My only excuse for posting this paper from my stu-dent days, in spite of
its flabby style, is that I still struggle with the fact and meaning of
philosophical plurality. I am willing to push past the pain that
its sentences induce to see whether the questions it raises, however
inelegantly, are still worth raising forty years after I began to take
philosophy serious-ly.
The course, held at the New School for Social Research, was “Hegel and
the History of Philosophy,”
the teacher the late Albert Hofstadter, and the date of submission
January 19, 1978.
For more mature
reflections on this topic, please see
Joseph Owens’
Aquinas and Philosophical Pluralism
and
Jacques Maritain’s
Can Philosophers Cooperate?
on this site.
Anthony Flood
March 27, 2010
Philosophic Diversity and Skeptical
Possibility: A Confrontation with Hegel
Anthony Flood
How
can philosophers persist in their inquiries in the face of both
historical displacement of one philosophical position by another and the
diversity of philosophical positions at any present moment? Surely they
recognize the probability that their hard work will not receive general
approval from their colleagues or from future philosophers, who may look
back upon the work and judge it, if they notice it at all, more as a
cultural artifact than a piece of reasoning. Yet philosophers fervently
believe in the intrinsic rationality of their diverse—to understate
things—efforts. I submit that diversity of philosophic position, and
ultimately of all “rational opinion,” is unsettling to the belief in
universal reason, the presupposition of all philosophical undertaking,
and consequently in objective truth. One philosopher, Hegel, offered a
very suggestive, but I believe ultimately flawed, solution to the
problem of philo-sophic diversity, viz., that such diversity is
constitu-tive of the very development of Philosophy in History. Hence a
discussion of Hegel’s attempted solution balances my generally skeptical
essay. Some of the consequences I believe follow from a failure to solve
the diversity problem will conclude this paper.
As
with all problems that pose the threat of skep-ticism, the present one
ensnares the very philosopher who tries to lay the issue on the table,
such as the present writer. This danger of self-implication seems to me
to be a major reason why most philosophers dismiss the question of
skep-ticism, as if it were merely on the order of philosophic
“interest,” or treat it only historically, i.e., as an intellectual and
cultural oddity that occasionally raises its head to distract serious
philosophers from their productive work. But it must be stressed here
circumscribed epistemological position which is derived from a certain
analysis of the concept of knowledge.1 The skepticism here
considered is rather a kind of “frustrated consciousness,” a attitude
conceded after a survey of the staggeringly varied terrain of
philosophy, whereupon one questions the very meaningfulness of taking
another step in one direction rather than another. It is a skepticism
which turns the very belief in philosophy against itself. It is on the
order of the kind of skepticism toward common opinion that leads one to
philosophy in the first place.
I do
not deny that serious philosophical work is being conducted in all
branches of the field, work which, when grappled with, compels assent or
inspires constructive criticism. I could not list all the thinkers who
have convinced me through their work that philosophical inquiry is not
only worthwhile, but even indispensible to the rational conduct of all
human affairs, scientific, political, and cultural. But what is my
“conviction” worth? These latter endeavors may often be rightfully
criticized by philosophers for not giving sufficient attention to the
ontological and epistemological presuppositions of their work. But who
are philosophers to criticize when their own field gathers under its
umbrella a staggering multiplicity of intensely rational,
self-consciously justifiable activities whose authors are at loggerheads
over the very meaning of the rubric which wins their devotion, not to
mention the substantive issues which divide them?
