meta-moral reasoning, but the argument was not that
liberal neutrality is a myth because it is the conclusion of a
particular sort of non-moral argument, namely a meta-moral argument.
15. John Locke,
The Second Treatise of Government, Chapter VIII, paragraphs 119 sqq,
tried to present this unlikely event as required by the logic of social
contracting: “[E]very Man, when he . . . incorporates himself into any
Commonwealth, he . . . annexed also, and submits to the Community those
Possessions, which he has, or shall acquire, that do not already belong
to any other Government” (§ 120). Actually, these paragraphs contain
some of Locke’s most absolutistic utterings: “[The obligation to obey
the laws of the government] reaches as far as the very being of anyone
within the Territories of that Government” (§ 119): “[H]e, that has once
. . . given his Consent to be of any Commonweal, is perpetually and
indispensably obliged to be and remain unalterably a Subject to it, and
can never be again in the liberty of the state of Nature (§120). To
appreciate the illiberality of these statements, just substitute “woman”
for “man,” “holy matrimony” for “commonwealth,” and “husband” for
“government.”
16. Not many
people appear to have accepted Robert Nozick’s all too complex and
convoluted attempt, in Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1972) to
provide what he called an “invisible hand” explanation of the lawful
genesis of the state.
17. As it was
defended by Robert Filmer in his Patriarcha (1675), the target of
Locke’s First Treatise.
18. I take the
word “war” in its broad original sense of confusion, disorder
(as, in Dutch, ver-war-ring).
19. Or perhaps:
her—in Jewish mythology Leviathan was often depicted as a female monster
that ruled the seas and that would ultimately defeat Behemoth, the male
monster that ruled the land. In the book of Job, where Hobbes
probably got the idea of using “Leviathan” as a metaphor for the state,
Leviathan is a male creature of which it is said that “When he raiseth
up himself, the mighty are afraid . . . He maketh a path to shine after
him . . . Upon earth there is not his like, who is made without fear.
He beholdeth all high things; he is king over all the children of
pride.” (41:25-43) Thus, “Leviathan” stands for all that is awesome,
fearless and invincible, like a mythological warrior, or as Hobbes put
it, “a mortal god.”
20. Among the
“Diseases of a Commonwealth, as are of the greatest, and most present
danger,” “the poyson of the seditious doctrine . . . That every
private man is Judge of Good and Evil Actions” ranks second,
immediately after the king’s want of absolute power. “Another doctrine
repugnant to Civil Society, is, that whatsoever a man does against
his Conscience is Sinne; and it dependeth on the presumption of
making himself judge of Good and Evil.” (Leviathan, Chapter 29).
21. Richard Tuck’s
Philosophy and Government (Oxford 1994) extensively discusses the
intellectual background of the “revolution” in political thought brought
about by Grotius and Hobbes.
22. In an age when
Cartesian dualism was an increasingly influential philosophical
paradigm, the idea that the “divine” element, the mind or the soul,
exists in a realm apart from the lowly body and material nature, the
dissociation of action and judgement could easily appear to be
uncontroversial.
23. And also,
Plato adds, a war of each against himself: people are likely to adopt
ever more unhealthy lifestyles.
24. The Nocturnal
Council appears in Plato’s last work, The Laws. The
Philosopher-King is the linchpin of “the city constructed in speech” in
The Republic.
25. This is one of
the main dividing lines between marxism and liberalism (or even
libertarian socialism: e.g. Franz Oppenheimer’s comments on Marx, in his
The State (1975 [1914], p. 12). For natural law liberalism, the
basic distinction is between lawful and unlawful action (which
corresponds to Oppenheimer’s distinction between economic and political
methods of purposive action). Unfortunately, most economists have come
to believe that the distinction between lawful and unlawful should be
made on “economic” grounds (utility, efficiency). This is most clearly
the case with the adherents of the Law and Economics movement and the
Property Rights school (see the critique by W. Block, “Ethics,
Efficiency, Coasian Property Rights, and Psychic Income: A Reply to
Harold Demsetz,” The Review of Austrian of Economics, 1995, VIII,
2, 61-125, and the literature cited therein), but also of mainstream
public policy analysts (cf. note 38 below).
26. This vision of
Rousseau’s citizen as a model for the New Communist Man concludes part
one of Marx’s revealing essay on emancipation, On the Jewish Question
(1844).
27. Marx’s
extension of citizenship to all social activities set the stage for the
totalitarian and utopian project of remaking mankind, of recasting the
raw human material in the mould of the New Man. According to the logic
of the theory, state and society would then coincide. When everyone has
absorbed the requirements of citizenship, there is no or only a marginal
need for a coercive institution. Most of the totalitarian projects
inspired by Marx have now collapsed under the weight of their own
inefficiencies. Other projects have attempted to create a new class of
guardians, mainly by appealing to racist and nationalistic sentiments.
Most of these too have collapsed or spent themselves in bloody wars.
However, we need not go into this aspect of the history of the
twentieth century.
28. It is true
that Plato, like Rousseau occasionally went into the business of
political consulting, but what advice he gave his “clients” is not very
clear. We do know, however, that Rousseau, as a political consultant,
took care to advise against using Du Contrat Social as a
revolutionary’s handbook.
29. Hobbes does
not fit this interpretation, but he was more concerned with maintaining
an absolutist state than with getting one off the ground.
30. I was somewhat
surprised to hear Erik Schokkaert object to my “enumeration of
undesirable consequences [of statism]” on the ground that
“consequentialism is in direct conflict with [Van Dun’s natural law]
position.” However, a “natural law position” does not condemn looking
into the consequences of actions, even it will not accept that a
particular person’s (or profession’s) valuation of an action’s
consequences may be sufficient to permit that action to be executed if
it is not to be allowed on account of its unlawful character. Moreover,
it should be clear that I am discussing consequences that most of the
adherents of statism have themselves claimed to be undesirable, and, in
fact, were precisely the symptoms of the disease they thought statism
would cure. Besides, I hope it will be granted that it is not improper
for me to comment on the undesirability of systems of action and thought
that do not take the distinction between the lawful and the unlawful
into account. Even more surprising was Schokkaert’s comment that “[Van
Dun] never makes explicit in what terms consequences should be
evaluated. This gives his description a very moralising tinge.” This
is surprising, because I believe that individuals (whether economists or
not) “evaluate consequences” in whatever way they deem appropriate. As
a philosopher of law, I am not concerned with how people evaluate
alternative courses of action, but with what they do [to others] after
they have come to a conclusion.
31. As Rousseau
wrote in his essay Sur l’economie politique (“On Political
Economy”) for the Encyclopedie: “We may say that a government
has reached the ultimate stage of corruption when it has no other link
to the people than money. But every government always tends to become
lax, and that is sufficient proof that no government will subsist unless
it continually seeks to increase the revenue.”
32. Top billing
goes to the famous Prisoner’s Dilemma that has been studied and
discussed ad nauseam by social scientists and psychologists for
the past fifty years or so. Few appreciate the irony that the situation
that gave the dilemma its name was concocted by a state official to
trick two hapless prisoners into an extended stay in jail.
33. In his
comments Erik Schokkaert noted that “prisoner’s dilemma-type of
argumentations seem to upset Van Dun so much.” He finds this
surprising, “since recent developments in the theory of repeated games
show that in many cases the cooperative solution can be reached without
outside intervention, and I would suppose Van Dun would be quite happy
with that conclusion.” However, PD-type of argumentations as such do
not upset me at all; what does upset me is the clear bias (in the
economic literature, especially textbooks) in presenting them almost
exclusively as analyses of “market failures” and grounds for “government
intervention.” As for the theory of repeated games—Schokkaert
presumably refers to the work of Anatol Rapopport, Michael Taylor,
Robert Axelrod, and others, I am happy with cooperative outcomes
where lawful activities are concerned. But I must confess that I
find no reason to rejoice in the prospect of a cooperative outcome when
the repeated game is, say, between rival gangs attempting to control a
city—even if the outcome, is ex post facto called “the city
government.”
34. Professor
Schokkaert’s views on the welfare state are somewhat perplexing: on the
one hand, “[it] has to be reformed quite urgently; . . . [it] is too
redistributive, and therefore has lost the support of large groups; . .