Few
philosophers are bold enough to express their doubts when they ponder
this embarrassing but stubborn fact, assuming they are alive to it (and
I assume that most philosophers of many years’ engagement are even more
attuned to this issue and the pertinent data than I). Professor Charles
F. Bigger is one of the few, and he opens his essay of Platonic
philosophy with a scathing remark about the absence of agreement within
the profession over such a foundational figure as Plato, which “positive
scandal” compels him to offer the following generalization:
Philosophers seem to agree on nothing, not even on what philosophy is;
and yet they insist on teaching it and inform entire curricula, perhaps
even historic epochs, with their confusion. They prate of unity and
order and everywhere produce chaos. Perhaps Socrates’ fate was
ironically a measure of the integrity of the Athenean polis, and the
prevalence of philosophers today a condemnation of our own.2
Is
such harshness justified? Certainly Professor Bigger’s book, from which
I believe I benefited, has only added to the existing “confusion” unless
there is unanimity of positive appraisal of his interpretation of
Plato. Professor John Wisdom, in a book which examines philosophic
diversity without underscoring the skeptical possibility which I believe
lurks beneath his subject matter’s rational veneer, tells his students
that
. .
. for every philosophical statement I make or subscribe to, I can name a
highly distinguished, intelligent and competent philosopher within a few
hours’ distance who would think it false and perhaps even stupid.3
Add
to the list of Professor Wisdom’s critics the philo-sophers he cannot
name, and consider that there is a similar list for every other
philosopher, and that every philosopher is, at least potentially, some
other philosopher’s critic, and perhaps some sense of skeptical
possibility emerges.
That
this negative circumstance obtains, I believe there is general
agreement. Philosophers tend to manifest their recognition of this
otherwise unnerving state of affairs by good-naturedly conveying the
sentiment that, “Of course, I could be wrong.” (Even Professor
Bigger, midway in his attempt to undo the “positive scandal” in Platonic
studies, admits that access to Plato’s “real view” of time, pertinent to
an accurate account of participation, is probably impossible and hence
all we may hope for is “interesting error” in the remainder of his book.4)
Such an attitude betrays an epistemological relativism that, I hold, no
philosopher can consciously accept and continues his work. For every
philosopher—and this assumption is central to my argument—must presume
that when he or she is engaging in philosophical inquiry
and exposition, he or she is pursuing some universal and accessible
truth and that this pursuit is not necessarily bound to failure
(granting that it may fail in a particular attempt). But—and this is my
central claim—if the state of affairs described in the preceding
paragraph obtains, then the possibility of a successful pursuit of
truth, assumed by all philosophers, can only be formally assented to,
but never concretely grasped. And this is more a “positive scandal” for
philosophers to suffer than is any discord in Platonic studies. Before
turning to the philosopher who offered a solution that commands
attention in the absence of more satisfactory and less demanding ones, I
would like to elaborate upon my “existence postulate,” my assumption,
and my skeptical claim.
“Existence Postulate.”
If we consider nominalism and realism; materialism and idealism;
metaphysics and linguistic analysis; and all attempted syntheses of
these antithetical conceptions, we may note that each of these positions
has some difficulty that can be exploited by some interested thinker.
Even within any of these “schools” or traditions there is dis-agreement
over interpretation. One of the unfor-tunate consequences of this
diversity of views and interpretations is that we learn to appreciate
philosophers by the lights of any number of criteria—historical,
sociological, psychological, ideological—other than the one by which
they must be judged: their agreement with the truth (more on this in the
following paragraph). In other words, for any philo-sophic position,
however forcefully argued for, by however “distinguished, intelligent
and competent,” and perhaps even influential a thinker, there exist
thinkers who, upon considering the position and the arguments, are
inclined to and capable of reducing that position to problematic status,
if not of “de-molishing” it. This obtains across philosophic periods as
well as within such a period. This is the essence of philosophic
diversity, which may indicate that the conditions of free inquiry
obtain, but also indicates that the results of such inquiry never lead
to the universal recognition of the truth. (This is, of course, not to
be taken as an argument against free inquiry or for enforced dogmatism;
such conditions only underscore the present difficulty.) Every
philosophic effort, including this paper and responses to it, is a
thread in the fabric of diversity. Therefore, even disagreement with
this paper, while not proving its thesis, unavoidably corroborates it.
Assumption.
Every philosopher, from the miserly skeptic to the ambitious
metaphysician, attempts to say what is the case, whatever that may be,
and however little he can say about it; in a word, he seeks truth. To
refute a philosopher is to say that what he or she says is false, that
his or her attempt to get at the truth has failed. No philosopher can
be indifferent to such a judgement. Now while I expect disagreement
over my definition of truth (in cor-roboration of my existence
postulate, of course), I can only hope that it is acceptable for the
purposes at hand. In other words, even if two philosophers cannot agree
on a definition of truth, the work of every philosopher presupposes some
notion of it and evinces a drive to get at it and express it. I would
challenge a philosopher to show that his philo-sophical endeavors do not
in any way consist in an attempt to get at the truth of something.
Claim.
If there is but one totality of states of affairs to be known and
explained, i.e., one ultimate Truth, and if it is the job of philosophy
to explicate that Truth, but if it is also the case that
philosophers never reach agreement as to what Truth is, or even what its
formal definition is, then philosophy has been, is, and forseeably will
be a failure on its own terms, an interesting cultural phenomenon at
best, a standing historical joke of great pretense at worst. There may
be objective Truth, and pursuing it may be man’s noblest venture. But
if individual claims of success in its pursuit are perennially met with
damaging criticism and even derision from other philosophers whose own
claims are met with the same, then persistence in philosophy in the face
of such a situation indicates a dogmatism incompatible with the
philosopher’s claim to objective, reasonable thought. The dogmatism
either takes the form of conceit in the superiority of one’s own
philosophical efforts such that those who disagree must of necessity be
blind, incompetent, or under the spell of some allegedly discredited
tradition (in other words, diversity implies error—someone else’s); or
it takes the more common form of annoyance with any critical effort that
tends to call into question the very activity of philosophizing itself.
These words may be harsh, but unless the problem of genuine philosophic
diversity is seriously addressed and successfully handled, the chances
that those whom we refer to as philosophers are doing philosophy is
slim: the probability is that they are rather doing the history of ideas
or semantic-logical analysis, or achieving edification and other
personal satisfactions—anything but elaborating a science of Truth.
Before proceeding with an examination of Hegel’s view of philosophy, I
would like to make my purpose clear. While Hegel may be the greatest of
the philosophers who have consciously dealt with the problem of
diversity, the use of Hegel here is strictly illustrative. Any error
Hegel may have committed in any other aspect of his philosophy is a
separate question. For my purpose, the philosophical acceptability of
Hegel’s thought as a whole becomes a question when and if one has first
decided to opt for Hegel’s solution to the diversity problem. If one
has so decided, one may then accept Hegel whole, modify him slightly or
drastically or some measure in between, or reject Hegel’s own philosophy
of Spirit and replace it with one’s own, thereby sharing with Hegel only
the generalities of a solution to the diversity problem. Of course, the
possibility remains that even as a type of solution, Hegel’s
attempt fails.
Philosophy is, for Hegel, the highest realization of Spirit, which is
the actualization of the Absolute Idea or Truth, which in turn is the
systematic totality of all thought determinations. Thought is Hegel’s
Absolute, his definition of Being, which, in order to be Absolute or
unlimited, must externalize itself as nature and then, with the
appearance of man, as Spirit. The Idea is Spirit in itself (an sich),
or potentially; Spirit is the Idea for itself (fur sich), or
actually, concretely. The fullest expression of Spirit, Absolute
Spirit, through which man attempts to relate consciously to all there
is, comprises Art, Religion, and Philosophy. Philosophy specifically is
the attempt to grasp the totality of what-is in thought. The highest
form of this spiritual activity is the philosophy which expresses itself
as the actuality of self-thinking thought, namely, Hegel’s own
philosophy. The Absolute thus relates itself to itself through
philosophy. Prior to philosophy’s having achieved this perfection, its
story, and Spirit’s, is incomplete.