. many [of its] regulations, are unnecessary and dismantling them would
lead to a far better society”; on the other hand, “I do like very much
the basic inspiration behind it.” Unfortunately, he does not tell us
what that basic inspiration is. However, he does tell us, that “theory
(and empirical reality) show us that private insurance is impossible or
will be extremely incomplete for risks related to unemployment and to
health,” because the textbook conditions for private
insurance—independent risks, approximate information symmetry, and
control of moral hazard—are not satisfied. “Introducing a collective
insurance system is then Pareto-improving.” Really? Always? Any
collective insurance system? How do we know this is a fact of
“empirical reality,” given that such a system is likely to crowd out,
even suppress, any private alternative with which it might be compared?
Is it superior to private charity? Is it superior to a world with low
or no taxes that depress economic activity, a world without banking laws
and monetary institutions that induce inflation and boom and bust
cycles? Is not moral hazard much more of a problem with “collective”
insurance than with private insurance? How about the moral hazards
affecting the managers of the system-playing politics with social
security, et cetera? And what about information asymmetry in
“collective” insurance systems, which (as theory and empirical reality
show) tend to be captured by well-organised, well-informed groups, and
to end up in such desperate financial straits that politically imposed
“adverse selection” in some guise or other soon becomes an enlightened
policy option?
35. At present
many statist intellectuals prefer to locate their imaginary Olympus in
the palaces of international and supranational organisations rather than
in the centres of the somewhat worn-out nation states. They are still
looking out for a relatively inaccessible sphere where the guardians can
rule serenely without being reminded at all times where their power
comes from and on what conditions they can keep it.
36. Professor
Schokkaert: “I do not know any economist who could [identify with the
statist position as it is described by Van Dun]. I think that what he
describes is a straw man that can easily be defeated afterwards.” But
this remark misses the point. Yes, statism is a straw man, in the sense
that few people (other than the statist philosophers who, as
philosophers, are willing to follow the argument wherever it may lead)
accept all of its implications in toto; nevertheless statism
continues to supply arguments that can be used in an ad hoc
fashion, either to defend particular state actions and policies, or to
ridicule pleas to strengthen the institutions of law and justice.
Amazingly, Schokkaert then goes on to demonstrate this very point.
Repeatedly he stresses that “the answer [to the question of the
desirability of state intervention] depends on a careful analysis of the
consequences of state intervention in specific circumstances and for
specific cases.” I shall not comment on the claim of economists to be
able to “analyse consequences” of an as yet unperformed act of state
intervention in “specific circumstances and for specific cases” (which
are uncertain, because they are by no means guaranteed to remain stable
in the [near or not so near] future, or to resemble past cases in all
the relevant respects)—Schokkaert appears to agree that the empirical
(necessarily historical) data are hardly ever “conclusive.” Rather more
pertinent is the fact that, unless we have a Platonic Economist-King,
the economists can only submit their speculative “answers” concerning
the desirability of state intervention in specific circumstances and for
specific cases to the rulers. But the question as it exists in the mind
of a ruler is probably not: “Is intervention in this case better
[in some unspecifiable “scientific” way] than non-intervention?” The
question is likely to be: “Is it in my interest to intervene here
and now in this way rather that that, or is it in my interest not
to intervene right now?” or “Which ‘analysis of the consequences’ should
I buy?” Even more to the point Schokkaert seems to suppose, that the
decision, whether to intervene or not, should depend only on his
“careful analyses”—but does this not mean, that in principle the state
should be able to intervene whenever, wherever and howsoever its
[economists] wisdom suggests? Is this not full-fledged statism as
defined in this paper?
37. It might be
objected that at a deeper level the state is neutral. The argument
might be that the state can be captured by any private interest or
combination of private interests—that it is not inherently biased with
respect to any private morality. This argument implies that the state
is merely a form of action and does not specify any particular end or
value. In its popular form the argument is that state power can be used
for good as well as bad purposes. Nevertheless, the argument fails,
because, whether its purpose is “good” or “bad,” state action still
embodies the particular judgement that the end justifies the means,
i.e., the judgement that law should not hinder the powerful from
reaching their ends, if necessary by coercive means.
Return to:
Introduction
Posted November 8, 2007
van Dun page