Human history, the medium within which this perfection or actualization
occurs, is thus a diachronic show of a timeless logos whose
telos is absolute philosophy. As Hegel expounds it in his
Lectures on the Philosophy of History5: “. . . the
History of the World with all the changing scenes which its annals
present, is this process of the development and the realization of
Spirit . . . .” (457) Philosophy, as the meaning which can only come at
the end of the story, “concerns itself only with the glory of the Idea
mirroring itself in the History of the World.” (457) Freedom, the state
of having over-come all externalization, the achievement of autonomy, is
the sole truth of Spirit. (7) Philosophy is the expression of this
truth. Spirit’s consciousness of its own absolute, autonomous, free
nature—which self-consciousness can only find its way in philosophy—is
the “destiny of the spiritual world and . . . the final cause of the
world at large. . . .” (19)
What
Hegel has to say about philosophy, it should be stressed, is not
relevant only to his own philosophy. He is not saying that when he
alone is doing philosophy, he alone is doing the work of Spirit while
his colleagues serve different ends. There is but one Absolute Idea or
Truth striving to get itself expressed in order to be actually what it
is potentially, i.e., in order to be free. The succession of human
philosophic attempts in time are only stages of this one great effort.
Hegel writes:
The
history we have before us [i.e., the history of Philosophy—A.F.]
is the history of thought finding itself, and it is the case with
Thought that it only finds itself in producing itself. The productions
are the philosophic systems; and the series of discoveries on which
Thought sets out in order to discover itself, forms a work which
has lasted twenty-five hundred years.6
The
history of philosophy, the highest vantage point from which to view
human history in general, is a development of a single subject,
Philosophy, from its barest abstractions in Thales to its full
concretiza-tion, Hegel modestly suggests, in his own system. Hegel is
thus claiming to consummate a single development, not set himself apart
from others who have devoted themselves to Philosophy have done. The
procession of “noble minds, [the] gallery of heroes of thought,” which
is the history of Philosophy, have “by the power of Reason, . . .
penetrated into the being of things, of nature and of spirit, into the
Being of God, and have won for us by their labors the highest treasure,
the treasure of reasoned knowledge.” (1)
Begging forgiveness for the necessarily rushed quality of the above
exposition, I will now present Hegel’s words on our specific topic,
philosophic diversity. Where others see a battlefield, Hegel saw a
developing quasi-organic unity, replete with the nearly destructive
internal conflicts that beset all living developments. Philosophy, in
order to develop, must put itself forward in the form of particular
positions. As particular positions, incapable of encompassing the
Absolute Truth, they must be overcome; but they can only be overcome
through philosophical opposition, which itself takes the form of
particular positions. Thus what appears irrational—the accumulation and
conflict or irrecon-cilable positions—is actually the very work of
Reason itself. The view that diversity in Philosophy’s history argues
for skepticism is treated as merely one of the “reflections most likely
to occur in one’s first crude thoughts” on the subject. (11)
Another such “crude thought,” related imme-diately to our topic and in
conflict with the assump-tion of this paper’s argument, is that the
history of Philosophy merely represents “various opinions in array,” and
what “can be more useless than to learn a string of bald opinions, and
what more unim-portant?” (12) Mere opinion is the worst
characterization of a philosophy. For “Philosophy is the objective
science of truth, it is the science of necessity, conceiving knowledge,
and [is] neither opinion nor the spinning out of opinions.” (12)
Opinion is only “a subjective conception, an uncontrolled thought, an
idea which may occur to me in one direction or in another: an opinion is
mine [Meinung ist mein].” (12) The “Platonic opposition between
opinion (doxa) and Science (episteme)” (14) must be
maintained, because otherwise truth disappears as unknowable. While
this latter conclusion may still be possible, and may be defended by
conscious skeptics,7 we must remember whom Hegel is
criticizing here, viz., philosophic novices and historians of philosophy
alike, who carelessly commit the above error and thereby vitiate their
efforts.
Of
course, the skeptical position is still a possibility. It is quite
possible that all that is the case in the history of Philosophy is that
“each opinion asserts falsely in its turn that it has found the truth.”
(15) How to choose from “such manifold opinions and philosophic systems
so numerous”? (15) And if the “greatest minds,” Hegel’s among them, we
might note, have erred, what hope do I have in producing an
“objective science of truth”? (16) This Hegel treats with utmost
seriousness, because Hegel does not want philosophers to choose between
dogmatic acceptance of his own philosophy and skeptical rejection of
Philosophy on account of its manifest diversity. For while not
sufficient for philosophic achievement, “personal conviction is the
ultimate and absolute essential which reason and its philosophy, from a
subjective point of view, demand in knowledge.” (14) Unless I genuinely
“see” the truth in a given philosophic system, I am fraudulent in
expounding it as if I do. Therefore, “this diversity in philosophic
systems is far from being an evasive plea.” Hegel’s appreciation of this
difficulty is acute. Allow me to quote at length.
It
has far more weight as a genuine serious ground of argument against the
zeal which Philosophy requires. It justifies its neglect and
demonstrates conclusively the powerlessness of the endeavor to attain to
philosophic know-ledge of the truth. When it is admitted that
Philosophy ought to be a real science, and one Philosophy must certainly
be the true, the question arises as to which it is, and when it can be
knowm. Each one asserts its genuineness, each even gives signs and
tokens by which the Truth can be discovered; sober reflective thought
must therefore hesitate to give, its judgement. . . .
The
whole of the history of Philosophy be-comes a battlefield covered with
the bones of the dead not merely formed of dead and lifeless
individuals, but of refuted and spiritually dead systems, since each has
killed and buried the other. (16, 17)
What
“solution” does Hegel propose for this difficulty he appears to grasp so
well? First, Hegel denies that one can remain satisfied with one’s
skepticism, or at least bewilderment in the face of philosophic
diversity, and that intellectual life, like physical life, will press on
to overcome its hunger for knowledge of the truth. (Presumably, a need
is dependent for its own existence upon the existence of the object of
need; hardly a compelling argument, though suggestive.) Secondly, the
common bond all these diverse instances share is their being
Philosophy. To regard diversity alone in treating a subject matter is
as erroneous in Philosophy as it is anywhere else. (18) If it is a
category mistake to ask “Where’s the fruit?” when looking through the
contents of a bowl of cherries, plums, and grapes, so it is if one asks,
“Where’s Philosophy?” when con-fronted with the writings of Edmund
Husserl, Alfred North Whitehead, and Martin Heidegger.
Of
course, experience with cherries, plums, and grapes helps to fill out
one’s understanding of the generic universal “fruit”; likewise, the
study of different philosophers fleshes out one’s notion of Philosophy.
To read but one philosopher’s work is to become acquainted with
Philosophy, although one’s knowledge of it will be as limited as
knowledge of fruit for one whose acquaintance with fruit is limited to
plums. (18-19) Thus, as we’ve noted earlier,
We
must make the fact conceivable, that the diversity and number of
philosophies not only does not prejudice Philosophy itself, that is to
say the possibility of Philosophy, but that such diversity is, and has
been, absolutely necessary to the existence of a science of Philosophy
that is essential to it. (19)
But
Hegel has, throughout his treatment of the diversity problem, committed
an error which, while not refuting his interpretation of the history of
philosophy, creates difficulties for accepting it. The error is simply
one of begging the question: Hegel has asked the open-minded philosopher
to accept his philosophy of Spirit in order to avoid the diversity
problem. In other words, the problem of how to choose from “such
manifold opinions, and philo-sophic systems so numerous” (15) disappears
once you’ve chosen Hegel’s system with its view of history.
Hegel asserts that the facts of history “are not a mere collection of
chance events, of expedi-tions of wandering knights, each going about
fighting, struggling purposelessly, leaving no results for all his
efforts.” Rather, “in the activity of thinking mind there is real
connection, and what there takes place is rational. It is with this
belief in the spirit of the world that we must proceed to history,
and in particular to the history of Philosophy.” (19; my stress)
Why
“must” we? The identification of Being with Spirit—which is what
Hegel’s deductive system amounts to—may help make everything else
intelligible, but it cannot ground itself; the “argument” for it is
necessarily pre-systematic: it is, as Hegel himself terms it, a
“belief.” The diversity problem must in some way be overcome if we are
to seriously pursue philosophy; yet, paradoxically, such a solution
itself always involves a philosophical position which, in its turn,
generates philosophical opposition and diversity—opposition which may,
for all we know, be right.
At
least Hegel was aware of the problem and “solved” it in good faith in
the context of elaborating his system. But if for any reason we reject
Hegel’s philosophy of Spirit—there’s no need to enumerate possible
reasons here—his solution to the diversity problem remains unsupported,
and his philosophy becomes merely one more instance of diversity. More
bothersome to me has been the willingness on the part of many
Anglo-American linguistic and positivistic thinkers to skirt the present
issue by adopting—in the name of philosophy, of course—a skepticism
toward everything philosophy has attempted to be, viz., an “objective
science of truth,” and engaging in philosophy for the worst of reasons.
For I agree with Hegel when he wrote that philosophy is not
justifiable as an “erudite investigation” from which one profits from
others’ opinions; nor as that which merely “stimulates the powers of
thought and . . . leads to many excellent reflections.” (12) Indeed, if
philosophy is justifiable only as something which gives those who pursue
it pleasure, then the presumed objective importance of each piece of
philosophizing is undercut. On the other hand, if philosophy is to be
more than merely personally satisfying, we are back in the muddle of
diverse claims to objective science. My only complaint against the
linguistic writers is that they have made a virtue of skeptical vice,
and they have labeled the products of this transvaluation “philosophy.”
If philosophy as an objective science of truth is a myth, or, if
already attained, unknowable as such for the reasons offered in this
paper, so be it. But let us not muddy an already complex issue by
including techniques and concerns external, if not also hostile, to the
possibility of such science under the rubric of “philosophy.”
Is a
pre-philosophic theory of philosophic diver-sity possible? Hegel’s
theory, for one, is not pre-philosophic; and the philosophy which
grounds his theory—even if I’m wrong in taking his identification of
Being and Spirit as pre-systematic—is at the very least controversial.
In his essay, “Hegel as an Historian of Philosophy,” Quentin Lauer
remarks that the “perennial problem . . . has been the univer-salizing
of a reason whose activity takes place in individuals, but whose
validity transcends the limits of individual reason.”8 I
believe it is a problem with the force of a paradox. Unless we assume
the possible universality of what we say, more particularly, unless I
assume that what I say in this paper is more than a personal
statement, why should we bother to expound and criticize? Yet if we can
never prove that this assumption is not on the order of myth—and the
existence of profound and manifold disagreement argues for its mythic
character—what is the assumption worth? We cannot, it seems, to do
without philosophy, and yet we can do pitifully little with it, not ever
agree on its definition and office. We turn to philosophy out of
dissatisfaction with “common reflections,” yet it is hard to say that
such notions are held in greater contempt than is the painstaking work
of a philosopher with whom we happen to fundamentally disagree.
I
happen to believe that philosophy’s office is to explain the world as a
whole, note merely to describe parts of it accurately or advise others
on how to talk right. I believe that efforts to so explain lead
logical-ly to a systematic ontology which is in principle capa-ble of
systematically relating all phenomena and ideas. I therefore find
myself in sympathy with the work of, among others, Plato, Hegel, and
Brand Blan-shard. But for all I know, the neo-positivist and
linguistic critiques of metaphysics may be essentially correct. I
believe Blanshard demolished the preten-sions of the Anglo-American
analytic tradition in his Reason and Analysis, but work in that
tradition has not ceased during the quarter-century since Blanshard’s
Carus lectures, upon which his book was based, were delivered. Is
Blanshard wrong or are the linguistic philosophers thick? I shrink from
choosing here. And I don’t believe I’m dragging innocents into my swamp
when I suggest that philosophers who are enamored of, say, Wittgenstein
or Austin, and who also have a sense of the diversity problem, can
reproduce for themselves the form of my dilemma with the allegiances and
criticisms reversed.
In
sum, I can tell you my beliefs, orientation, and sympathies, but
probably never convince you of the truth of any of my philosophical
positions. The more I consider possible and actual opposition to my way
of thinking, the more self-deceptive do I consider my “objective”
pretensions to be. I therefore must conclude that, until I’ve solved
the diversity problem, I also do philosophy for the worst of reasons: I
enjoy it, it stimulates my mind, and affords me many “excellent
reflections,” to recall Hegel’s derision of dilettantes such as myself.
I do everything but know the truth.
In
closing, I would suggest that we either face up to this problem and
solve it, or admit the skeptical conclusion that follows from our
failure to do so, viz., that no philosopher ever knows his philosophy to
express objective, universal truth. How close this is to Professor
Unger’s radically skeptical position that nobody ever knows
anything to be the case, I have not fully reflected upon.9
But if philosophy, despite its rational appearances, is a battlefield
of pre-philosophical “bents,” “posits,” or pre-systematic
identifications, how much more troubled are those intellectual
disciplines, which are just as wracked by internal feuding and whose
students are generally less concerned with epistemological rigor? If
philosophers cannot agree about epistemology, can, for example,
political scientists justify their methodology? If they really can,
they belong in the philosophy departments, and those who are presently
designated “philosophers” should take their courses. But I suspect that
this is not the case, and I suggest that the skepticism that threatens
philosophy threatens much of what is done in the social sciences and the
humanities.10 The longer we remain merely amused or annoyed
over the possibility of skepticism, the longer the logic of reasoned,
but unremitting, disagreement works behind our backs. In a world where
rational discourse is too often subordinated to ideological imperatives
and mocked by irrationalists as inconsequential when compared with the
presumed “real world” values of power, wealth, and physical
gratification, those who are concerned with the possibilities as well as
the limits of such discourse, and believe—for what that belief is
worth—in the integrity of reason to freedom, ought to seek an
explanation of our vast and skepticism-inducing disagreements. For if
disagreement is truly a “fact of life” and shatters even the vindication
of reason, then, even if we dogmatically entrench ourselves in our
particular positions to hide from the conse-quences, reason unavoidably
deceives us by its presumptions. Even to speak of “rational”
disagreement is such a context is presumptuous.
Notes
1
See, e. g., Peter Unger, Ignorance: The Case for Scepticism
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), the general treatment of which
the profession conforms, I contend, to the above-mentioned pattern.
2
Charles P. Bigger, Participation: A Platonic Inguiry (Baton
Rouge, La.: Louisiana University Press, 1968), p. 3.
3
John Oulton Wisdom, Philosophy and Its Place in Our Culture (New
York: Gordon & Breach, 1975), p. 3n.
4
Bigger, op. cit., p. 123.
5
G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of History, trans. J.
Sibree (New York: Dover, 1955); all parenthetical page references in
this paragraph only are to this edition.
6
G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans. E.
S. Haldane (New York: Humanities Press, 1963), I, p. 5, my stress; all
parenthetical page references through the rest of this paper are to this
edition.
7
Cf. Unger, op. cit., last chapter, “The Impossibility of Truth.”
8
This essay appears in J. J. O’Malley, et. al., eds., Hegel and
the History of Philosophy, Proceedings of the 1972 Hegel Society of
America Conference (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974). The quote is
from p. 46.
9
The
only hope I hold out against Unger’s skepticism is that since it is a
product of the linguistic philosophical tradition, it may suffer from
the defects of that tradition. Indeed, I’m hoping that Unger’s
skepticism is the reductio ad absurdum of that tradition, rather
than of natural language, as Unger would have it. But my hope, of
course is cognitively worthless.
10
Physics, which enables us to do so many things, seems less
subject to skeptical attack. Unger’s skepticism would deny even this.